Mètode Science Studies Journal ISSN: Universitat de València España

Similar documents
IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

Intelligent Design. Kevin delaplante Dept. of Philosophy & Religious Studies

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Prentice Hall Biology 2004 (Miller/Levine) Correlated to: Idaho Department of Education, Course of Study, Biology (Grades 9-12)

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter One. Individual Subjectivism

Darwinist Arguments Against Intelligent Design Illogical and Misleading

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Coptic Orthodox Diocese of the Southern United States Evangelism & Apologetics Conference. Copyright by George Bassilios, 2014

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Course Webpage:

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

ASA 2017 Annual Meeting. Stephen Dilley, Ph.D., and Nicholas Tafacory St Edward s University

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

BIO 221 Invertebrate Zoology I Spring Course Information. Course Website. Lecture 1. Stephen M. Shuster Professor of Invertebrate Zoology

An Interview with Jaakko Hintikka

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH

Physics 496 Introduction to Research. Lecture 2.0: Tools for the Scientific Skeptic (Based on a talk by Lance Cooper)

Ground Work 01 part one God His Existence Genesis 1:1/Psalm 19:1-4

William B. Provine. February 19, 1942 September 8, 2015

Stout s teleological theory of action

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Basic Concepts and Skills!

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Lars Johan Erkell. Intelligent Design

The Debate Between Evolution and Intelligent Design Rick Garlikov

Roots of Dialectical Materialism*

Introduction to Evolution. DANILO V. ROGAYAN JR. Faculty, Department of Natural Sciences

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Charles Robert Darwin ( ) Born in Shrewsbury, England. His mother died when he was eight, a

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Of Mice and Men, Kangaroos and Chimps

Scientific Dimensions of the Debate. 1. Natural and Artificial Selection: the Analogy (17-20)

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

The Biological Foundation of Bioethics

However, this law was quickly challenged by a group called the ACLU, which stands for the American Civil Liberties Union, and was taken to court.

Final grades will be determined by 6 components: Midterm 20% Final 20% Problem Sets 20% Papers 20% Quizzes 10% Section 10%

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

The Design Argument A Perry

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Homology versus analogy

FAITH & reason. The Pope and Evolution Anthony Andres. Winter 2001 Vol. XXVI, No. 4

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Explaining Science-Based Beliefs such as Darwin s Evolution and Big Bang Theory as a. form of Creationist Beliefs

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2013 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Keeping Your Kids On God s Side - Natasha Crain

DNA, Information, and the Signature in the Cell

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

EVOLUTION, EMPIRICISM, AND PURPOSENESS.

BERKELEY, REALISM, AND DUALISM: REPLY TO HOCUTT S GEORGE BERKELEY RESURRECTED: A COMMENTARY ON BAUM S ONTOLOGY FOR BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

The Problem of Normativity

MINNESOTA HISTORY A SCIENTIST LOOKS AT HISTORY^

DARWIN and EVOLUTION

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Written by Rupert Sheldrake, Ph.D. Sunday, 01 September :00 - Last Updated Wednesday, 18 March :31

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

Department of Philosophy

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

The tribulations of Rationality in Philosophy, Economics and Biology by Alex Kacelnik University of Oxford

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

Philosophical Arguments

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Transcription:

Mètode Science Studies Journal ISSN: 2174-3487 metodessj@uv.es Universitat de València España Sober, Elliott IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Mètode Science Studies Journal, núm. 5, 2015, pp. 195-199 Universitat de València Valencia, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=511751360027 How to cite Complete issue More information about this article Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Scientific Information System Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative

