QUERIES: to be answered by AUTHOR

Similar documents
Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

Leibniz and His Correspondents

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Philosophy 3020: Modern Philosophy. UNC Charlotte, Spring Section 001, M/W 11:00am-12:15pm, Winningham 101

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Phil 3121: Modern Philosophy Fall 2016 T, Th 3:40 5:20 pm

Review of Riccardo Saccenti, Debating Medieval Natural Law: A Survey, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, pages.

RADICAL ENLIGHTENMENT

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Help! Muslims Everywhere Ton van den Beld 1

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Philosophizing about Africa in Berlin

Instructor Information Larry M. Jorgensen Office: Ladd Hall, room Office Hours: Mon-Thu, 1-2 p.m.

Timothy Peace (2015), European Social Movements and Muslim Activism. Another World but with Whom?, Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillian, pp

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Wittgenstein. The World is all that is the case. http// Philosophy Insights. Mark Jago. General Editor: Mark Addis

d) The (first) debate about Pantheism

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

131 seventeenth-century news

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Introduction. efraim podoksik

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

Spinoza s Tractatus Theologico Politicus Fall 2018, University of Haifa, Instructor: Dr. Daniel Schneider

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Environmental Ethics in Buddhism: A Virtues Approach

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Volume 25, Number 2, Winter 2011 Marx or Spinoza

Lend me your eyes; I can change what you see! ~~Mumford & Sons

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Spinoza and German Idealism

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Naturalism and is Opponents

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

Did Leibniz Really Reject the Spinozistic Monism in 1677?

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

The Age of Enlightenment

The British Empiricism

Must We Choose between Real Nietzsche and Good Philosophy? A Streitschrift Tom Stern, University College London

Schleiermacher on Christ and Religion by H. Richard Niebuhr (S.C.M.)

Skepticism and Toleration in Early Modern Philosophy. Instructor: Todd Ryan Office: McCook 322 Office Phone:

Arabic sciences between theory of knowledge and history, Review

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Spinoza on the Principles of Natural Things. Alison Peterman, University of Rochester

This authoritative translation by John Cottingham of the Meditations is taken from the much acclaimed three-volume Cambridge. Descartes: Meditations

WEEK 1: CARTESIAN SCEPTICISM AND THE COGITO

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement


A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. VOL.5. HOBBES TO HUME. By FREDERICK. COPLESTON

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Spinoza and Spinozism. By STUART HAMPSHIRE. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.

An Attempt to Reconcile Three Theories of the Origin of Finite Things in De Summa Rerum

BCC Papers 5/2, May

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

book review Out of Time The Limits of Secular Critique MACQUARIE UNIVERSITY

1/8. Leibniz on Force

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Title Interpretation in the English-Speak.

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

ntroduction to Socialist Humanism: An International Symposium by Eri...

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Philosophy Courses-1

Realism and anti-realism. University of London Philosophy B.A. Intercollegiate Lectures Logic and Metaphysics José Zalabardo Autumn 2009

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Leibnizian Meditations on Monism, Force, and Substance, in relation to Descartes, Spinoza and Malebranche

Spinoza as a Philosopher of Education. Cetin Balanuye, Akdeniz University, Turkey

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study


2003 Marc Helfer. Leibniz s Evil. by Marc Helfer

Spinoza, A Spinoza Reader, ed. and trans. E. Curley (Princeton University Press).

THE ROOTS OF RELIGIOUS TOLERATION HIST 317N, JS 311, RS 306, EUS 306 MWF 2:00-3:00 CBA 4.348

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

REVIEW THE MORALS OF HISTORIOGRAPHY

PHI 516 SEMINAR: LEIBNIZ FALL This seminar will be focused on understanding the thought of G.W. Leibniz in historical context.

Personality and Soul: A Theory of Selfhood

Transcription:

Manuscript Information British Journal for the History of Philosophy Journal Acronym Volume and issue Author name Manuscript No. (if applicable) RBJH _A_478506 Typeset by KnowledgeWorks Global Ltd. for QUERIES: to be answered by AUTHOR Dear Author Please address all the numbered queries on this page which are clearly identified on the proof for your convenience. Thank you for your cooperation QUERY NO. QUERY DETAILS No Author Queries.

