Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

Similar documents
Lecture 8 Keynes s Response to the Contradictions

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Outline. The argument from so many arguments. Framework. Royall s case. Ted Poston

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

William Clifford and William James on sufficient evidence for belief

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

With prompting and support, identify the reasons an author gives to support points in a text.

Establishing premises

11 Beware of Syllogism: Statistical Reasoning and Conjecturing According to Peirce

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Grade 6 correlated to Illinois Learning Standards for Mathematics

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

A (Very) Brief Introduction to Epistemology Lecture 2. Palash Sarkar

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

occasions (2) occasions (5.5) occasions (10) occasions (15.5) occasions (22) occasions (28)

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

INDUCTIVE.LOGIC AND SCIENCE

HIGH CONFIRMATION AND INDUCTIVE VALIDITY

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

the negative reason existential fallacy

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Theory of Knowledge Series

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Part III SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY? David Tin Win α & Thandee Kywe β. Abstract

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Refutation by elimination JOHN TURRI

Natural Law Theory. See, e.g., arguments that have been offered against homosexuality, bestiality, genetic engineering, etc.

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

Elgin High, Church of Scotland. Survey of New Elgin residents & Elgin High School pupils

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

The Problem of Induction. Knowledge beyond experience?

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Bayesian Probability

Introduction to Philosophy

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

YFIA205 Basics of Research Methodology in Social Sciences Lecture 1. Science, Knowledge and Theory. Jyväskylä 3.11.

University of International Business and Economics International Summer Sessions. PHI 110: Introduction to Philosophy

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

The argument from so many arguments

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

LOGIC. Inductive Reasoning. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

MLLunsford, Spring Activity: Conditional Probability and The Law of Total Probability

As noted, a deductive argument is intended to provide logically conclusive support for its conclusion. We have certainty with deductive arguments in

PHIL / PSYC 351. Thinking and Reasoning

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

John Maynard KEYNES b. 5 June d. 21 April 1946

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Giving up Judgment Empiricism: The Bayesian Epistemology of Bertrand Russell and Grover Maxwell

Bayesian Probability

PURE THEORY OF LAW - Legal Validity - Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

1.2. What is said: propositions

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Mètode Science Studies Journal ISSN: Universitat de València España

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Reason and Argument. Richard Feldman Second Edition

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Explanationist Aid for the Theory of Inductive Logic

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

A Note on Straight-Thinking

GCE Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Unit G571: Philosophy of Religion. Advanced Subsidiary GCE. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Transcription:

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability Patrick Maher Scientific Thought II Spring 2010

John Maynard Keynes 1883: Born in Cambridge, England 1904: B.A. Cambridge University 1914 18: World War I 1919: The Economic Consequences of the Peace 1921: A Treatise on Probability 1936: The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money 1946: Died in Sussex, England

The meaning of probability (Chapter 1) Examples of inconclusive arguments (by me) Induction by simple enumeration: All observed A are B All A are B Method of hypothesis: If H then E E H What probability theory is about In Metaphysics, in Science, and in Conduct, most of the arguments, upon which we habitually base our rational beliefs, are admitted to be inconclusive to a greater or less degree. (3) The theory of probability deals with the degree to which arguments are conclusive.

Probability is a relation between propositions h (premises) a (conclusion) Let our premises consist of any set of propositions h, and let our conclusion consist of any set of propositions a, then, if a knowledge of h justifies a rational belief in a of degree α, we say that there is a probability-relation of degree α between a and h. (4) In my notation: p(a h) is the degree of belief in a that is rational given h. In ordinary speech we often say a conclusion is probable or improbable, e.g. It will probably rain tomorrow. What we mean is that it is probable given our evidence.

Objectivity Probability is relative to a body of knowledge, which is different for different people. To this extent, therefore, probability may be called subjective. But in the sense important to logic, probability is not subjective... A proposition is not probable because we think it so. When once the facts are given which determine our knowledge, what is probable or improbable in these circumstances has been fixed objectively, and is independent of our opinion. (4) When we argue that Darwin gives valid grounds for our accepting his theory of natural selection, we do not simply mean that we are psychologically inclined to agree with him... We believe that there is some real objective relation between Darwin s evidence and his conclusions, which is... just as real and objective, though of a different degree, as that which would exist if the argument were... demonstrative. (5)

Probability is part of logic (3) If logic investigates the general principles of valid thought, the study of arguments, to which it is rational to attach some weight, is as much a part of it as the study of those which are demonstrative.

Measurement of probabilities (Chapter 3) Keynes s view A probability is measurable if it has a numeric value. Keynes accepted that some probabilities are measurable. Example (from Laplace): The probability that the balls in urn C are black, given that two of urns A, B, and C have white balls and the other has black balls, is 1/3. Keynes claimed that many probabilities are not measurable, i.e., they don t have a numeric value.

An unmeasurable probability (29) We are out for a walk what is the probability that we shall reach home alive? Has this always a numerical measure? If a thunderstorm bursts upon us, the probability is less than it was before; but is it changed by some definite numerical amount?

Statistics may be inapplicable (29) 1 There might, of course, be data which would make these probabilities numerically comparable; it might be argued that a knowledge of the statistics of death by lightning would make such a comparison possible. But if such information is not included within the knowledge to which the probability is referred, this fact is not relevant to the probability actually in question. 2 In some cases, moreover, where general statistics are available, the numerical probability which might be derived from them is inapplicable because of the presence of additional knowledge with regard to the particular case. My example: Statistics can tell you what proportion of people of your age, gender, etc., live to age 70. But you also have other relevant information about yourself, e.g., your health and your ancestors longevity. So your probability of living to 70 won t equal the statistical proportion who do.

Non-comparable probabilities The probability of getting home alive from a walk with a thunderstorm is less than without a thunderstorm. Keynes says these probabilities are comparable, even though they don t have numeric values. Keynes claimed that in other cases the probabilities aren t even comparable, i.e., there is no fact as to which is larger than the other. My elaboration of an example of Keynes (29 30): H: All crows are black. E 1 : 1000 crows in Illinois were examined and all were black. E 2 : 250 crows in Illinois and 250 in California were examined and all were black. E 1 contains more observations but E 2 is more varied. Keynes would say p(h E 1 ) and p(h E 2 ) aren t comparable.

Questions 1 According to Keynes: (a) What does it mean to say that the probability of a given h is α? (b) In what sense is it true that probability is subjective? In what sense is this not true? 2 Does Keynes think probability theory is part of logic? What is his reason? 3 Give an example of probabilities that Keynes would say are comparable but not measurable. 4 Give two reasons why, according to Keynes, the probability that you will live to be 70 years old cannot be measured by collecting statistical data. 5 Give an example of probabilities that Keynes would say are not comparable.

Reference John Maynard Keynes. A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan, 1921. On Google books. Numbers in parentheses are page numbers of this book.