Critical Scientific Realism

Similar documents
Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

ONE CANNOT BE JUST A LITTLE BIT REALIST: PUTNAM AND VAN FRAASSEN*

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

KITCHER S MODEST REALISM: THE RECONCEPTUALIZATION OF SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Howard Sankey Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Melbourne

Varieties of Apriority

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

What the History of Science Cannot Teach Us Ioannis Votsis University of Bristol

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

REALISM/ANTI-REALISM

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

Relativism. We re both right.

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Assertion and Inference

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Scientific realism and anti-realism

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Constructing the World

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

IS TRUTH ABSOLUTE OR RELATIVE? Ilkka Niiniluoto University of Helsinki Philosophy & Logic 2013, Kyiv, May 25, 2013

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014):

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Brandom s five-step program for modal health

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp , 2008.

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Epistemology Naturalized

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Postmodal Metaphysics

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Philosophy Courses-1

145 Philosophy of Science

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Philosophy Courses-1

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Transcription:

Book Reviews 1 Critical Scientific Realism, by Ilkka Niiniluoto. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. xi + 341. H/b 40.00. Right from the outset, Critical Scientific Realism distinguishes the critical realists, who subscribe to fallibilism, from the naïve realists, who believe that certified truth is easily accessible (p. 13). I am not aware of any such naïve realists, nor does Niiniluoto name any names. Of course, one might say that there could be such a philosophical position, even if no-one actually held it. But the issue isn t merely academic. The fallibilist tradition in epistemology, though independent of realism as an ontological thesis, has always been its bedfellow. Realists cannot seriously afford to be naïve since insofar as they engage in epistemic matters, they have to face squarely the sceptical injunction that certainty in knowledge is not possible, especially when it comes to matters unobservable or inaccessible. Hence, they have to base their epistemic optimism on epistemic theories which make knowledge possible while leaving certainty aside. In his significant book, Niiniluoto does discuss the prospects of fallibilism in epistemology (pp. 79 85) but, I think, does not give the attention they deserve to some epistemic theories (for example, naturalism, pp.15 8) which aim to show how fallibilism can be grounded. Nor does he engage in a defence of his own theses against objections. Although he repudiates the foundationalist first philosophy (p. 17), he also wants to keep a place for normative judgements. He then dismisses naturalism too on the basis that it reduces the normative to the descriptive. But naturalism and normativity do mix (as many philosophers, including Quine, have pointed out). Niiniluoto downplays this and pledges a mutual dialogue between philosophy of science and the special sciences (p. 18). To be sure, in his discussion of Laudan s Normative Naturalism (pp. 170 4), he does accept that means-end norms (aka instrumental rationality) can be naturalized. And although he is quite right to point out (p. 174) that a truth-linked axiology should somehow be constitutive of science, he does not discuss in any detail the issue of how constitutive rules (p. 172) are grounded. I take it that there has lately been a lot of interesting work on how these rules and a concomitant substantive notion of normativity can be analysed in terms of supervenience, so that they retain their normative force without being taken to be sui generis. A relevant discussion would do better justice to naturalism and would also help ground Niiniluoto's truth-linked axiology. When it comes to his own positive views in chapter four, he eloquently argues that realism in epistemology should employ the fallibilist conceptions of probable, conjectural and truthlike knowledge (p. 85). These conceptions are distinct and different, as Niiniluoto himself makes clear. However, one of them ( conjectural knowledge, which Niiniluoto discusses briefly on pp. 83 4) seems to be a non-starter. For a proposition is either conjectured or known, but not both. (Popperians might think the opposite, but as D. C. Stove Popper and After: Four Modern Irrationalists, Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1982 nicely argued, they are simply wrong). Let s focus our attention on truthlike knowl-