devia 17/4/10 14:33 RBJH_A_478506 (XML) British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18(3) 2010: 521 524 BOOK REVIEW 5 Mogens Lærke: Leibniz lecteur de Spinoza. La gene se d une opposition complexe. Paris: Honore Champion, 2008, pp. 1092. e165.00 (hb.). ISBN 978-2-7453-1698-1 Spinoza was a great philosopher and a highly original metaphysician. He was also a radical and unsettling thinker whose views were perceived as scandalous, heretical and dangerous. Spinoza was seen as a threat, especially to established religion and its authority in society. Because he was such a highly influential and controversial figure, the way he was perceived by his contemporaries is of great interest. One of the most remarkable minds in Europe at the time, and one who had a particularly curious combination of fascination and repugnance to Spinoza s views, was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Leibniz, who was one the most important contributors to the formation of modern science was also a firm conservative, a man fully committed to the reconciliation of the new science and the discoveries of human reason with the accepted doctrines of Christianity and established traditions. Thus, while Spinoza advocated philosophy and its geometrical method as the only norm of truth, Leibniz sought to reconcile philosophy with revealed religion and believed that their results must be consistent. In fact, much of Leibniz enormous intellectual energies were devoted precisely to this reconciliatory project. While being himself a great innovator in the sciences and in philosophy, Leibniz assumed the role of a traditional theologian, showing how reason can be made consistent with faith. It is this role of the theologians that Spinoza s philosophy despises the most, as it attempts to provide rational justification to human superstition and prejudice. If only for this reason, one would expect Leibniz to be in clear and vehement opposition to Spinoza. Indeed, such an opposition can be found in Leibniz s reactions to Spinoza; but, as Mogens Lærke s monumental study demonstrates, this opposition is far more complex and nuanced than one would expect or that has been recognized thus far. The task Lærke sets himself is to study the genealogy of Leibniz s opposition to Spinoza in full detail, examining the repercussions of his various encounters with Spinoza his texts, letters and acquaintances and turning every stone in search of evidence that can throw any light on this complex story of encounters. In particular, Lærke attempts to avoid any of the prejudices or ideological bents that have contaminated the study of this relationship in the past. Lærke s study excels in executing this task to the highest degree. There is, indeed, hardly any stone that remains unturned through the 1,092 pages of 10 15 20 25 30 35 40 45 British Journal for the History of Philosophy ISSN 0960-8788 print/issn 1469-3526 online http://www.informaworld.com DOI: 10.1080/09608781003779842

522 BOOK REVIEW 50 55 60 65 70 75 80 85 90 this careful and comprehensive study. There is also no succumbing to a grand thesis or to a facile conceptualization of these encounters. In the first part of the study, Leibniz s opposition to Spinoza is nuanced by exposing different attitudes towards the theological-political aspect of Spinoza s work when he read and reread the Tractatus-theologico-politicus (TTP) in 1670 1 and again in late 1675. This includes attempts to reconstruct Leibniz s stand with regard to Spinoza s conception of theological questions such as the existence of miracles, the nature of true religion and the method for interpreting of Scripture. It also includes discussions of problems in political philosophy such as the foundations of natural right and the relations between church and state. Next, Lærke turns to Leibniz attitude towards Spinoza s metaphysics. Spinoza s position was gradually exposed to him during the latter part of his stay in Paris, in 1675 6, when he met and discussed Spinoza s philosophy with Spinoza s friend and follower Ehrenfried Walther von Tschirnhaus. Elaborating mainly on suggestions originally made by Mark Kulstad, Lærke argues that these exchanges prompted Leibniz to engage seriously with Spinozistic ideas in the set of metaphysical fragments known as the De summa rerum. Lærke argues that, for several months during this period, Leibniz in effect holds a quasi-spinozist system. Although he had already learned about aspects of Spinoza s philosophy during this early period in Paris, Leibniz only had the opportunity to study in detail the Ethics in 1678 after Spinoza s Opera posthuma had been published towards the end of 1677. Leibniz s reception of this publication is the object of the following part of the book. Lærke analyses Leibniz critical comments on Spinoza with regard to the use of language in philosophy, the nature of substance and modes, the existence of God, and the necessity or contingency of the world. In addition, Lærke also attempts to reconstruct what Spinoza s response to Leibniz comments might have been. According to Lærke s account, the 1678 reading of the Ethics constitutes the main turning point in his attitude towards Spinoza. After 1679, Leibniz s opposition is fully formed and becomes a straightforward and complete rejection. In fact, it appears that he never reread Spinoza after that date. This lack of direct engagement with Spinoza s texts in Leibniz s later comments has led commentators such as Georges Friedmann to speak of his attitude towards Spinoza as lacking both nuance and textual basis. According to Lærke, however, Leibniz later writings testify to a change of strategy in dealing with this dangerous thinker, whom the German philosopher now attempts to master and tame through a series of comparative interpretations of Spinoza s work, in relation to Cartesianism, cabbalism and the moderate form of scepticism defended by Pierre Bayle. Thus, to summarize the story about Leibniz and Spinoza told by Lærke, the young Leibniz seeks to refute the views expressed in the TTP, though he has high esteem for the erudition of its author and finds himself metaphysically curious about Spinoza in 1672 6. Once Leibniz reads the

