Soft Systems Methodology, Phenomenology and Information Systems Development: A Critical Analysis

Similar documents
Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Craig on the Experience of Tense

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

Naturalism and is Opponents

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

1/12. The A Paralogisms

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Phenomenology, Empiricism, and Science

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

5 A Modal Version of the

1/5. The Critique of Theology

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Philosophy of Consciousness

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Stephen K. Probert Cranfield University, United Kingdom. Abstract

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

An Epistemological Position: Knowledge by Sensation is the only Knowledge that can be regarded as Truth. Leon Reynolds

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Two Ways of Thinking

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Some questions about Adams conditionals

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Evidential arguments from evil

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Delton Lewis Scudder: Tennant's Philosophical Theology. New Haven: Yale University Press xiv, 278. $3.00.

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Transcription:

Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) AMCIS 2003 Proceedings Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) 12-31-2003 Soft Systems Methodology, Phenomenology and Information Systems Development: A Critical Analysis Stephen Probert Cranfield University Follow this and additional works at: http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2003 Recommended Citation Probert, Stephen, "Soft Systems Methodology, Phenomenology and Information Systems Development: A Critical Analysis" (2003). AMCIS 2003 Proceedings. Paper 375. http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2003/375 This material is brought to you by the Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) at AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). It has been accepted for inclusion in AMCIS 2003 Proceedings by an authorized administrator of AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). For more information, please contact elibrary@aisnet.org.

SOFT SYSTEMS METHODOLOGY, PHENOMENOLOGY AND INFORMATION SYSTEMS DEVELOPMENT: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS Stephen K. Probert Computing and Information Systems Management Group Cranfield University stephenprobert@aol.com Abstract Successful uses of information technologies usually require teams of developers working in concert (rather than individuals working alone); implying that methodological prescriptions for such developers should centre on issues such as communication and co-ordination. Here, it will be argued that the epistemology proffered by the SSM advocates does not provide a practical basis upon which to conduct team-based systems development; because the SSM advocates over-emphasise the need for subjective certainty and meaning, thus rendering their epistemology over-idealistic. It is concluded that the need for effective communication between team members necessarily implies abandoning the search for subjective certitude and supplanting it with the search for practical working knowledge of the actual situation in which IS development occurs. Keywords: Soft systems methodology, phenomenology, systems development, epistemology, meaning Phenomenological Ambitions Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) developed phenomenology, which supposedly provides the foundation of SSM s epistemology, Soft systems methodology implies... a model of social reality such as is found in the... (phenomenological) tradition deriving sociologically from Weber and philosophically from Husserl. (Checkland, 1981, p. 19). Consequently, the arguments put forward in this work will be based on Husserl s phenomenological works (Husserl, 1931, 1970, 1977 and 1990). Although it has been argued that many of Husserl s substantive arguments have been virtually ignored by the SSM advocates (Probert, 1998), certain traits of his key ideas do seem to map neatly to some of the key epistemological assumptions of the SSM advocates. This, it is argued, is no accident for (at the theoretical level) both Husserl and the SSM advocates have similar motives for adopting the positions that they hold. Ultimately, these motives relate to the real world conditions in which they have to operate. Essentially, what is intended herein by the phrase theoretical level is a body of doctrine not about how the world is, but about how statements about the world must be linguistically formulated. In the case of SSM, they must be formulated such that they do not violate the ontological assumptions made by subjective idealists. An examination of the reasoning behind the relevant aspects of the SSM advocates stated (epistemic) position is undertaken. This examination will be based on a critical analysis - in order to develop a critical interpretation using arguments that have been adopted (and modified slightly) from Adorno (1982). Essentially, the argument is that, Not least because it was reminiscent of psychology, did proud philosophy since Husserl reject psychology. Dread of psychology leads philosophy in quest of the residuum to sacrifice everything for which it exists. (Adorno, 1982, p. 16). A practically-oriented (critical) interpretation will be provided below to indicate the SSM advocates motivations for adopting the position that they hold; this will be characterised as the result of a perceived need to attain epistemic altitude (this concept will be explained). Further considerations concerning Husserl s search for certitude will inform the pragmatic recommendations, which will be discussed at this point. The practical conclusion drawn is that, whilst not attempting to sanction sloppy systems analysis, epistemic certitude is not attainable - therefore the demand for it can only be counter-productive when undertaking systems development 2872 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems

