Mitzvat Asei 1: Knowing/Believing in God's Existence By David Silverberg

Similar documents
Hilkhot Teshuva 2:7 The Obligation to Repent on Yom Kippur By David Silverberg

Hilkhot Teshuva 1: The Mitzva of Teshuva By David Silverberg

Parashat Ki Tisa "The Lord Would Speak to Moshe Face to Face": Maimonides' Seventh Principle of Faith by Rabbi David Silverberg

Maimonides on Hearing the Shofar Rabbi David Silverberg

The Akeida By David Silverberg

KRIAT SHEMA 2:1. by Rabbi Yitzchak Etshalom

Moshe s Mission to Pharaoh in Light of Rambam s Hilchos Teshuvah

The Counting of the Omer by David Silverberg

Hilkhot Teshuva 2:10 Granting Forgiveness to One's Fellow By David Silverberg

Hilkhot Teshuva 2:6 The Ten Days of Repentance By David Silverberg

Relationship of Science to Torah HaRav Moshe Sternbuch, shlita Authorized translation by Daniel Eidensohn

Rabbi Farber raised two sorts of issues, which I think are best separated:

Chapter 2 - Intellectual Knowledge and Experiential Knowledge

The Glory of God Is Intelligence : A Note on Maimonides. FARMS Review 19/2 (2007): (print), (online)

Rambam. Rabbi Moshe ben Maimon (Maimonides)

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

Be Wholehearted (Tamim) with the L-rd, Your G-d.

Shemitta and Yovel by David Silverberg

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Time needed: The time allotments are for a two hour session and may be modified as needed for your group.

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

How to Live with Lavan

Mitzvot & Tzadaka. by Michael Rudolph Message Delivered to Ohev Yisrael December 5, 2009

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

Response to Rabbi Eliezer Ben Porat

The Voice That Did Not Cease

In preparing a sermon, especially during the Yomin Noraim, the first question that

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

THE DIVINE CODE - 20'16 ASK NOAH INTERNATIONAL 1

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

The Purpose of the Mishkan

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Understanding the Essence of Shema Yisrael

Response to Rabbi Marc D. Angel s Article on Gerut

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

Mitzvot Religious & Moral Principles

The Length of Exile - The Mechanism of Time and a Discrepancy in the Torah By Rabbi Dovid Markel

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

The Purpose of Creation

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Hebrews 3:1-6 (NIV) Matthew 7:24-29

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Week of. Parshas Yisro. Compiled from the works of Rabbi Menachem Mendel Schneerson The Lubavitcher Rebbe. by Rabbi Shmuel Mendelsohn

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

ON DEGREE ACTUALISM ALEXANDRA LECLAIR 1 INTRODUCTION

1/9. The First Analogy

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

DID THE PATRIARCHS KNOW GOD S NAME?

1/12. The A Paralogisms

THE DIVINE CODE ASK NOAH INTERNATIONAL

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

1/8. The Third Analogy

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

How to Love Your Fellow Jew

GILYON BIRCHAS BINYOMIN. Pirsumei Nisa - Even The Shirt On Your Back

Not Remembering and Forgetting What They Really Mean

THE RATIONALITY OF JEWISH ETHICS

GCSE Religious Studies: Paper 2, Unit 9: Judaism: beliefs and teachings. 9.6 The Promised Land and the covenant with Abraham

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

A FEW QUESTIONS: What is belief? Do you believe in God? Is there a benefit to belief in God? What benefit? Does belief require trust?

Lehrhaus Lunchtime Talmud The Invention of Marriage. Selections from Responsa On Jewish Marriage by Rabbi Eugene Mihaly

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

A Medieval Controversy About Profit and Loss Allocations

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

The Posek: His Role and Responsibility

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Parshas Lech-Lecha. What G-d Owns

15 Does God have a Nature?

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

'Things' for 'Actions': Locke's Mistake in 'Of Power' Locke Studies 10 (2010):85-94 Julie Walsh

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

The Vatican and the Jews

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Love and Fear-Awe / Ahava v yirah. from Alei Shur, by Rabbi Shlomo Wolbe, pp

"Halacha Sources" Highlights - Why "Shekalim"? - Can't "Ki Sisa" Stay In Its Own Week?

Who Is the Righteous Remnant in Romans 9 11?