BOOK REVIEW 523 Ethics, his curiosity turns sour. He comes to see that Spinoza s metaphysics and his political theology form one inseparable whole an extremely repugnant one, even to his creative mind. Leibniz, who has a remarkable knack of using every conceptual thread and every insight for his grand reconciliatory project, finds nothing to borrow, nothing to modify, nothing to use in Spinoza s system and a total rejection ensues. So much for the overall thesis of Leibniz Lecteur de Spinoza. Let me now briefly consider Lærke s discussion of Leibniz reading notes on Spinoza s Ethics from 1678. Lærke presents and discusses these notes in great detail. His discussion is comprehensive, insightful and illuminating. It also greatly enriches the book in comparing the way Leibniz has read Spinoza with what Lærke regards as the true system of Spinoza (993). The result is a rich discussion of the philosophical opposition between Leibniz and Spinoza. However, Lærke argues that, generally speaking, Leibniz has not engaged the true Spinoza in dialogue but rather, something of a cre ature me connaissable (993). In his conclusion, Lærke argues that Leibniz detailed criticisms of some of Spinoza s propositions and their alleged proofs do not even address the true system of Spinoza but only Leibniz misconception of Spinoza ( son Spinoza (993). According to Lærke, in a certain sense, Leibniz cannot even be regarded as an anti-spinozist because he does not master the peculiar form of reasoning that governs Spinoza s thought. Leibniz, thus, does not object to Spinoza s true philosophy but to his own translations of it. Since Leibniz misread Spinoza s Ethics in this way, it goes without saying that his critical remarks are off the mark. Lærke s conclusion concerning these notes raises some interesting questions of both method and substance. For example, I find the claim that Leibniz could not grasp the form of reasoning that governs Spinoza s thought exaggerated. Is it not the case that Leibniz has made some good objections to Spinoza s reasoning and metaphysical system? The problems of ambiguity and obscurity he is pointing out in the Ethics seem to me real and in fact are probably bound to arise in any attempt to formalize philosophy. The difficulty arises with the very definition of terms that have their origin in natural languages in a precise formal fashion (Lærke addresses some aspects of this difficulty in his section on Language and its use (593 624)). Unlike what Lærke s conclusion suggests, I think that Leibniz s critical remarks are helping to expose some of the inherent difficulties in Spinoza s metaphysics and in the enterprise of doing philosophy more geometrico. Thus, I remain unconvinced by Lærke s point that Leibniz does not criticize Spinoza but only his own Spinoza. After all, how is one to read and criticize any system or text other than according to the way one understands it? I doubt that anyone has a better theory of what understanding a certain philosopher means other than to engage his text in a critical discussion. And isn t this what Leibniz does, sometimes more successfully and sometimes less so? If I could amend Lærke s conclusion, I would add that there is another 95 100 105 110 115 120 125 130 135

524 BOOK REVIEW 140 145 150 155 strand, as important to Leibniz s reading of Spinoza, namely that it is precisely because Leibniz sees through Spinoza s system that he attempts to present a philosophical system that avoids its consequences (such as the moral neutrality of the world). It is precisely because he reads and understands Spinoza in the context of the seventeenth century that he is urged to enhance his own system as an alternative. Such an observation would surely not make the opposition between Spinoza and Leibniz less complex; rather, it would slightly modify the complexity Lærke has so convincingly exposed and would amend his somewhat imbalanced conclusion. Moreover, I also think that this modified conclusion only increases the interest and profit one can draw from Lærke s detailed analysis. After all, Leibniz and Spinoza s remain the two great systems after Descartes. As Lærke s book shows, there is still much to be learned from a detailed comparison of their texts and the context of their opposition. If my review has not made this out, let me state explicitly that no Spinoza or Leibniz scholar can afford to ignore a book as informative and stimulating as this one. Ohad Nachtomy Princeton University ª 2010, Ohad Nachtomy 160 165 170 175 180