Probert/SSM, Phenomenology, and IS Development Epistemic Altitude Essentially, SSM advocates hold that statements about the real (i.e. objective) states of affairs in the social world are unwarranted and untenable. Consequently, discourse about mental states is elevated to a position of high (or higher) epistemic significance, whilst statements about the real world are denigrated as having a low - or even insignificant epistemic status (Checkland, 1991, 1992). It is precisely this elevation (of discourse about mental / ideal states of affairs) which constitutes the common ground between the SSM advocates and Husserl; this (generic) approach is criticised by Adorno for what he characterises as its imaginary altitude. Prima facie the (crude) positivists position is that sense-data puts us in immediate contact with external reality (although considerable variations on this theme can be found in the writings of the so-called positivists). At any rate, it is this (arguably a straw man ) version of positivist thought that both Husserl and the SSM advocates take umbrage at. The SSM advocates have often proffered the view that, as ideas, human activity systems have properties, characteristics, etc. which may be examined; whereas on the contrary human activity systems as real world occurrences are strictly-speaking unknowable and therefore they cannot be modelled. In this respect Husserl s ideas and those of the SSM advocates (subjective idealism) are strikingly similar. Adorno argues that the motivation for idealism is a ( theoretical ) belief that unless a thought (or a judgement) about some aspect of experience admits the possibility of being certain (whether true or false) then that thought is epistemologically worthless: The thesis of the perceptibility of the purely possible as a doctrine of essential insight, or as Husserl originally called it, categorial intuition, has become the motto of all philosophical approaches which evoke phenomenology. The fact that the new method should guarantee ideal states of affairs the same immediacy and infallibility as sense-data in the received [ positivist ] view, explains the influence which Husserl exercised over those who could no longer be satisfied with neo-kantian systems and yet were unwilling to blindly hand themselves over to irrationalism. (Adorno, 1982, p. 200 [emphases added]) The altitude supposedly gained by taking such a view (i.e. the idealism adhered to by both the SSM advocates and Husserl) is achieved by, as it were, rising above the real world into an ideal world (or worlds) in a search for greater epistemic security. Of course, the price to be paid is in the removal ( elevation ) of oneself from the real world within which one may be attempting to act. However, and in agreement with Adorno, it is not being suggested here that an alternative position of naïve positivism should be adopted: [C]ategorial intuition is the paradoxical apex of his [Husserl s] thought. It is the indifference into which the positivistic motif of intuitability and the rationalistic one of being-in-itself of ideal-states-of-affairs should be sublated. The movement of Husserlian thought could not tarry at this apex. Categorial intuition is no newly discovered principle of philosophizing. It proves to be a sheer dialectical moment of transition: imaginary altitude. (Adorno, 1982, p. 201) Similarly, it might be argued that the SSM advocates in fact hold the position that thought is not so detached from the real world as the above account would apply. Indeed, the SSM texts contain many references to an unfolding flux of ideas and events. However, it is also made clear in the various SSM texts (e.g. Checkland, 1981, 1991, 1992, Checkland and Scholes, 1990) that perceived events are for the SSM advocates - just (precisely) subjective perceptions of events. Adorno cogently distinguishes between epistemological accounts of experience given in terms of sense-data of and (ephemeral) encounters with the real world: In a certain way categorial intuition was devised by the doctrine of propositions in themselves If these are truly to be more than creations of thought, then they cannot really be products of thought but must simply be encountered by it. The paradoxical demand for a merely encountering thought arises from the claim to validity on the part of logical absolutism 1. The doctrine of categorial intuition is the result of this on the subject side. (Adorno, 1982, pp. 201-202). However, it should be noted that Husserl felt the compulsion to extend his idealism to cater for object-correlates of thought. Put bluntly, Husserl considered that if there are perceptions of objects then there must be real objects out there somewhere. As Adorno stresses: Only if categorial moments of meaning copy some objective-ideal being and correspond to it instead of just producing it, can objective-ideal be intuited in any sense at all. Thus Husserl is forced, in spite of his own 1 The term logical absolutism is introduced by Adorno to connote Husserl s general view of logical statements as being in no way dependent on events occurring in the real world for their truth-values; this is an important aspect of Husserl s conception of eidetic sciences. 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems 2873

