Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Similar documents
Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Compresence is a Bundle A Problem for the Bundle Theory of Objects

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

5 The necessary and the possible

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

Are All Universals Instantiated?

The Relation of Compresence in the Bundle Theory: Four Problems

ISSN , Volume 73, Number 1

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Constructing the World

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

PRESENTISM AND PERSISTENCE

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity Robert Merrihew Adams

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

Bare Particulars. Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006),

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Constructing the World

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Metaphysics. A contemporary introduction. Michael J. Loux. Third edition

The Relationist and Substantivalist Theories of Time: Foes or Friends?

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Aboutness and Justification

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Nathan Oaklander IS THERE A DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SPACE?

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Constructing the World

The Big Schema of Things:

Moore on External Relations

The argument from almost indiscernibles

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Analyticity and reference determiners

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Tom Vinci. Dalhousie University

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

5 A Modal Version of the

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

A flaw in Kripke s modal argument? Kripke states his modal argument against the description theory of names at a number

Is There Immediate Justification?

Skepticism and Internalism

Presentism and eterrnalism HAROLD W. NOONAN. Department of Philosophy. University of Nottingham. Nottingham, NG72RD, UK. Tel: +44 (0)

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Fred Wilson UNIVERSALS, PARTICULARS, TROPES AND BLOBS

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

A Rate of Passage. Tim Maudlin

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Replies to Glick, Hanks, and Magidor

Presentism, roughly, is the thesis that only the present is real. The opposite view is

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview Administrative Stuff Philosophy Colloquium today (4pm in Howison Library) Context Jerry Fodor, Rutgers University Clarificatory questions on study questions or papers topics? Agenda: Concrete Particulars (Cont d) The Bundle Theory Motivation Objection #1: Subject-predicate discourse Objection #2: The Identity of Indiscernibles The Substratum Theory Motivation Some problems An Alternative Account: Aristotelian substances

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 Concrete Particulars VI: Background on Bundle Theory Bundle theorists agree with substratum theorists in denying that the concrete objects of everyday experience are ontologically basic or fundamental. According to Bundle Theory, a concrete particular is just a bundle, a cluster, a collection, or a congeries of the empirically manifest attributes that common sense associates with it. No mysterious bare substrata. The glue that binds bundles is a primitive relation called compresence, collocation, combination, consubstantiation, or coactuality. This primitive relation is explained informally as the relation of occurring together. According to bundle theorists, there are really only attributes, properties, or tropes. What we call particulars are mere constructions out of these. Different attributes entail different bundles, so where we have change we have numerically different bundles and, hence, numerically different objects. As Loux points out, this is also a problem for substratum theory general problem: changes in constituents lead to changes in wholes. Study Question.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 Concrete Particulars VII: Objection #1 to Bundle Theory We make all kinds of nonequivalent claims about concrete particulars. For instance, Sam is red, Sam is spherical, Sam is 2 inches in diameter, etc. Challenge from substratum theorist: Answer the following 2 questions: What is the thing Sam to which an attribute is being said to be related? A1: Just the bundle of attributes that is the thing we ve dubbed Sam. But, then don t these claims come out tautologous (true by logic)? However, we can use the name Sam to denote a bundle without knowing all of its constituents. So, claims can still be informative. A2: The bundle of attributes Sam sans the attribute in question. Now, no two nonequivalent statements are about the same thing. What relationship is being said to obtain between the two? The relation of constituent to whole. This is just like set membership. But, like sets, bundles cannot change their membership, so they have their attributes necessarily. Key difference between substratum & bundle theories.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 Why does Loux (Van Cleve) say that bundle theory implies particulars have their attributes necessarily? Parallels the claim that trope theory implies there could not have been more or fewer courageous people than there in fact are. This also seems like an undesirable consequence, since it seems that (for instance) I could have been taller than I in fact am. But, on this reading of bundle theory, no particular could have had any attributes other than those it in fact has. Is there a way for the bundle theorist to avoid this consequence? In the case of trope theory, I suggested that the definite description the set of courage tropes is like the number of planets or the set of courageous people, which may refer to different sets in different worlds or situations. This seemed plausible for trope theory s account of abstract singular terms. Will a parallel move work for bundle theory s account of proper names? It s not so clear. Bundle theory says that Branden denotes a set of compresent attributes. We could try to Quine/Russellize here: the set of compresent attributes that is-branden. Is this description like the number of planets? Maybe. But, this time the question is trickier, owing to thorny questions about personal identity, and identity conditions for particulars, generally. To wit...

