Improving Students' "Dialectic Tracking" Skills (Diagramming Complex Arguments) Cathal Woods for 2010 AAPT Meeting.

Similar documents
1/19/2011. Concept. Analysis

In a previous lecture, we used Aristotle s syllogisms to emphasize the

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

On Freeman s Argument Structure Approach

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Syllogism. Exam Importance Exam Importance. CAT Very Important IBPS/Bank PO Very Important. XAT Very Important BANK Clerk Very Important

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - HANDBOOK

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application A

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

LOGIC Lesson 10: Univocal, Equivocal, Analogical Terms. 1. A term in logic is the subject or the predicate of a proposition (a declarative sentence).

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Instructor s Manual 1

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Critical Thinking - Section 1

Introducing Our New Faculty

Cumulative Arguments and Smoking Guns. Mark Vorobej. Following David Ray Griffin, we can distinguish between the following three propositions

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

With prompting and support, identify the reasons an author gives to support points in a text.

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Argument Mapping. Table of Contents. By James Wallace Gray 2/13/2012

The linked-convergent distinction

National Quali cations

CHAPTER 9 DIAGRAMMING DEBATES. What You ll Learn in this Chapter

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

The Dialectical Tier of Mathematical Proof

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Dr. Carlo Alvaro Reasoning and Argumentation Distribution & Opposition DISTRIBUTION

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

1.2. What is said: propositions

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Chapter 1 Why Study Logic? Answers and Comments

Write three supporting reasons that would convince the reader to agree with your position (in order of importance).

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Artificial Intelligence Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Indian Philosophy Prof. Satya Sundar Sethy Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

A New Parameter for Maintaining Consistency in an Agent's Knowledge Base Using Truth Maintenance System

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

How to Generate a Thesis Statement if the Topic is Not Assigned.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

EBSCO Publishing. Student Success Tools

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 1 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 1

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Houghton Mifflin English 2001 Houghton Mifflin Company Grade Three Grade Five

Grade 7. correlated to the. Kentucky Middle School Core Content for Assessment, Reading and Writing Seventh Grade

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Introduction to Philosophy

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

Writing the Thesis Statement

6. Truth and Possible Worlds

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Test Item File. Full file at

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

Natural Deduction for Sentence Logic

Overview: Application: What to Avoid:

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Transcription:

Improving Students' "Dialectic Tracking" Skills (Diagramming Complex Arguments) Cathal Woods for 2010 AAPT Meeting. My e-mail: cathalwoods at gmail dot com. Contact for a copy of my logic book, or go to http://facultystaff.vwc.edu/~rwoods/methodsoflogic.htm Students and of read one sentence, perhaps one paragraph, at a time. By contrast, in philosophy courses we often mention the ability to "follow the dialectic" to keep track of claims, reasons, objections (and rebuttals to those objections) which might stretch over pages of text. We lack a systematic way of developing this skill in our students. In this session, I'll share an expanded system of diagramming and have you review graduated exercises in "dialectic tracking" which culminate in tackling newspaper editorials. I invite others to share their experiences and to help apply, expand and improve the exercises. You might think that critical reasoning or logic books and courses would cover this, but the treatments are very rudimentary. The basic options are standard form and diagrams. I'll focus on diagrams because standard form is useful only for short passages. In a diagram, numbers are given to the propositions involved, and arrows are used. Additionally, there can be a plus sign (+) and parentheses or braces. Text-books will usually cover these reasoning structures: single-premise, single-conclusion multiple-premise, single conclusion extended arguments

Among multiple-premise arguments, a distinction is made between dependent and independent premises. Note: there are various other names. And part of the reason that there are different names is that the concepts are confused. The confusion is between Premises working together to give their (possibly non-sufficient) support to the conclusion (or: lends some support) And Premises working together to give the (i.e. sufficient) support to the conclusion (or: are the support) In short: does the arrow mean "supports" or "therefore"? Examples of simple deductive arguments (e.g. AA, CC and DS) are often used to illustrate dependent premises. In such cases, the premises are dependent and sufficient. Such an argument is diagrammed with a single arrow and a plus-sign. I have no problem with this, except that it suggests that the dependent premises will be specific and general, whereas two pieces of specific information might be dependent. Also, for reasons that will become apparent, I additionally use parentheses, as follows, to indicate a single line of support: (1 + 2) 3 Then, in contrast, an argument with a number of lines of support is given. E.g. reasons to buy a dog. Such an argument is diagrammed with a number of arrows, each pointing at the conclusion. This is a mistake. I have two objections (really two versions of the same thing): 1. There is only one argument, and so only one arrow. However, it's often true that the speaker is simply piling on reasons and so, that a subset of the reasons will be sufficient.

2. If we are to diagram passages with objections and rebuttals, we cannot have these multiple arrows. Here's why: objections are either to the truth of the premises or to the strength of the inference (btw: no existing text has a diagramming system that allows this difference to be diagrammed) but, in a multiple reasons argument, how could we diagram an objection to the inference which says, "these reasons, together, do not make the conclusion likely"? Consider a cluster of premises (5-9) which support proposition (2). Imagine an objection to the effect that, even granting the truth of all of these, (2) does not securely follow. At what would we point the challenging arrow? We can't neatly draw it against all of (5) through (9). 9 8 7 6 5 2 I solve this problem by allowing an objection-arrow to point either at the number representing the premise, or the arrow from premise to conclusion. [An alternative (hinted at by Epstein) is to demand a connecting premise. The purpose of this premise is to clarify which premise(s) are sufficient. This makes us lazy.] Positive proposal: use a split-tailed arrow. This allows for challenges to the truth of any premise, the support from any premise, and the overall support. Each of the (multiple) tails of the arrow means "support"; the (single) head of the arrow mean "justifies". Direction of Arrows A final suggestion is one of design.

Those who allow for objections and rebuttals employ arrows of a different type, but pointing in the same direction as the arrow standing for the initial argument. All of Epstein, Kelley and Moore & Parker use an arrow with horizontal marks through them (which I'll call "hash-arrows") to represent a counterargument, while Johnson & Blair use dashed arrows. The premises which support the counterargument are given regular arrows, and the counterarguments to those get hash-arrows. Here's an example (Epstein p. 363) (using dashed arrows instead of hash-arrows): 11 12 9 8 7 6 5 4 10 3 + 2 1 Two possible confusions (two versions of the same thing): The supports for the objections have regular arrows. E.g. 11 to 10 looks the same as 3 to 1, even though 11 is indirectly contrary to 1. (Austhink "Note that the reason here helps the objection, not the main contention. It provides evidence that the objection is a good one." http://austhink.com/reason/tutorials/tutorial_4/2_reason_objection/reason_objectio n.htm ) Similarly, objections to objections look identical to objections, even though the former are indirectly supporting the main conclusion. E.g. 12 to 10 looks like 10 to 1, even though it is indirectly supporting 1. We can respond to this issue by getting rid of the hash-arrow/dashed-arrow and using up-arrows for the objections, and their supports. Here's an example from a different argument. (8) is denying the truth of (7); (9) is pushing down against (8)'s attack on (7.)

(5 + 6) 7 9 1 8 The role of the arrow in the overall argument is immediately clear, but determining whether an arrow supports or challenges what it points at is now more complicated, as it depends on the direction of the other arrow involved. For example, an objection to an objection will point downwards, in the same direction as the original supporting premises. The hash-arrow method tells us the reverse: it tell us immediately whether a proposition is supporting or challenging what it points at, but the role of the support or challenge in the overall argument has to be worked out in relation to the chain of arrows back to the conclusion.