Research Methods and Epistemology of IS critical discernment, to plead positively for the object correlates of categorial forms and thus for an intuition which fulfils them and is non-perceptible in principle, so that the fundamental thesis of propositions in themselves does not collapse. (Adorno, 1982, p. 204) It is concluded that, to date, the SSM advocates have not felt similarly compelled. Indeed, SSM advocates prima facie would hold that the world is constituted by and through subjective perceptions. Ostensibly, the reason for this position is epistemological rigour (i.e. what should more properly be understood as imaginary altitude). Subjective Certitude and Epistemological Rigour The question that must now be asked is: why should so much emphasis be placed on (the need for) subjective certitude in the SSM advocates formulations of the epistemological problems of systems analysis? The demand for subjective certitude inherent in the epistemology proffered by the SSM advocates would prima facie seem to generate immediate problems for the use of (soft) systems epistemology in practical endeavors. One might think that practical IS development work should, minimally, be more concerned with getting a practical working knowledge of a situation in order to take positive action rather than getting embroiled in epistemologically purist issues and concerns. Of course, to take this literally would be to proceed uncritically. In order to operate in a critically aware manner, epistemological considerations will be important but it will be argued here that epistemological purism is not the best way to proceed. Further discussion of an appropriate epistemological framework with which to undertake critical systems analysis lies outside the scope of this paper. Adorno s Structural Argument Now to return to the question raised above (why should so much emphasis be placed on the need for subjective certitude in the SSM advocates formulations of the epistemological problems of systems analysis?) According to Adorno, the answer is to be found in the actual circumstances in which academics find themselves, i.e. (what he calls) middlemen the social grouping that we might characterize today as the middle class. Interestingly, Adorno s argument would appear to hold a fortiori for the likes of SSM practitioners, consultants, etc. Adorno s argument can be applied as follows. The source of the subjective idealism - inherent in the SSM advocates epistemological accounts may be found in practice (i.e. experience) rather than in theory. The accounts of epistemology given in the SSM texts are supposedly based on (or supported by) the practical experiences of using systems ideas in organisations. In all such accounts (encountered by the author at any rate), the Soft Systems Practitioner does not claim to be the owner of the system. Indeed, the impression one gets is usually of the SSM practitioner being rather unceremoniously dumped into a conflictridden and potentially hostile social situation of which he or she has little prior knowledge and little power to control. Might this explain the perceived need for (or the motivation for seeking) certitude? Adorno makes the following comments about subjective idealists (in general) in the introduction to his Against Epistemology A Metacritique 2 : The open or secret pomp and the totally unobvious need for absolute spiritual security for why, indeed, should the playful luck of spirit be diminished by the risk of error? are the reflex to real powerlessness and insecurity. They are the self-deafening roar through positivity of those who neither contribute to the real reproduction of life nor actually participate in its real mastery. As middlemen, they only commend and sell to the master his means of lordship, spirit objectified into method [or methodology, for that matter] They use their subjectivity to subtract the subject from truth and their idea of objectivity is as a residue. (Adorno, 1982, p. 15) However, there is another aspect to the search for certitude; this is bound up with the desire to attribute meaning to one s experiences another central tenet of SSM. The search for certitude begins with Descartes in particular with his cogito ergo sum proposition. This is normally understood as I think therefore I am. although there are other interpretations, and Descartes himself used a variety of formulations of what has come to be known as the Cogito (Williams, 1978): 2 The title of this book is somewhat misleading, as in it - Adorno is conducting a critical analysis of subjective idealist epistemology as a (sort of) groundwork for an alternative epistemology, Criticizing epistemology also means retaining it. (Adorno, 1982, p. 27 [N.B. the three dots are included in the original text]). Some aspects of what such an alternative epistemology might look like are discussed in Guzzoni (1997). 2874 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems

