How Can Act 5 Forget Lear and Cordelia

Similar documents
King Lear Sample answer

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ideas are often developed through the patterns of images Shakespeare creates. Some of the images and themes remain perplexing.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Professor Colin Gardner. This article is based on a talk presented by to a school audience.

Themes in King Lear. Motifs (Recurring elements and patterns of imagery in King Lear which support the play's themes)

Out of tragedy comes self knowledge. Do you find this to be true in King Lear and Oedipus the King?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

King Lear. William Shakespeare. Three Watson Irvine, CA Website:

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

King Lear Sample answer

4.a) What did Lear ask his three daughters? A. When King Lear decided to divide his kingdom among his daughters; he called them in

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Understanding King Lear Theme Disguise and Deception

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

The Problem with Forgiveness (or the Lack Thereof) and Seven Reasons to Consider It

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

The Meaning of Judgment. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

(Paper related to my lecture at during the Conference on Culture and Transcendence at the Free University, Amsterdam)

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Aboutness and Justification

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

Oxford Scholarship Online

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

KANT ON THE BEGINNINGS OF HUMAN HISTORY - CONJECTURES BY A SOCIOLOGIST by Richard Swedberg German Studies Colloquium on Immanuel Kant, Conjectures on

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

COMMENTS ON SIMON CRITCHLEY S Infinitely Demanding

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

The Paradox of the Question

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

Why Have You Forsaken Me?

36 Thinking Errors. 36 Thinking Errors summarized from Criminal Personalities - Samenow and Yochleson 11/18/2017

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

**************************************

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

AS ENGLISH LITERATURE B

Transcription:

How Can Act 5 Forget Lear and Cordelia Every time I read King Lear I am startled by the moment when the characters recognize they have forgotten Lear and Cordelia: Kent. I am come to bid my King and master aye good night; Is he not here. Alb. Great thing of us forgot! Speak Edmund, where s the king? and where s Cordelia? Seest thou this object Kent? [The bodies of Goneril and Regan are brought in.. Kent. Alack! Why thus? Edm. Yet Edmund was belov d: The one the other poisoned for my sake, And after slew herself. (5.3.232-40) The Arden edition suggests that this forgetting should not be surprising because there is no reason why Albany should suspect that Lear and Cordelia were in danger; and he has plenty to occupy his mind (p. 200). But this seems almost as serious a myopic statement as the play s forgetting King Lear and Cordelia. If we are concerned only with the action of the play this footnote might be right. But why then would the play call attention to the forgetting? Shakespeare could have been lazy and just decided to get back to Lear in the easiest available way. But he also could have been the typical Shakespeare of the tragedies and had something surprising and powerful in mind in insisting on the distance between the practical world of struggle for the other characters and the kind of space that Lear and Cordelia create for one another. Once we attend to that possibility we are likely also to notice that the forgetting does not end with Albany s recognition. The play insists on the contrasts involved by immediately switching attention again. Albany asks Kent to see this object, the bodies of Goneril and Regan. It is only when the play turns to the dying Edmund s intention to do some good (242) that it gets around to recognizing something must be done for the prisoned pair. And Edmund by this point in the play is in many ways no longer part of the action. He shares more with Lear and Cordelia than with Edgar and Albany. The basic critical challenge posed by the end of King Lear is probably the need to characterize the kind of world Lear and Cordelia come to inhabit. We know that this space is composed by the power of their love for one another. But how are we to judge the relevance of that love for those who must obey the weight of this sad time? Is it a figure of transcendental grace, or does it force Lear to self-delusion in order to maintain that sense of difference after Cordelia is dead? I want to propose a third possibility that

may occur only to a modernist, and that requires a mode of abstraction that does not entirely satisfy me. Yet it does explain the possible philosophical energies at work in this conclusion at work primarily in the negatives and the contrasting imperatives. If we ask what links all the villains in the play, clearly the answer is that they all commit themselves to various versions of Edmund s faith in something like raw nature. And the storm plays its role in reinforcing this texture of correspondences. The crucial step here is to recognize that Edmund s naturalist metaphysics is of a piece with the Machiavellian ethics that he brings out as the yet unrealized potential of Goneril and Regan. Naturalism deals with desires and ambitions as also pure facts that are caught up in wills to power and resist any moral constraints, which in nature seems mere weakness and cowardice. So far nothing I have said is news for Renaissance scholars. And it is not at all incompatible with a Christian reading of the play. But the case gets more complicated when we have to place the good but ineffectual characters like Kent, and Gloucester, and even Edgar. They are not Machiavellian. But they have no power in a world that encourages and reward Machiavellian behavior. And they have no alternative world on which to look for power: Gloucester s despair and Edgar s sheer dogged coping are logical responses to their situation. Christian explanations can handle this, but with some strain since they seem condemned to the order of nature rather than choosing it. There seems no redemption for them. Not so Lear and Cordelia who have learned to occupy a different world, where Edmund s death is plausibly just a trifle (5.3.294). That world is defined largely by the great speech when they must go off to prison. The focus there is not on eternal salvation but on the particular state of two persons who now have suffered enough for Lear simply to offer a repeated series of negations of Cordelia s depressed acceptance of the need to see again Goneril and Regan: No, no, no, no! Come, let s away to prison; We two alone will sing like birds I the cage; When thou doth ask me blessing, I ll kneel down, And ask of thee forgiveness: so we ll live, And pray, and sing, and tell old tales, and laugh At gilded butterflies, and hear poor rogues (5.3. 8-13) The negatives are motivated primarily by the space Lear s reunion with Cordelia opens for his imagination. That space is not devotional. Rather it is experienced as the permission to explore a logic of parataxis radically opposed to the logic of imposed contradiction facing the other characters. Lear sees himself and Cordelia entering a world where possibility flows into adjacent possibility for pleasure and fulfillment. Something about the world they share warrants an attitude very different from the versions of scarcity economics that his daughters impose on Lear and society imposes on the daughters to compete to be the one wife of Edmund. This new world of