Deed & Creed - Class #7

Transcription:

Mitzvat Asei 1: Knowing/Believing in God's Existence By David Silverberg In the prevalent Hebrew translation of Sefer Ha-mitzvot, Maimonides describes the first mitzvat asei ("positive commandment") as follows: "The first commandment is that He commanded us to believe in the divine, meaning, that we believe that there is a primary cause that brings all things into existence, and this is what is said, 'I am the Lord your God'." According to Maimonides, the verse that opens the Ten Commandments, "Anokhi Hashem Elokekha" "I am the Lord your God" (Shemot 20:2) introduces an obligation to believe in the existence of God, or, more precisely, a Creator, and this obligation constitutes one of the 613 Biblical commands. Maimonides proceeds to cite a Talmudic source for his view that this verse introduces one of the 613 commandments. In Masekhet Makot (23b), the Gemara cites the famous passage of Rabbi Simlai that forms the basis of the entire notion of there being 613 commandments: "613 mitzvot were said to Moshe at Sinai." The Gemara finds a subtle allusion to this number from the celebrated verse (Devarim 33:4), "Torah tziva lanu Moshe" "Moshe commanded us the Torah." The numerical value of the word Torah, the Gemara observes, is 611, suggesting that Moshe transmitted to Benei Yisrael 611 commandments. The Gemara comments that in addition to these 611 commandments, Benei Yisrael heard two commands from God directly, without the mediation of Moshe: Anokhi and Lo yihyeh lekha. It appears that the Gemara refers to the first two of the Ten Commandments "I am the Lord your God" and "You shall have no other gods besides Me" claiming that these two commandments were heard directly from God, for a total of 613 mitzvot. It thus clearly emerges from this passage that the Gemara deemed this verse "I am the Lord your God" as one of the 613 commandments. Maimonides understands this mitzva as requiring the fundamental belief in the existence of a Creator. Mishneh Torah This mitzva begins not only Maimonides' listing of the commandments, but also his halakhic code, Mishneh Torah. He begins this work by establishing that "the most fundamental of principles and the pillar of wisdoms is to know that there is a first cause and He brings into existence everything that exists" (Hilkhot Yesodei Ha-Torah 1:1). Later (1:6), Maimonides adds, "Knowing this matter is a mitzvat asei, as it says, 'I am the Lord your God'." Many writers have addressed the seeming discrepancy between Maimonides' formulation in describing this mitzva in Sefer Ha-mitzvot, and in Mishneh Torah. Whereas in Sefer Ha-mitzvot Maimonides speaks of "belief" in the Creator, in Mishneh Torah he describes the obligation as "knowing" that there exists a Creator. "Belief," or emuna in Hebrew, generally connotes holding a concept to be true irrespective of any rational proof, whereas yedi'a, or knowledge, usually refers to cognitive, definitive 1

acknowledgment of an idea. For example, if somebody informs his fellow that he performed a certain act the previous day, the friend will believe the information; he has no concrete, logical proof that his friend did as he claimed, but he will nevertheless trust that the information is accurate. By contrast, somebody who witnesses his friend perform that act knows cognitively that this in fact occurred. In Sefer Ha-mitzvot, it appears, Maimonides enjoins us to believe in the Creator, to acknowledge His existence despite the fact that we cannot rationally prove it. In Mishneh Torah, however, he speaks of knowing that the Creator exists, just as we know without any doubt or hesitation that which we directly perceive with our senses. Indeed, a number of writers interpret Maimonides' description of the mitzva in Mishneh Torah in terms of philosophical inquiry to prove the Creator's existence. The Radbaz (Rabbi David Ben Zimra, Egypt, 1480-1573), for example, in his work Metzudat David, understands Maimonides here as requiring that one arrive at rational proofs and effective arguments to refute heretical theories denying God's existence. The work Ma'aseh Rokei'ach explains that Maimonides requires philosophical engagement resembling that undertaken by Avraham, as Maimonides describes later in Mishneh Torah (Hilkhot Avodat Kokhavim 1:3), to prove the existence of a single Creator and reject the claims of paganism. Furthermore, Rabbi Meir Leibush Malbim (1809-1879), in his Torah commentary (Shemot 20:2), interprets Maimonides' comments in Mishneh Torah in light of the controversial theory he posits in the Guide for the Perplexed (2:33), that "the existence of God and His unity can be arrived at by means of reasoning." According to Malbim, when Maimonides speaks of an obligation to "know" the existence of the Creator, he mandates that we employ logic and philosophical reasoning to arrive at the knowledge of God's existence. But while this is very likely Maimonides' intent in Mishneh Torah, it does not explain why he formulated this obligation differently in Sefer Ha-mitzvot. Among the intriguing theories advanced to resolve this seeming discrepancy was suggested by Rabbi Aharon Soloveitchik, in his work Perach Mateh Aharon, a commentary on the Madda section of Mishneh Torah. Rabbi Soloveitchik boldly asserts that Maimonides understood this mitzva as imposing different demands upon different classes of people, and that the two aforementioned contexts are addressed to two different audiences. Sefer Ha-mitzvot, Rabbi Soloveitchik claimed, was written for the masses, and it therefore requires belief, a conviction that one holds without concrete proof or rationalization. In Mishneh Torah, however, Maimonides speaks to the scholar, and demands of him the knowledge of God's existence, that he probe and inquire philosophically into the notion of a Creator. According to this theory, whether the Torah requires intuitive belief or definitive knowledge depends on the given individual's personal capabilities. Many others, however, claimed that the perceived discrepancy between the two passages results from an inaccurate translation of Sefer Ha-mitzvot. (Recall from our introductory shiur that unlike Mishneh Torah, which was written in rabbinic Hebrew, Sefer Ha-mitzvot was written in Arabic.) The Arabic word employed by Maimonides in this context and rendered as le-ha'amin ("to believe") is itakad, which, as Rabbi Chayim Heller notes in his annotation to Sefer Ha-mitzvot, is also used to mean "knowledge." Indeed, this word is the second term in the title of Saadia Gaon's famous philosophical treatise which has become known to us by Hebrew translators as Emunot Ve-dei'ot, which of course assumes that this word is equivalent to the Hebrew word dei'a, or knowledge. 2