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 Concrete Particulars VIII: Objection #2 to Bundle Theory 1 The 2nd objection is an argument involving the following three principles: (II) Necessarily, for any concrete objects, a and b, if for any attribute, φ, φ is an attribute of a iff φ is an attribute of b, then a is numerically identical with b. (II) says that complete qualitative indiscernibility (agreement with respect to all attributes) entails numerical identity. Its converse seems trivial. Why? (PCI) Necessarily, for any complex objects, a and b, if for any entity, c, c is a constituent of a iff c is a constituent of b, then a is numerically identical w/ b. (PCI) is accepted both by substratum theorists and by bundle theorists. It says that agreement with respect to all constituents entails identity. As was the case with (II), the converse of this claim (which is a distinct claim) seems trivial. (BT) Necessarily, for any concrete entity, a, if for any entity, b, b is a constituent of a, then b is an attribute. [this should be an iff, I think, see below] (BT) is basic for bundle theory: only attributes are constituents of particulars.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 The argument of objection #2 (from simplified versions of the 3 principles): (II) Agreement on all attributes entails identity. (PCI) Agreement on all constituents entails identity. (BT) The attributes a thing has are all and only (!) the constituents it has. Step 1: (PCI) + (BT) entails (II). [Easy.] Step 2: (II) is false. [Not so easy. This is where the real controversy is.] Step 3: Since (PCI) is uncontroversial, (BT) is false. [Easy.] Step 4: Since bundle theory entails (BT), bundle theory is false. [Easy.] NOTE: This argument only applies to the realist s (BT). A trope theorist will either accept (PCI) and (II) in vacuous forms (with no consequences for their theory), or they will deny them. No two objects can share any tropes (viz., constituents). Agreement is merely similarity between tropes. But that s not agreement in a sense strong enough to imply a non-vacuous (II). So, (II) may follow from (BT) and (PCI), but only vacuously for a trope theorist. There are no compelling trope counterexamples to (II)! The difficult step here is step 2. What are the counterexamples to (II)?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Concrete Particulars IX: Objection #2 to Bundle Theory 2 Loux (Black) considers a pair of spheres (a and b) with the same shape, color, mass, texture, size, etc. As he puts it they are so similar that no one can tell the difference between them. Could this be a counterexample to (II)? What about the properties A = being identical with a, and B = being identical with b. Don t a and b fail to share these properties? (Aa, not Aa, not Ba, Bb) Loux argues that the bundle theorist is not allowed to appeal to such properties, since they are reductionists about particulars, and such properties presuppose an irreducible notion of a particular: one that cannot be be understood as a mere bundle of attributes. Such properties are impure. This leads Loux to formulate a revised version of (BT). (BT*) Necessarily, for any concrete entity, a, if for any entity, b, b is a constituent of a, then b is a pure property/attribute. (BT*) and (PCI) entail something stronger than (II) (w/only pure properties).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 (II*) Necessarily, for any concrete objects, a and b, if for any pure property/attribute, φ, φ is an attribute of a iff φ is an attribute of b, then a is numerically identical with b. And, it seems, this provides an argument against bundle theory that cannot be escaped by appealing to properties like A and B which are patently impure. But, it is impossible for two different concrete objects to occupy the same region of space at a given time. So, no two concrete objects will agree with respect to those properties that specify their spatiotemporal location either. In a rebuttal on behalf of the substratum theorist, Loux says:... these properties are one and all impure. [the substratum theorist] will argue that since space and time represent relational structures, the properties that specify the spatiotemporal position of concrete objects are always properties like being 2 miles north of the Eiffel Tower properties that already presuppose or involve concrete particulars and so cannot number among the items the bundle theorist construes as constituents of concrete objects. What do you think about this move? Are such properties impure? See Casullo.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 Concrete Particulars X: An Argument for Substratum Theory Many people view the above argument [from not (II*) and (PCI) to not (BT*)] as a refutation of the metaphysical realist version of bundle theory [(BT*)]. Thinking more deeply bout these conditions leads, according to Loux, to a persuasive positive argument in favor of substratum theory. If (II*) is false, then there will be distinct particulars which (nonetheless) share all pure properties. For instance, think about our spheres a and b. a and b will share all pure properties. And, their impure properties are not useful for determining their constituents. As Loux says:... since our aim is to identify the constituents out of which concrete particulars are composed, the items we appeal to... cannot already presuppose the complex entities that are concrete particulars, and impure properties all do. No... impure... properties can explain the [nonidentity] of [a and b]. But, since (PCI) is true, and a b, there must be some constituent they do not share, which is not determined by any attributes a or b has bare substrata!