freedoms is a place where one can, as Cordelia does, utter without paradox the claim that finally she is completely recognized by her father, And so I am, I am (4.7. 70). But what can this assertion of identity entail since she has so little time to live. This is one basic question that demands a response to Lear s final speech. What can he see that he demands we also observe: And my poor fool is hanged! No, no, no life! Why should a dog, a horse, a rat, have life, And thou no breath at all? Thou will come no more, Never, never, never, never, never! Pray you undo this button: thank you, Sir. Do you see this? Look on her, look, her lips, Look there, look there! (5.5.304-09) Christian salvation provides one such story. But I think that model would have been too easy for Shakespeare. It is not an accident that King Lear is set in a world where the gods have no bonds to humans; in that world the secular would be the best the characters could get. Everything else might be demonic. So we need to be more abstract, and possibly thereby more concrete. What kind of life can Cordelia have still after all these negations? I propose that she has the kind of life that can live at least in memory as something simply different from the order of nature that defines life and death for the other characters. The relation between father and daughter exemplifies something not subject to nature, even if it also may not secure transcendental life. So rather than turn to Christian thinking I want to invoke almost its opposite the tradition of Positivist thinking that tried to stabilize what we could know about nature when we completely expunge it of all transcendental elements. But I want to view these Positivist demands under the distinct project of Wittgenstein s Tractatus Logicus Philosophicus that paid careful attention to what becomes of our values when we see they have no place in nature. Wittgenstein s is by far the most compelling version of the Positivist spirit for me because his by far the most appreciative of what cannot be thought or found in the world where empiricist values prevail. Machiavellian principles are not quite the same as Positivist ones, but given Edmund s grounding them in a theory of nature, they are more consistent with empiricism than one might think. And by using Wittgenstein we can recast Manichaen theology into the absolute conflict of a domain of fact ineluctably divided from a domain of value. This enables us to take Lear s sense of a space in which Cordelia still lives as not just an escapist failure of character showing that he has learned nothing from his adventures except perhaps better manners to his servants. I need from the Tractatus only two statements. Then I can return to one more feature of the play that these quotations establish as central to its power. First there is Wittgenstein s most general statement about the incompatibility with values in the same

way that a language capable of picturing the world is incompatible with one that expresses a personal stance: 6.41 The sense of the world must lie outside the world. In the world everything is as it is, and everything happens as it does happen: in it no value exists and if it did it would have no value. If there is any value that does have value, it must lie outside the whole sphere of what happens and is the case. For all that happens and is the case is accidental. What makes it non-accidental cannot lie within the world, since if it did it would itself be accidental. It would lie outside the world. (Tractatus, p. 145) I am not arguing that Edmund believed anything like this formulation. The case is more interesting than that. Positivism offers a strange reversal of Christianity with much the same force. In the Christian world, value is stable, fixed by the incarnate Word, while the truth of the senses are unstable and unreliable. In basing his life on the senses Edmund denies the stability of value. For Wittgentstein the stable world is oddly the world of accidents because that is the world of natural law. Logic deals with accidents because there is no reason facts are as they are: logic displays what is given not what is justified by purposes. But even though there are opposed pictures of what is stable, these traditions share an absolute divide between naturalism and the domain of values. From the perspective I am developing Edmund causes such trouble because he wants to treat values as if they were merely facts, as if they were accident subject to human will rather than goals which promise meaning for that will. Because Edmund comes to dominate the world of facts, and because the human economy in the play is shaped by the horrors of valueless existence, there is considerable pressure on the audience to treat as sentimentality any claim about distinctive values established by or for the play gorgeous and noble sentimentality but sentimentality nonetheless. Hence the critical history of criticizing Cordelia for her unwavering goodness and the corresponding sense of Lear as figure of ultimate pathos. There is no escaping history and the perspectives it establishes. But that does not mean the historic-empirical perspective is always the only one we can take. If we stand only within history we can only ironize Shakespeare s obvious heroizing of Lear at the end from his caring behavior to others to his heroic killing of the man who killed Cordelia, to the sentiments that flow from his identifying Cordelia as his daughter despite his madness (4.7.68-69)? But if we are driven to ask how his heroism can be taken seriously as something other than sentimentality, we can also focus on how they in part shift the drama onto a plane where sheer value seems to work out its own imperatives. One can see the relationship between Lear and Cordelia as their learning through extreme suffering that the sense of the world must lie outside the world. The man who could imagine We two alone will sing like the birds i th cage is