2 Book Reviews edge. Ordinary theories of knowledge (both internalist and externalist; fallibilist and infallibilist) make knowledge a species of true belief. Niiniluoto s brand of fallibilism makes knowledge a species of truthlike belief (p. 84). Truthlike beliefs may be true beliefs (since, on Niiniluoto s view (p. 73) the most truthlike theory is the complete truth). But they are, typically, false beliefs. Hence, on Niiniluoto s view, knowledge does not imply true belief. In fact, in most typical cases of truthlike knowledge, knowledge would end up being a species of false belief. This sounds odd and, to say the least, requires some good defence. But even if it is granted that all we have are false beliefs (which is doubtful), what conditions should be met in order to say that some of our false beliefs count as knowledge whereas others do not? Searching for a sufficiently wide interval estimate which covers the truth value with high degree of certainty (p. 84) leaves too much up in the air: our knowledge will vary with the width of the interval and with the degree of certainty with which the truth value is said to be in it. Besides, if, like Niiniluoto, we take as a third (justification) condition on a truthlike (that is, false) belief h to count as knowledge that X has a reason to claim that h is more truthlike than its rival on available evidence (p. 84), we seem to end up with problems. For the knowledge of X is relativized to X s state of information. If fresh evidence shows that there is a rival (incompatible) h' which is more truthlike than h and if X has now reason to claim that h' is more truthlike than h on the fresh evidence, can we say that X then knew that h and that he now knows that (incompatible) h'? Hardly. Standard theories of knowledge (both fallibilist and infallibilist) avoid the problems that Niiniluoto faces by making knowledge a species of true belief. But Niiniluoto s association of knowledge with false belief leaves him in need of more work in order to get his critical epistemological realism off the ground. Early on (p. viii), Niiniluoto draws our attention to a major conclusion of his book: different conceptual frameworks (pace Donald Davidson) may carve up the mind-independent world (pace Richard Rorty) in different ways into individuals, kinds, and facts. There is no a priori privileged or a posteriori ideal Peirceish framework for describing the world (pace Sellars); truth is relative to the conceptualization of reality. He adds that all this does not make truth an epistemic notion. Rather, this conclusion gives grounds for a realism worth fighting for. All this would give pause to some realists. But let s not dwell on it. For later on enters Kant. Where Critical Realism differs from Kant, we are told, is in its claim that an epistemological subject is directly, without a veil, in contact with reality (p. 91). Hence, the Critical Realist affirms both the knowability of the things-in-themselves and their existence (cf. ibid.). But there is a veil after all. For even if we exorcize (as we should) sense-data and the like, we are still left, on Niiniluoto s account, with our conceptual frameworks, each of which provides us with a perspective on objective reality (p. 91). Perspectives may be direct (as when I see a house from an angle), but perspectives don t show an object as it is. And incompatible perspectives (see conceptual schemes) may suggest that different objects

Book Reviews 3 might be present (or no object at all). These perspectival veils might be inevitable in our give-and-take with the world, but for a realist there must be a fact of the matter as to which is the correct one especially when incompatible perspectives are in play: is there phlogiston or oxygen in the air we breathe? Which leaves Niiniluoto with a dilemma. Either he has to accept that there is a fact of the matter as to how the things-in-themselves really are or there is no fact of the matter. If the latter, why posit them in the first place? If the former, then there must be some conceptual framework (or perspective) which, at least in principle, resonates with the way things are. (This might well be Bernard Williams s absolute conception of the world.) Niiniluoto tries to move between the horns of this dilemma by noting (a) that Kant unwarrantedly jumped from the inexhaustibility of things-in-themselves (that is, that they cannot be completely known (p. 93)) to their inaccessibility ; and (b) that a critical realist acknowledges dirty (partial, incomplete, inexact, conceptually relative etc. but truthlike) forms of knowledge. He sounds right about Kant, but still there seems to be a tension in his views. Even if there can be dirty knowledge (and note, a propos, that inexact etc. knowledge is quite different from conceptually relative knowledge), to say that this knowledge is knowledge of an objective reality is not enough to posit such an objective reality (the things-in-themselves). Nor is it enough to note, after the positing, that this reality is inexhaustible. (Who knows that?) Nor is it enough to adopt a correspondence theory of truth since this can well be scheme-relative. You also need to show that what you say of this reality is correct (or sufficiently correct, or truthlike). But this last move presupposes that not all perspectives (or conceptual schemes) are equally good, and that, ultimately, what judges which is the correct, or the most correct, one is the objective reality and its own inherent structure. In other words, you need to prioritize some conceptual scheme, especially if you are faced with incompatible ones. Hence, I feel that Niiniluoto pays only lip service to conceptualscheme pluralism. (Compare: ( ) all structures W L [that is, world versions, conceptual schemes] are fragments of the same WORLD and therefore cannot be incompatible with each other. p. 224) Right after all this, he endorses two well-known arguments in favour of the possibility of objective knowledge of reality: (a) that there is causal contact and interaction with this reality; and (b) that convergence-of-opinion in the description of this reality is a reliable sign of the correctness of this description (cf. pp. 93 4). Both of these point to ways in which judgements about priorities among conceptual schemes can be grounded. Niiniluoto returns to these issues when he discusses Putnam s Internal Realism in chapter seven. Here he makes clear that he wants to defend a position which is centred around the correspondence theory of truth (impeccably defended in chapter three) but also endorses conceptual pluralism ( There is more than one true description of the world, pp. 211 and 218) and minimal ontological realism (p. 218). It is a serious, and I think still