Probert/SSM, Phenomenology, and IS Development [I]t is plausible to suspect, on the basis of the development of European philosophy from Descartes onward, that if we start with Cogito, we can reconstruct the world only as somehow correlated with subjectivity The converse relation is probably valid, too. If we start with the thing the categories applicable to it do not enable us to describe the irreducible subjectivity, this miracle of miracles (Husserl), this being-directed-towardoneself, this act of experiencing oneself It is very doubtful if anybody has succeeded in producing a language jointly encompassing these two viewpoints: one directed toward Cogito and the other directed toward things. 3 (Kolakowski, 1987, pp. 82-83) Ultimately, most modern-day systems development is a social activity, and it is groups who must ultimately conduct effective systems development in organisations, e.g. Griffiths and Probert (1998) point out the importance of teamwork in the development of Electronic Payment Systems. Groups imply a need for individuals to communicate, and communication implies a need for the interpretation of what is being said by others in the social settings that systems development takes place. However: [A] certitude mediated in words is no longer certitude. We gain or we imagine to have gained access to certitude only as far as we gain or imagine to have gained perfect identity with the object, an identity whose model is the mystical experience. This experience however is incommunicable; any attempt to hand it over to others destroys the very immediacy that was supposed to be its value consequently it destroys certitude. Whatever enters the field of human communication is inevitably uncertain, always questionable, fragile, provisory, and mortal. (Kolakowski, 1987, pp. 83-84 [emphases added]) Philosophically-speaking, other people s experiences are outside of our immediate subjective experience, therefore reports about them are essentially uncertain (for the recipient). Meaning-Attribution One final important point in the context of this discussion is that, ultimately, the drive for subjective certitude has strong religious or crypto-religious ( meaning-endowing ) overtones. It is, precisely because science - and, arguably, most other intellectual pursuits - have abandoned the search for absolute certitude in their methods (Popper, 1979, Quine and Ullian, 1978) that the search for certitude must direct itself (or take its cues ) from elsewhere as a consequence. One avenue open in this respect is that of (allegedly) pure or unmediated subjective experience: This search [for certitude] has little to do with the progress of science and technology. Its background is religious rather than intellectual; it is, as Husserl perfectly knew, a search for meaning. It is a desire to live in a world out of which contingency is banned, where sense (and this means purpose) is given to everything. Science is incapable of providing us with that kind of certitude, and it is unlikely that people could ever give up their attempts to go beyond scientific rationality. (Kolakowski, 1987, p. 84) However, the actual demands made upon systems development teams require that they proceed in an epistemologically uncertain manner. Conclusion So, to conclude, there are two plausible explanations for the drive for epistemic altitude: firstly, one that arises from the psychological insecurity engendered by the social situations in which most soft systems projects (and no doubt many systems development projects) take place. Secondly, the more general psychological effect that - despite the remarkable progress that some essentially uncertain enterprises, e.g. the physical sciences, have had - an unsatisfied demand for meaning in many practitioners subjective experiences persists 4. However, it need not follow that a desire to take purposeful action implies a search for some kind of ultimate and/or certain meaning to life. 3 This analysis provides us with an insight into the reasoning behind the proffered arguments that soft systems thinking is fundamentally different from hard systems thinking; however, this issue lies outside the scope of this paper. 4 Exactly why this is so is an interesting question, which lies outside the scope of this paper. 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems 2875

