Language, reference and representation

Similar documents
Putnam: Meaning and Reference

WHY WE NEED A-INTENSIONS

NARROW CONTENT AND REPRESENTATION or TWIN EARTH REVISITED * Frank Jackson. Intentional states represent. Belief represents how we take things to be;

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988.

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03

In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1. Frank Jackson

Natural Kinds: (Thick) Essentialism or Promiscuous Realism?

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Varieties of Apriority

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

ON CONSIDERING A POSSIBLE WORLD AS ACTUAL. by Robert Stalnaker and Thomas Baldwin. II Thomas Baldwin

Contextual two-dimensionalism

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Scott Soames Two-Dimensionalism

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Classical Theory of Concepts

Glossary (for Constructing the World)

Constructing the World

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

Realism and instrumentalism

INTRODUCTION THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Constructing the World

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Two-Dimensionalism and Kripkean A Posteriori Necessity

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. Against Descriptivism

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

In Meaning and Truth, J. Campbell, M. O Rourke, and D. Shier, eds. (New York: Seven Bridges Press, 2001):

Direct and Indirect Belief

Act individuation and basic acts

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 73, No. 1; March 1995

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by

Naming Natural Kinds. Åsa Maria Wikforss Stockholm University Department of Philosophy Stockholm

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

What is knowledge? How do good beliefs get made?

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Week Eleven: Objections to Jackson 1. The Objection From Linguistic Ignorance

Informalizing Formal Logic

APRIORISM IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

Analyticity and reference determiners

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

REALISM AND REASON* HILARY PUTNAM

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

IN SEARCH OF DIRECT REALISM

CONTENT INSIDE OUT. Joseph Mendola s Anti-Externalism 1 defends internalism,

A Defense of the Kripkean Account of Logical Truth in First-Order Modal Logic

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

A Posteriori Necessities

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

Coordination Problems

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 2

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 1

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Transcription:

Language, reference and representation First of four seminars at CUHK on some issues arising from the Kripke-Putnam revolution in the philosophy of mind and language March 2006 Special thanks to: Philosophy at CUHK, Professor Kwan Tze Wan and Professor Cheung Chan Fai, and to Wong Kai Yee.

Background Saul Kripke's attack on the description theory of reference (DTR) for names, in Naming and Necessity. Hilary Putnam's argument that names for natural kinds don't go by superficial properties and that meanings are not in the head, in 'The Meaning of "Meaning"'. 2

Kripke's three main arguments The view Kripke was attacking: a name 'N' refers to x, as a matter of the name's meaning, to that which has the descriptions or properties associated with 'N'. Modal argument against the description theory of reference (DTR) Epistemic argument against the DTR Error and ignorance argument against the DTR. 3

Modal argument If 'N' means 'the D', then 'N might not have been the D' would be a nonsense, and it manifestly isn't for more or less any choice of D. The are two standard replies, one in terms of scope and one in terms of rigidification. The scope reply points out that 'The D might not have been the D' makes perfect sense indeed it is often true ('The tallest woman might not have been the tallest') but 'the D' does mean the same as 'the D'. 4

Scope for DDs 'The D might have been F' can be read as affirming that the proposition that the D is F is possible, i.e. that there is a possible world where 'The D is F ' is true, or as affirming that the D is such that it might have been F The second gives the DD wide scope with respect to the possibility operator. Some defenders of the DTR for names hold that names are DDs that take wide scope with respect to possibility operators and handle Kripke's modal argument that way. 5

Rigidified definite descriptions 'The D' refers to the unique D at every possible world W if such there be. 'The actual D' refers at every world W to the unique D at the actual world if such there be and if it appears in W. The reply to Kripke is then that i) names are rigidified descriptions, and ii) 'The actual D is not (the) D' is in general true at some worlds. the actual D in W the D in W A W A = W the D in W 6

Scope versus rigidity as replies to Kripke Scope sticks with the claim that names are DDs but adds the proviso that they are DDs that take wide scope in certain modal contexts. Rigifidification concedes that names are not ordinary DDs but holds that they are rigidified DDs instead or descriptive names. I favour the second reply as we'll see. 7

Kripke's epistemic argument against the DTR for names For every candidate to be 'the D' in some account of name N, we might discover (it might turn out) that N is not D. It might e.g. turn out that Gödel did not prove Gödel's theorem. Scope doesn't help here: it is false that it might turn out that the D is not the D. Equally rigidity doesn't help: the actual D could not have turned out not to be the D. Defenders of DTR must deny Kripke's datum. They must insist that for each N, there is a D such that it could not have turned out that N is not D. 8

The argument from error and ignorance There are clear cases where 'N' refers in someone's mouth or from their pen and yet they do not know a distinguishing feature of that which is being referred to. Putnam e.g. claimed that he didn't know the difference between elms and beeches; all the same, 'elm' and 'beech' referred (to different things) in his mouth and from his pen. Standard reply. Putnam did know the difference. He knew that beeches are called 'beeches' by experts whereas elms are called 'elms'. Mutatis mutandis for all alleged examples. 9

Putnam and natural kind terms Putnam argues that although natural kind terms like 'water' and 'gold' are introduced via 'folk markers' (not Putnam's term), they name the kind that the items mainly belong to (especially on the occasions when we name the kind) rather than whatever falls under the markers. This means that a sample of water i) need not satisfy any of the usual markers as long as it is of the right kind, and ii) that 'fools' water and fools gold is possible stuff that has the markers but isn't water or gold. This is widely agreed. 10