capable of seeing something at the margin of the world, especially when he repeats his imperatives to Look at the end of the play. We cannot be sure he sees anything real or even sees anything beyond his need to have something to see. But Look is an interesting imperative in part because it does not necessarily connect to a proposition that will bind itself to the world of fact. Looking can be content with appearance, or content with a world in which something might be discovered or pursued even though it yields no clear objective manifestation. Look asks us to observe Cordelia not just as this dead body but as this being given matter and spirit by the play. So while we cannot be sure Lear s sees anything at all, we can wonder what the cost is of our determining that we must reproduce the object in order to believe in the importance of the seeing. The play forces a choice, and suggests that the best answer is to maintain both poles of the choice. The choice is whether to accept the empirical stance in which we only responding to Look if the observer provides proof, or to accept the possibility that there is a scene of seeing subject to other conditions of response. We have to see the logic arguing for the first option. But we risk impoverishing ourselves if we do not also sympathize with Lear s call at the end of the play for keeping some principle of value alive because Cordelia still responds to it, or responds to what love makes it possible to see. Lear s repeated imperatives suggest that there is something significant just in the spectacle that Cordelia becomes in the end, framed by her love and fidelity and honored by his capacity to enter into the space that his love and fidelity have the strength to compose. This is where my second borrowing from Wittgenstein becomes appropriate: There are, indeed things that cannot be put into words. They make themselves manifest (6.522). i This inaugurates an extended mediation throughout Wittgenstein s career on what has to be displayed rather than described. Ultimately the fullest appeal a person can make is not to ethical principle but to what confession displays that cannot be grasped by reason s universals: The criteria for the truth of the confession that I thought such and such are not the criteria for a true description of a process. And the importance of the true confession does not reside in its being a correct and certain report of a process. It resides rather in the special consequences which can be drawn from a confession whose truth is guaranteed by the special criteria of truthfulness. ii ( PI p. 222.) The domain of human value here cannot be encompassed within a true description of a process because the language of value is not something we find or argue for. It is something we display and hope that an audience will see into the display what reason cannot establish. Lear offers no confession. But he does make a total unguarded commitment to his speaking at the end that serves very much the same purposes. Suppose then that Lear s repeated imperative to Look leads beyond the dramatic situation to Shakespeare s reflection on the possibility that the role of spectacle might recuperate

for this play something fundamental to drama that was at risk of being lost as playwrights tried to make its home in Edmund s world. There have been countless studies of the motif of seeing and blindness within this play. But how many of these worry about the play itself as something to be seen as different from what realism dictates as our mode of viewing. Minimally the spectacles of Lear denying Cordelia in public and then being humiliated by his begging and raging on the heath in a kind of recompense bring the play into a domain of intense feelings pulling at the ontology that calls for understanding in realistic terms. In fact by this understanding Goneril and Regan are largely right about their father in his dotage. And by this kind of understanding Gloucester almost deserves his punishment for how he treats Edmund. It is spectacle that dignifies suffering and makes sympathy overrule what judgment might be tempted to conclude. And it is ultimately spectacle that makes Lear s display of seeing something in Cordelia sufficiently believable that we look for a world in which that might be possible. That world must lie outside the whole sphere of what happens and is the case, but it may be no less central for our sense of being human. ii i Wittgenstein concludes this statement with one more sentence: They are what is mystical. I drop it from my argument because it is easy to mistake what Wittgenstein means by the mystical. He does not mean anything transcendental. His view is summarized by a statement a page back, Feeling the world as a limited whole it is this that is mystical (6.45). Ultimately what is mystical is the fact that the world can fit logical form that gives shape to propositions. And because we would have to use logic to describe logic, there is no way to get outside of logic. The force of logic can only be displayed. Perhaps that is also true of theater at its most intense and demanding. The passion behind this formulation emerges in Wittgenstein s private writing: The Christian Faith as I see it is a man s refuge in this ultimate torment. Anyone in such torment who has the gift of opening his heart, rather than contracting it, accepts the means of salvation in his heart. Someone who in this way penitently opens his heart to God in confession lays it open for other men too. In doing this he loses the dignity that goes with his personal prestige and becomes like a child. A man can bare himself before others only out of a particular kind of love. A love which acknowledges as it were, that we are all wicked children. We could also say: Hate between men comes from our cutting ourselves off from each other. CV, 46