4 Book Reviews open, philosophical issue whether realism implies that there is exactly one true and complete description of the way the world is, as Putnam has put it. What is of interest here is how Niiniluoto tries to avoid this commitment. Already in chapter one, he defended the view that physical objects are bundles of tropes, where the tropes have natural relations of similarity (p. 30). Properties (for example, the property of being red), on his account, are human-made classes of similar tropes, where the class is created by abstraction. He calls this view tropic realism. One may wonder what these natural relations of similarity are and what the method of abstraction involved in the making of properties is. But let s leave aside some natural worries about the viability of this metaphysical picture. Niiniluoto puts this picture to work in chapter seven. If, he says, the furniture of the world is tropes ( property-individuals ), and if the properties are human constructions out of this material, then given that the predicates of the language refer to properties, there can be many ways to construct these properties and hence many different languages (conceptual schemes) to structure the world (cf. pp. 214 5). So, on tropic realism there is just not one true description of the world. Still, this is questionable. There may be more than one ways to group together, for instance, red-tropes and orange-tropes based on their similarity. But (a) it is objective ( natural, Niiniluoto says) similarities that guide this constructions; and (b) it is objective dissimilarities (for example, between brown-tropes and electron-tropes) that constrain this construction. So, even if we don t get one uniquely correct description of the world, if the chosen descriptions are constrained by objective similarities and differences in the world, we can still dispense with many of them as wrong. And in any case, whether or not there can be such a uniquely correct description will depend on how loosely or tightly we understand the required similarity relations. Niiniluoto s metaphysical picture is completed by bringing in (again) the Kantian things-inthemselves. He calls them UFOs (p. 221). (Given his overall ontological landscape, UFOs should be particularized tropes. But Niiniluoto (p. 221) takes objects-before-their-identification, for example, dinosaurs, to be UFOs.) He then takes our cognitive give-and-take with UFOs to produce IFOs (Identified Flying Objects), viz. UFOs under a description, which exist only relative to a conceptual scheme (p. 221). As such (that is, human-made constructions), IFOs inhabit the Popperian World 3 (p. 222). This is minimal ontological realism indeed! But all is not lost, since Niiniluoto assures us that the existence and the properties of IFOs depend on the reality, and knowledge about IFOs gives truthlike information about UFOs (p. 233). How exactly this is done might need some more work to be substantiated. A reason perhaps for the book's brisk treatment of many important issues is its breadth. Critical Scientific Realism is impressively wide-ranging. Apart from the metaphysics, semantic and epistemology of realism, it also discusses the debate between realists and instrumentalists as well as particular instances of this debate in quantum mechanics, economics and other areas

Book Reviews 5 (Ch. 5), the role of truth in the scientific realism debate, the argument from the underdetermination of theories by evidence and the explanations of the success of science (Ch. 6), the different varieties of relativism, including moral relativism and feminist philosophy (Ch. 8), social constructivism (Ch. 9) and the role of science in a modern democracy (Ch. 10). Being a master technician, Niiniluoto is at his best in formalizing philosophical notions, such as truthlikeness, approximate truth, success, idealization, etc. His formulation and discussion of a precise theory reference for theoretical terms (pp. 120 32 and 189 92) is also a step forward in the relevant debate. Yet one might have liked to see a more detailed discussion of constructive empiricism and of arguments such as the pessimistic induction although Niiniluoto and the underdetermination of theories by evidence. Be that as it may, Critical Scientific Realism is a very rich book. I have been mostly critical in my comments partly because there is so much I agree with in this book. In fact, I think that it is admirable that Niiniluoto tries to deal with the metaphysics of realism, an area that has been relatively neglected. Critical Scientific Realism is an important contribution to the realism debate and will be very useful to all philosophers working in this area. Department of Philosophy and History of Science University of Athens 37 John Kennedy Street 16121 Athens Greece STATHIS PSILLOS