Putnam's point in a diagram 'water' is of same kind sample that is 'watery' water sample that is not watery but is of the same kind stuff that is watery but not the same kind not water 11

Putnam's Twin Earth It also implies, argued Putnam, that meanings aren't in the head, using his Twin Earth example. This claim was originally one about linguistic meaning but was extended by Tyler Burge and others (in ways Putnam broadly endorsed) to a conclusion about mental content to the effect that what subjects' believe is a function of their environment as well as how their heads are. Doppelgangers can believe differently if their environments differ in certain ways. This both the part about meaning and the part about mental content is the more controversial claim (although it is widely accepted nowadays). We'll (I'll) be denying it though. 12

Putnam's remote place version of Twin Earth H 2 O is mostly watery Earth XYZ is watery; XYZ H 2 O; H 2 O is tarry Twin Earth 'water' Jackson on Earth 'water' Twin Jackson Prime intuition: 'water' in Jackson's mouth names H 2 O whereas in Twin Jackson's it names XYZ. Putnam's conclusion is that the reference of 'water' doesn't go by what's in their heads. The environment plays a role. 13

End of background! 14

The recalcitrants' charter The reference of proper names does go by associated descriptions and what we learn from Kripke and Putnam are important facts about the associated descriptions, about centering, and about rigidity. When these lessons are digested we see that some arguments for externalism fail, including Twin Earth. Actually we (I) doubt that any arguments for externalism succeed but that's another story. 15

What's to come Search and destroy versus starting from basics A guiding idea and how it impacts on much current theorising about mind and language The representationalist approach to language Finding the right representation relation The connection with truth Three issues about reference distinguished The core claim of the description theory for names 16

Ramsey's Idea belief is 'a map of neighbouring space by which we steer' (F.P. Ramsey, The Foundations of Mathematics, London: Kegan Paul, 1931) better: a sentence is a map by which we steer sentences and maps differ from beliefs in being shared public structures that are given one or another interpretation. 17

Labouring the obvious two ways to find the body 'The body is in the lounge, past three studies on the right and the seminar room on the left'. 18

What's needed for good steering using sentences? sentences need to provide information about how things are this requires a known function from sentences to ways things might be, just as there are known functions from photos to ways things might be 'Boy at computer' 19

How should we think about the provision of putative information about how things are We shouldn't get bluffed by H.P. Grice's troubles into denying what must be the case. What kind of thing is the value of the relevant function from sentences? 20

Representation and possibility I The value of the function from sentences to ways things might be is the putative information provided by the sentence, and in representing that we need to capture the fact that the information is about the world, not concepts or words the fact that the information is silent about a lot. The possible worlds treatment of (representational) content of sentences delivers both to us. 21

Representation and possibility II representational content meaning. The shape below is the shape 'is an equiangular triangle' and 'is an equilateral triangle' alike represent something as having; hence there's one content but the predicates differ in meaning. Similar point applies to x's being taller than y versus y's being shorter than x, and being half empty versus being half full. 22

Representation and possibility III the 'God' way of thinking about content. Sometimes express materialism about the mind by saying that all God has to do to make a conscious minded creature is to assemble aright purely physical ingredients. God way of thinking of content is in terms of what God would have to do to make some sentence (or thought) true. God would not have to do two things to make something half empty and half full. 23

The possible worlds scheme S ways things might be that are as S represents them to be If S is an egocentric sentence (or thought), the circle is the set of centred worlds whose centres in those worlds are as S represents them to be 24

Representing representation Slogan: represent representational content by pretending to be Lewisian modal realists. This is externalist in one good sense. S 25

Finding the right representation relation for language I We sometimes speak as if there was one answer as to what some structure represents: the number of tree rings represents age of a tree; a petrol gauge represents how much fuel is in the tank; photos represent what they are photos of; etc. But in fact there is no one answer. Rather, there are indefinitely many representation relations and we need to think in terms of what some structure represents relative to so and so a relation. 26

Finding the right representation relation for language II A gauge can equally be thought of as representing how much fuel is left, the state of wire from the tank to the gauge, how far the car can travel without a refill, etc. Just we learnt years ago when discussing how to count objects, that the number of objects is relative to a count sortal (one book but 300 hundred pages; one table, five table parts, etc) so representation is relative to a mapping. Of course we don't always need to make the relativity explicit in either case. 27

Basic framework The pattern our simple examples exemplify: mappings from ways things might be to ways things might be: {S i } M j >{T k } Easy-going in the sense that any function from ways to ways counts as a case of representation; we then divide cases we wish to discuss from junk. Analogy with Quine s easy-going attitude to objects. S 1 S 2.. S n T n M j 28

Correctness Correctness relative to a mapping S i represents correctly relative to M j iff a) M j maps S i into T k, and b)t k obtains. S i M j W A T k obtains iff the circle contains the actual world W A 29

How it looks for belief, desire and perception Belief, desire and perception are all representational states: they represent how a subject takes, wants, perceives things to be, respectively. What it takes for a belief to be true The (neural) state belief-maps onto a state of affairs that obtains What it takes for a desire to be satisfied The (neural) state desire-maps onto a state of affairs that obtains What it takes for a perception to be veridical The (neural) state perception-maps onto a state of affairs that obtains 30