Research Methods and Epistemology of IS Also, it is concluded that whatever the motivations for desiring it epistemic certitude is not attainable, therefore the demand for it can only be counter-productive when undertaking systems development work. Our understanding of the real world in which systems development must take place may often be partial, confused and even bigoted. Essentially, critically-minded vigilance will provide some defence against the latter as will openness to the critical comments and suggestions of others. For the former the epistemological problems we had best learn to make do with whatever understanding of the problem situation can be obtained, given the time and resources available. This is not to sanction sloppy analysis! The alternative - only to sanction (unattainable) epistemological rigour - can only force us to withdraw our attention from the real world and into our (subjective) selves. Few practical problems are amenable to solution solely by introspection - although this is not to deny the value and importance of critical reflection. Moreover, the need for effective communication between systems development team members necessarily implies abandoning the search for subjective certitude and supplanting it with the search for practical working knowledge of the salient aspects of the actual situation in which IS development takes place. It is easy to imagine why IS practitioners (and particularly systems analysts) find themselves in positions of daunting epistemic insecurity. 5 Complex organisational structures, procedures, cultures, etc. - all have to be understood in a relatively short space of time if information technology is to be fruitfully exploited to provide real benefits for organisations. But the very complexity of the environment may well engender a (counter-productive) tendency to withdraw into an inner realm of subjective epistemic certainty. Practitioners need to resist this temptation. Of course there will always be technical aspects of the models to attend to, and here subjective rigour is both possible and desirable (notwithstanding the fact that attempting to be too rigorous can sometimes be unproductive). But the main point of this discussion is to argue that practitioners need to produce models of the actual situation (and understand that that is what they should be attempting to produce!) although these will almost certainly be poor (factually incorrect) models in the early stages of analysis. Although poor models can be refined, it will probably never be the case that they can be refined until they are 100% accurate (even if a model was 100% accurate we could probably never know it!). This is not the same a suggesting a return to naïve positivism, because the need in practical endeavours is not for the truth; the need is for an understanding (or even an interpretation) of the situation which is rationally defensible. Moreover, if the IS practitioners are working (sensibly) as a team, each model produced by the different practitioners will inevitably be only a part of the picture. Therefore, as Kowlakowski (1987) argues, any certainty about the models will be destroyed once they have been communicated to other members of the team. Consequently, all models built by teams are inherently (subjectively) uncertain and this is something which, as humans, we must simply endure. However, this need not lead to the abandonment of attempting to establish an understanding (or interpretation) of the actual situation. In practice, sensible project management will be needed to allow sufficient time for iterative modelling to be carried out relative to the needs of the IS development project. This, of course depends on the nature of the project, as some projects have rigid time constraints whilst others have looser time frames but a greater need for accuracy etc. References Adorno, T. W. Against Epistemology: A Metacritique, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982. Checkland, P. B. Systems Thinking, Systems Practice, Chichester: Wiley, 1981. Checkland, P. B. Towards the Coherent Expression of Systems Ideas, Journal of Applied Systems Analysis (18), 1991, pp. 25-28. Checkland, P. B. Systems and Scholarship: The Need to Do Better, Journal of the Operational Research Society, (43:11), 1992, pp. 1023-1030. Checkland, P. B. and Scholes, J. Soft Systems Methodology in Action, Chichester: Wiley, 1990. Griffiths D. M. and Probert, S. K. Development Methods for Electronic Payment Systems: The Need for Methodology Research, In Proceedings of the British Computer Society s Information Systems Methodologies Specialist Group, London: Springer-Verlag, 1998. Guzzoni, U. Reason A Different Reason Something Different Than Reason? Wondering about the Concept of a Different Reason in Adorno, Lyotard, and Sloterdijk, In M. Pensky (ed.), The Actuality of Adorno, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997. Husserl, E. Ideas, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1931. Husserl, E. Logical Investigations, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970. Husserl, E. Phenomenological Psychology, The HagueMartinus Nijhoff, 1977. Husserl, E. The Idea of Phenomenology, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990. Kolakowski, L. Husserl and the Search for Certitude (2nd. edition), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. Popper, K. R. Objective Knowledge (2nd. edition), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979. 5 As a practitioner once myself, I can clearly recall being in such situations. 2876 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems

Probert/SSM, Phenomenology, and IS Development Probert, S. K. Should Soft Systems Methodology be Taught to All Our Information Systems Students?, In Proceedings of the British Computer Society s Information Systems Methodologies Specialist Group, London: Springer-Verlag, 1998. Quine, W. V. and Ullian, J. S. The Web of Belief (2 nd. Edition), New York: Random House, 1978. Williams, B. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978. 2003 Ninth Americas Conference on Information Systems 2877