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Concrete Particulars XI: Problems for Substratum Theory 1 We already hinted at one objection to substratum theory: the epistemology of bare substrata. How can we be acquainted with or know about bare substrata? Interestingly, many bare substratum theorists (e.g., Locke, Bergmann) have been self-identifying empiricists! They have various replies to this worry: To be acquainted with numerically diverse, yet qualitatively indiscernible objects is eo ipso to be acquainted with bare substrata. Being confronted with a pair of objects related as Black s two red balls, a and b, are, we are in a perceptual context where the principles of numerical diversity in them make themselves apparent to us. Since the attribute and subject are correlative concepts, it is impossible to be acquainted with an attribute without being acquainted with its subject. If attributes can be the objects of empirical awareness, so can the substrata that literally possess them. This sounds question-begging and disingenuous. The bare substratum was not motivated on epistemic, but conceptual grounds. That should be their reply.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 Concrete Particulars XII: Problems for Substratum Theory 2 Is the substratum theory even coherent? It seems to be saying: things that possess attributes are bare. But to be bare is to possess no attribute. So, are we to infer that things which possess attributes possess no attributes? There is an ambiguity in possess. To be fair, what the substratum theory is saying is that bare substrata (hence, particulars) do not possess any of their attributes necessarily All particulars have all their attributes contingently. In other words, the view is that none of the attributes of a substratum are essential to the substratum. None are constitutive of it (or of its identity). Note: This makes it clear that bundle theory (on Loux s reconstruction) and substratum theory are diametrically opposed on the question Which attributes do particulars have necessarily? BT: all; ST: none. We have already seen that it s pretty crazy to claim that particulars have all their attributes necessarily. It s also pretty weird (naively) to say they have none of their attributes necessarily. At this point, Loux rightly speculates:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 We are told, for example, that bare substrata have no attributes essentially; but what of this feature of bare substrata? Is it one that is merely contingently true of bare substrata? Likewise, bare substrata are said to be the literal bearers of attributes. Is this a merely contingent feature of bare substrata? Is it possible that things could be otherwise, so that not they, but some other entities played this role? Again, bare substrata are said to be the principles of numerical diversity. Might they have failed to diversify objects?... There seem to be properties that are essential to everything. E.g., the property of being self-identical, the property of being red or not red, or colored if red. There also seem to be properties that are essential to some things but not others. E.g., the property of not being identical to the number 7, the property of being red or non-red, or (perhaps) the property of being a human being. So, it seems, if there are substrata, they will have some attributes necessarily. But, if that is so, then we seem to be off on a regress. The substratum theorist now needs a new (finer-grained) substratum to serve as the literal bearer of these (essential) attributes. But, they will have some essential features...

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 Concrete Particulars XIII: Aristotelian Substance 1 It seems we re faced with a choice between extremes. We can choose a theory which says that all attributes of all particulars are contingent (substratum), or we can choose a theory which says that all attributes of all particulars are necessary (bundle). a This seems to leave us with only two options: Go for Austere Nominalism, and deny that particulars are complexes. Or, go for a trope-theoretic bundle theory (at least avoids (II)-argument). But, of course, this is a false dichotomy, since All X s are Y s and No X s are Y s do not exhaust the logically possible cases. A common-sensical view might be that some attributes of particulars are necessary and some are not. Or, as Loux puts it, one make take concrete particulars themselves, or at least some among them, to be basic or irreducibly fundamental entities. This is an Aristotelian ( mean ) view about substance, and our last theory of particulars. a Loux s second horn: a theory accepting (II), rather than a theory making all attributes necessary. Puzzle: why doesn t Loux state the dilemma in the obvious way here? Why retreat to (II)? Study Q.