MÈTODE Science Studies Journal, 5 (2015): 195-199. University of Valencia. DOI: 10.7203/metode.84.3883 ISSN: 2174-3487. Article received: 10/07/2014, accepted: 18/09/2014. IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE ELLIOTT SOBER Many philosophers and historians of science deny that there is a single scientific method that applies across all scientific disciplines. Here I distinguish normative from descriptive versions of this thesis. I defend the thesis that there are general normative principles that govern every science. Keywords: Darwin, Einstein, evolution, inference, methodology. LUMPERS AND SPLITTERS In many areas of inquiry, both inside and outside of science, there is a division between the «lumpers» and the «splitters». There are those who emphasize similarities and those who emphasize differences. The first person to use these terms in this way may have been Charles Darwin who in 1857 applied them in a letter he wrote to his friend Joseph Dalton Hooker about the problem of how to separate one biological species from another: «those who make many species are the splitters and those who make few are the lumpers». If you ask historians of science and philosophers of science whether there is such a thing as the scientific method, you will find that there are lumpers and splitters on that subject too. Historians are mostly splitters. They will say that the methods used in a scientific discipline have changed through time and that different scientific disciplines have different methodologies. Most historians of science are disinclined to present grand theories of scientific change, and this particularism shows itself when they think about the methods that scientists use. In the past fifty years or so, philosophy of science has moved closer to history of science than it was before. There now are more splitters and fewer lumpers in philosophy of science than there used to be. Lumping is now less fashionable, in part because the philosophy of the separate sciences has been on an upswing while «HISTORIANS ARE IN THE BUSINESS OF DESCRIBING AND EXPLAINING HOW SCIENCE ACTUALLY WORKS, NOT HOW IT OUGHT TO BE DONE IN SOME PHILOSOPHICAL UTOPIA» general philosophy of science is now in a downturn. For example, philosophers are now less likely to discuss what a scientific explanation is than they are to discuss what an explanation in evolutionary biology is. The days of grand philosophies of science are on the wane. And yet there still are lumping philosophers. One reason this tendency is more strongly represented among philosophers of science than among historians is that philosophers often think their job is «normative». These philosophers think their task is to describe the methods that scientists «ought» to use. Historians rarely see this as their job. They are in the business of describing and explaining how science actually works, not how it ought to be done in some philosophical utopia. Historians often believe that normative philosophy of science is absurd. This is what they frequently think, even if they are too polite to say so: «Who do these philosophers think they are, telling scientists what they should do? There are no philosopher kings, nor should there be! Scientists know best!» Normative philosophers do not want to be kings, but they still think their goals make sense. There are two main reasons why. WHY THERE ARE GENERAL NORMS OF SCIENTIFIC REASONING The first reason comes from science itself. Scientists often are confident that there are principles of MÈTODE 195

scientific reasoning that transcend the boundaries of particular disciplines. Here are quotations from two of The Greats. In the sixth and final edition of On the Origin of Species, which appeared in 1872, Darwin says the following about his theory: It can hardly be supposed that a false theory would explain, in so satisfactory a manner as does the theory of natural selection the several large classes of facts above specified. It has recently been objected that this is an unsafe method of arguing. But it is a method used in judging of the common events of life, and has often been used by the greatest natural philosophers. The undulatory theory of light has thus been arrived at; and the belief in the revolution of the earth on its own axis was until lately supported by hardly any direct evidence. DARWIN, 1959 And Einstein spoke for many of his fellow scientists when he said: It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience. EINSTEIN, 1933 Of course, the fact that Darwin and Einstein both claim that there are methodological principles that apply in multiple areas of science doesn t ensure that what they say is true! Einstein is famous for warning in that same 1933 lecture that «if you want to find out anything from the theoretical physicists about the methods they use, I advise you to stick closely to one principle: do not listen to their words, fix your attention on their deeds». This is a good point. But if you think that scientists are the sole authorities on how scientific reasoning should proceed, the testimony of scientists themselves should make you pause. If Darwin and Einstein are right, there are methods of reasoning that span different scientific subject matters. Scientists rarely are trained and rarely are interested in questions with this kind of generality. Geneticists study genes and astronomers study galaxies; neither specializes in the study of patterns of reasoning. The study of patterns of reasoning is something that philosophers aim to understand. The second reason for thinking that the project of constructing normative philosophical theories about the scientific method makes sense comes from within philosophy itself. In the twentieth century, logic became more and more of a mathematical discipline, but before then it was solidly anchored in philosophy. A central subject of logic was and still is the study of arguments that are deductively valid. Validity is MÈTODE The first person to use the terms «lumper» and «splitter» in this way may have been Charles Darwin (on the left) who in 1857 applied them in a letter he wrote to his friend Joseph Dalton Hooker (on the right) about the problem of how to separate one biological species from another: «those who make many species are the splitters and those who make few are the lumpers». a technical term. The following two arguments each have two premises and a single conclusion. Both are deductively valid, meaning that if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true: Socrates is a human being. All human beings are mortal. Socrates is mortal. The Parthenon is made of stone. All things that are made of stone are hard. The Parthenon is hard. Not only are both arguments deductively valid; they are valid for the same reason. The arguments have the same «logical form». That is, each can be obtained from the following skeleton by substituting words for letters: 196 MÈTODE