Rabbi Yosef Kapach, in his commentary to Mishneh Torah, argues that itakad means exclusively "knowledge," and not "belief," and he thus entirely dismisses the notion of any discrepancy between Maimonides' descriptions of this mitzva in Mishneh Torah and Sefer Ha-mitzvot. More importantly, perhaps, as Rabbi Kapach notes, Maimonides explicitly clarifies for us what he means by this Arabic term, in a passage in the Guide for the Perplexed (1:50). We cite this passage here from Friedlander's translation, where, interestingly enough, the term itakad is in fact rendered as "faith": When reading my present treatise, bear in mind that by "faith" we do not understand merely that which is uttered with the lips, but also that which is apprehended by the soul, the conviction that the object [of belief] is exactly as it is apprehended. If, as regards real or supposed truths, you content yourself with giving utterance to them in words, without apprehending them or believing in them, especially if you do not seek real truth, you have a very easy task as, in fact, you will find many ignorant people professing articles of faith without connecting any idea with them For belief is only possible after the apprehension of a thing; it consists in the conviction that the thing apprehended has its existence beyond the mind [in reality] exactly as it is conceived in the mind. Thus, itakad describes a cognitive process of "apprehension of a thing" followed by the "conviction" that this "apprehension" corresponds precisely to reality. It denotes a degree of confidence and certitude that extends beyond verbal professing or even acting upon the given notion. It thus appears likely that even in Sefer Ha-mitzvot Maimonides speaks of "knowing" the existence of the Creator, the intellectual process of arriving at this fundamental theological truth through rational thinking. A Mitzva or the Basis of Mitzvot? This understanding of Maimonides' definition of this mitzva, as requiring philosophical inquiry, rather than a mere declaration of belief, helps resolve two wellknown challenges to his inclusion of Anokhi as one of the 613 commandments. As Nachmanides notes in his critique of Sefer Ha-mitzvot, the Behag, author of what had been the authoritative listing of the 613 mitzvot, did not include the belief in God as one of the Biblical commands. Nachmanides speculates that the Behag omitted this command for the simple reason that the precept of God's existence is a necessary prerequisite for the acceptance of His commands. In the Behag's view, it would be tautological for God to issue a command demanding the recognition of His existence; the very setting of a Diving Being conveying instructions to His subjects presumes a rulersubject dynamic, which obviously depends on both parties' awareness and acceptance of the other's status within this framework. (Nachmanides raises also a second argument against the inclusion of this mitzva, which we will address later.) In addition, Rabbi Chasdai Crescas (Spanish Jewish philosopher, 1340-1410), in his harsh critique of Maimonides entitled Or Hashem, objects to the notion of God commanding the human being with respect to belief. Crescas contends that God could demand that we perform an action or refrain from performing an action, but He cannot demand that we think one way 3