as deductive logic generalizes across arguments that concern wildly different subject matters, nondeductive logic does the same. Statisticians have developed theories of reasoning that apply to weather systems, economies, and genetics. The tools they have constructed are general; they are not limited in their application to a single subject matter. Normative philosophy of science is in the same line of work. Individual i is an X. All Xs are Ys. Individual i is a Y. Deductive validity has nothing to do with the subject matters of arguments. What makes an argument valid is its form, not what it is about. Scientific arguments are often not deductively valid. They often begin with observations and end with conclusions that are very general and describe parts of the world that we cannot observe. The fact that these arguments are not deductively valid is not a criticism of them; these arguments aim to defend conclusions that go beyond the observations that are their premises. Many scientists, philosophers, and statisticians have thought that the rules for determining whether a nondeductive argument is strong or weak are provided by the mathematical theory of probability. The precedent of deductive logic has had a strong influence. Just «IN THE PAST FIFTY YEARS OR SO, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE HAS MOVED CLOSER TO HISTORY OF SCIENCE THAN IT WAS BEFORE» COMMON ANCESTRY, PLAGIARISM AND THE LAW OF LIKELIHOOD Let me give an example. One of the central concepts in Darwin s theory of evolution is common ancestry. Darwin thought that all living things now on earth trace back to one or a few «original progenitors». The other central idea in the theory is that natural selection is the main but not the exclusive cause of the diversity we see in living things. It is unfortunate that Darwin s theory is now widely thought of as the theory of evolution by natural selection, with no mention made of the common ancestry idea. Rather than calling it «the theory of evolution by natural selection», it is better to call it «the theory of common ancestry plus natural selection» (Sober, 2012). Because his theory has two parts, you might think that when Darwin discusses in The Origin of Species which characteristics provide the strongest evidence for common ancestry, that he ll cite the characteristics that evolved because of natural selection. This is the opposite of what he actually says: [ ] adaptive characters, although of the utmost importance to the welfare of the being, are almost valueless to the systematist. For animals belonging to two most distinct lines of descent, may readily become adapted to similar conditions, and thus assume a close external resemblance; but such resemblances will not reveal will rather tend to conceal their blood-relationship to their proper lines of descent. DARWIN, 1859 The best evidence for common ancestry comes from characteristics that did not evolve by natural selection. We observe that dolphins and sharks are both shaped like torpedoes; Darwin is saying that this similarity is not strong evidence that dolphins and sharks have a common ancestor. The reason is that the torpedo shape is useful to these organisms it helps them to swim fast. The similarities that provide MÈTODE 197

strong evidence for common ancestry involve traits that are not adaptive for one or both of the organisms considered. This is why the tailbones that monkeys and humans have are strong evidence for common ancestry. So far it may seem that Darwin s idea is specific to the subject matter of evolutionary biology. In fact, it is not. Precisely the same form of reasoning comes up in entirely different subject matters. The philosopher of science Wesley Salmon, in his 1984 book Scientifi c Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World, describes the following example. The students in a university philosophy class are told by their professor to write an essay on an assigned topic. When the students hand in their essays, the professor sees that two of them are virtually identical. The professor realizes that the similarity of the two papers might be an improbable coincidence; perhaps the students worked separately and independently and just happened to hit on nearly the same sequence of words. But it is far more plausible to suspect that the students plagiarized; maybe they worked together, perhaps going to the Internet together to find an essay that they would each copy. Let us now reflect on the different sorts of similarities that the two students essays might exhibit. Both of the essays use nouns, but that is not strong evidence for plagiarism. Rather, it is the fact the students misspell the same words in the same ways that provides strong evidence for plagiarism. Darwin s distinction between similarities that are useful and similarities that are not applies here. The misspellings are useless to the students, though they are useful to the professor who is thinking about whether the two essays trace back to a common Internet ancestor. In his 1965 book The Logic of Statistical Inference, the philosopher Ian Hacking formulated a principle that applies to both Darwin s remark about common ancestry and to Salmon s example about student plagiarism. Hacking called this principle «The Law of Likelihood»: Observation O favors hypothesis H 1 over hypothesis H 2 precisely when Pr(O H 1 ) > Pr(O H 2 ). The expression «>» means «greater than» and «Pr(O H 1 )» represents the probability that H 1 confers on O. If H 1 says that the observation O was to be expected and H 2 says that «SCIENTIFIC ARGUMENTS ARE OFTEN NOT DEDUCTIVELY VALID. THEY OFTEN BEGIN WITH OBSERVATIONS AND END WITH CONCLUSIONS THAT ARE VERY GENERAL AND DESCRIBE PARTS OF THE WORLD THAT WE CAN T OBSERVE» O was very surprising, the law says that we should conclude that O favors H 1 over H 2. Before we apply the law to the examples from Darwin and Salmon, I want to describe what it says about a much simpler example. You are looking at a large urn that is filled with balls; each ball is green or red. You have no idea what percentage of the balls in the urn are green but you want to consider two hypotheses: (H 1 ) 80 % of the balls in the urn are green. (H 2 ) 30 % of the balls in the urn are green. You draw one hundred balls from the urn and see that 85 of them are green. What does this observation tell you about the two hypotheses? Notice that your observation doesn t prove that H 1 is true and that H 2 is false. You cannot deduce that one of them is true and that the other false from what you have observed. Given your one hundred observations, each of the hypotheses might be true; neither is ruled out. However, there is a difference between them. The first hypothesis says that what you observed was probable while the second says that what you observed was very improbable. The law of likelihood tells you to conclude that your observations favor H 1 over H 2 for that reason. Now let s move from an urn full of balls to the two students and their essays. Let us consider first the significance of the identical misspellings in the two essays: Pr(the two essays contain identical misspellings the two students plagiarized from a common source) >> Pr(the two essays contain identical misspellings the two students worked separately and independently). The double >> means that the first probability is much bigger than the second. The misspellings strongly favor the plagiarism hypothesis over the hypothesis that the students worked separately and independently. Now let s apply the law of likelihood to the observation that the two essays contain nouns: Pr(the two essays contain nouns the two students plagiarized from a common source) = Pr(the two essays contain nouns the two students worked separately and independently). You would expect the essays to contain nouns in their essays whether or not the students had plagiarized; the observation that both essays contain nouns fails Visserligen 198 MÈTODE