and not another. Thought and belief, he argues, are not subject to the human being's free will, as one cannot necessarily control what he believes. Therefore, God cannot issue a command that we accept the belief in His existence. Both these challenges are instantly negated the moment we explain this mitzva as demanding "knowledge," rather than "belief." According to Maimonides, Anokhi Hashem Elokekha requires one to probe and inquire, not simply to profess a belief. Of course, Benei Yisrael believed in God's existence before they stood at the foot of Mount Sinai and heard Him command "I am the Lord your God"; the Torah explicitly describes their firm belief in God after the miracle of the splitting of the sea (Shemot 14:31). Anokhi demanded according to Maimonides that they develop and refine this belief, advancing it from mere faith to an incontrovertible philosophical truth. This is, in general terms, the approach taken by Don Isaac Abarbanel (philosopher and exegete, Spain- Portgual 1437-1508) to explain and defend Maimonides' position, in the seventh chapter of his work Rosh Amana (translated from Hebrew by Menachem Kellner). Abarbanel cites Crescas' challenge to Maimonides and offers the following response: I respond [to this objection] and say that I have already explained in the ninth proposition that beliefs are actualized and fixed in a man's heart and soul just as natural forms are fixed in their subjects, coming in an instant and by necessity, without choice and will. But despite all this, it is impossible for these beliefs to be actualized if no preparation for them is made, with respect to knowing those things which bring one to those beliefs and which cause them to be accepted by the soul. These facts, investigations, and examinations, and this study are the preparations which bring a person to belief. There is no doubt that these preparations are an activity of will and choice and are acquired over time. For it is up to each person "to perceive, learn, teach," and know those things which necessitate and give birth to belief in his soul. If he does not wish to involve himself with this, [beliefs will not be born in his soul]. Now Maimonides did not count as a positive commandment the form of the belief and its truth, but, rather, knowledge of those things which bring one to acquire beliefs Maimonides did not say that belief in this truth is an affirmative precept [mitzvat asei], for he did not relate the commandment to belief but to knowing those things which bring one to belief. The mitzva demands not belief itself, but rather what Abarbanel describes as "knowing those things which bring one to belief," or, in simpler terms, exerting the intellectual effort to arrive at the "knowledge" of the existence of a Creator. Abarbanel advanced this theory in response to Crescas' objection, that belief is not subject to human free will and thus does not lend itself to a Biblical imperative. But his reading of Maimonides just as well refutes Nachmanides' challenge, that belief precedes the very notion of a divine command and thus cannot itself constitute a divine command. Nachmanides is, of course, correct; one must believe in a Creator before one can accept the commands issued by that Creator. But, as Abarbanel explained, Maimonides understood Anokhi as mandating not belief, but intellectual engagement that leads to concrete knowledge. This process clearly does not necessarily precede the acknowledgment of the notion of a divine command. 4

We should also note that Rabbi Chananya Kazis, author of Kin'at Soferim, a work defending Sefer Ha-mitzvot from its critics, advances a different theory in response to Nachmanides' challenge. He claims that this verse introduces an obligation not to believe in the Creator a belief that Benei Yisrael had already attained previously but rather to "maintain this belief among them [the Jewish people] in the most perfect way, and teach it and bequeath it to their offspring, for eternity." According to the Kin'at Soferim, Maimonides understood Anokhi as a command not to believe, but to work towards the preservation of this belief among the nation's posterity. But while this approach to Maimonides' position indeed very easily resolves the challenges of Crescas and Nachmanides, it hardly accommodates Maimonides' formulation, which quite clearly indicates that this obligation relates to one's personal religious outlook, rather than its perpetuation through subsequent generations. Maimonides' Talmudic Source As Nachmanides was well aware, any defense of the Behag's position must address the seemingly convincing proof Maimonides brings to his position from the Talmud in Masekhet Makot, where the Gemara makes clear reference to the two commands of Anokhi and Lo yihyeh lekha. In response, Nachmanides suggests a novel but perhaps forced reading of the Gemara, whereby the Gemara refers to the two prohibitions subsumed under the passage that begins "Yo yihyeh lekha." The Torah here forbids fashioning and possessing articles of idolatry, as well as the worship of these articles ("Lo yihyeh lekha Lo ta'aseh lekha"; "Lo tishtachaveh lahem ve-lo ta'ovdem"). Nachmanides thus suggests that although the Gemara mentions Anokhi and Lo yihyeh lekha, it in truth refers to the two prohibitions of Lo yihyeh lekha possessing or making idols and Lo tishtacheveh lahem worshipping idols. According to this reading, the Gemara does not cast Anokhi as a separate command, and this is perhaps how the Behag interpreted this Talmudic passage. Indeed, as Nachmanides notes, the Behag lists possessing and worshipping idols as two separate commands, a listing consistent with the theory Nachmanides here seeks to attribute to him. (Interestingly enough, Rabbi Yerucham Fischel Perlow, in his commentary on Saadia Gaon's poetic listing of the commandments, notes that in more authoritative texts of the Behag, the prohibition against possessing idols is not, in fact, listed as a separate commandment.) Rabbi Chasdai Crescas suggests this reading of the Gemara, as well. Of course, as argued in the Lev Samei'ach and Megilat Ester commentaries to Sefer Ha-mitzvot, this reading is very difficult to sustain, as there seems to be little reason for the Gemara to make any mention of Anokhi if it does not deem it a mitzva at all. It seems more likely that the Behag, and the others like Saadia Gaon who likewise do not consider Anokhi as one of the 613 commandments, based themselves on a different source. The Mekhilta, as Nachmanides cites in his Torah commentary (Shemot 20:2-3), describes the declaration of Anokhi as God's calling upon Benei Yisrael to profess their acceptance of His authority before He proceeds to convey to them His commandments. This formulation very strongly resembles Nachmanides' understanding of the Behag's position, that Anokhi be seen as a necessary preamble to the commandments, rather than a commandment in and of itself. If so, then we might 5