like a reasonable principle, but is there some deeper justification that it has? Also, there are interesting questions concerning how the law applies to the examples of plagiarism and common ancestry. What assumptions are needed to show that the inequalities and equalities I have described are true? Are there assumptions that would alter these conclusions? Contrary to Darwin, maybe there are some adaptive similarities that provide strong evidence of common ancestry; perhaps the example of the torpedo shape shared by dolphins and sharks is not typical of all adaptive similarities. I explore these further puzzles in my book Ockham s Razors A User s Manual. In his 1965 book The Logic of Statistical Inference, the philosopher Ian Hacking formulated the law of likelihood. to discriminate between the two hypotheses. The same pattern applies to useless and useful similarities in Darwin s discussion: Pr(monkeys and human beings have tail bones monkeys and humans have a common ancestor) >> Pr(monkeys and human beings have tail bones monkeys and humans do not have a common ancestor). Pr(dolphins and sharks are shaped like torpedoes dolphins and sharks have a common ancestor) = Pr(dolphins and sharks are shaped like torpedoes dolphins and sharks do not have a common ancestor). In both the example about the student essays and the example about biological evolution, the law of likelihood explains why one similarity provides strong evidence that discriminates between the two hypotheses whereas the other similarity does not. The underlying principle is not about biology in particular or about student plagiarism in particular. The principle is very general, concerning how common cause and separate cause explanations are to be evaluated, regardless of their subject matters. We are now knee deep into philosophy. We have left the specifics of evolutionary biology and student plagiarism behind. But new problems now appear. The urn example makes the law of likelihood sound A CONFESSION «THE DAYS OF GRAND PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENCE ARE ON THE WANE» Let us return to the title question of this essay: is there such a thing as «the» scientific method, a method of reasoning that applies to all scientific subject matters? This is not a historical question about how scientists have actually reasoned, but a normative question about whether there are rules of reasoning that all scientists should follow. There is considerable controversy about this question in current philosophy of science, but now I can confess: I am a lumper. REFERENCES DARWIN, C., 1859. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. John Murray. London. (Facsimile, 1964. Harvard University Press. Cambridge, MA). DARWIN, C., 1959. The Origin of Species. A Variorum Edition. M. Peckham. University of Pennsylvania Press. Philadelphia. EINSTEIN, A., 1933. «On the Method of Theoretical Physics». Herbert Spencer Lecture. Oxford University Press. Oxford. HACKING, I., 1965. The Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge. SALMON, W., 1984. Scientifi c Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton University Press. Princeton. SOBER, E., 2012. Did Darwin Write the Origin Backwards? Prometheus Books. Amherst. New York. SOBER, E., 2015. Ockham s Razors A User s Manual. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge. Elliott Sober. Professor at the Department of Philosophy. University of Wisconsin-Madison (USA). MÈTODE 199