speculate that the Behag derived his stance from the Mekhilta, such that any indication in the Talmud to the contrary may be dismissed as representative of a conflicting position. Command or Affirmation? Nachmanides posed a second argument in defense of the Behag, as well, namely, that the clause "Anokhi Hashem Elokekha," which Maimonides understands as introducing an obligation, is clearly written as an affirmative, rather than imperative, statement. God here appears to merely introduce Himself, so-to-speak, to the Israelite people before proceeding to present to them His instructions. According to Maimonides, God should have declared, "You shall believe that I am God," or something of that nature, rather than simply establishing the fact that "I am the Lord your God." How could this verse introduce an obligation if it is written as an affirmative statement, rather than a command? The Maharal of Prague (Rabbi Yehuda Loew, 1525-1609) addresses this question in his work Tiferet Yisrael (chapter 37). He suggests that the Almighty chose not to formulate this mitzva as a command so as to emphasize the unshakeable truth that "I am the Lord your God" regardless of whether or not one chooses to accept this fundamental belief. Had God commanded, "Acknowledge Me as Creator," one might mistakenly conclude that just as it is conceivably possible to deny the authority of a mortal king and thereby free oneself of his rule, so, too, can one choose to shake himself free of divine authority. The Almighty wanted to impress upon Benei Yisrael that they are forever under His control and authority regardless of their acceptance or denial of this axiomatic truism; He therefore issued this command as a statement of fact, rather than as an order that could potentially be violated. A simpler answer is suggested by Rabbi Avraham Aligri, author of the Lev Samei'ach commentary to Sefer Ha-mitzvot. The Lev Samei'ach suggests that Maimonides understood from context that Anokhi Hashem Elokekha introduces a command, rather than a statement of fact. For one thing, even before the Revelation at Sinai, when Benei Yisrael first encamped near the mountain, God spoke to Moshe and had him tell Benei Yisrael, "You have seen what I did to Egypt, and that I carried you on wings of eagles and brought you to Me " (Shemot 19:4). With this verse God introduces to the people the terms of His covenant, which they gladly accept: "The entire nation replied in unison and said: All that the Lord said we will observe" (Shemot 19:8). There would be no reason, then, for God to once again "introduce Himself" to the people at the actual Revelation, before presenting His commandments. It thus stands to reason that Anokhi signifies a command, rather than a preamble. Furthermore, the Lev Samei'ach argues, it seems reasonable to assume that all the information inscribed upon the tablets involves commandments, and not introductory information. The context of Anokhi, as part of the ten principles that comprise the elementary creed of Jewish law, strongly suggests that it presents a command, rather than simply a truism. The Lev Samei'ach adds that in another instance, too, Maimonides identifies the Biblical source of an obligation in a verse that reads as an affirmation rather than a command. The 153 rd mitzvat asei listed by Maimonides is that of kiddush ha-chodesh, maintaining the lunar calendar system, which he derives from the verse in the Book of Shemot (12:2), "This month is for you the first of months." Here, too, the Torah simply 6

establishes a fact, implying a command that Benei Yisrael must implement and abide by this system. It should therefore not surprise us that Maimonides similarly understood "I am the Lord your God" as mandating albeit indirectly that every Jew firmly accept the basic precept of God as Creator. 7