In Defense of Truth functional Theory of Indicative Conditionals. Ching Hui Su Postdoctoral Fellow Institution of European and American Studies,

Similar documents
Pragmatic Presupposition

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

The main plank of Professor Simons thoroughly pragmatic account of presupposition

Conditionals IV: Is Modus Ponens Valid?

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

The paradox we re discussing today is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Here s an example of this sort of argument:!

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Denying the antecedent and conditional perfection again

The paradox we re discussing today is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Here are some examples of this sort of argument:

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Lying and Asserting. Andreas Stokke CSMN, University of Oslo. March forthcoming in the Journal of Philosophy

Cognitivism about imperatives

Conditionals, Predicates and Probability

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Comments on "Lying with Conditionals" by Roy Sorensen

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

The myth of the categorical counterfactual

Pragmatic Considerations in the Interpretation of Denying the Antecedent

CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND CONDITIONAL ASSERTIONS

Vagueness and supervaluations

Responses to the sorites paradox

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency

Lexical Alternatives as a Source of Pragmatic Presuppositions

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Horwich and the Liar

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Mandy Simons Carnegie Mellon University June 2010

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Superlative quantifiers and meta-speech acts

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

Moore on External Relations

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Might Counterfactuals

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

Tutorial A02: Validity and Soundness By: Jonathan Chan

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

LGCS 199DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Acting without reasons

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

(Some More) Vagueness

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

the negative reason existential fallacy

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

This is an electronic version of a paper Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: , 2014.

On Conceivability and Existence in Linguistic Interpretation

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

Lying and Knowing. Ben Holguín. September Abstract

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

What is a counterexample?

Chapter 2. A Little Logic

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

Embedded Attitudes *

Can the lottery paradox be solved by identifying epistemic justification with epistemic permissibility? Benjamin Kiesewetter

Is justification knowledge? University of Notre Dame Australia

DISCUSSION NOTES A RESOLUTION OF A PARADOX OF PROMISING WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Linguistic Society of America

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Instrumental Normativity: In Defense of the Transmission Principle Benjamin Kiesewetter

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

Warrant and accidentally true belief

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

A presupposition is a precondition of a sentence such that the sentences cannot be

The projection problem of presuppositions

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

INFERENCES LING106 KNOWLEDGE OF MEANING DOROTHY AHN SECTION 2 [2/12/2016]

Reply to Pryor. Juan Comesaña

CLASSIC INVARIANTISM, RELEVANCE, AND WARRANTED ASSERTABILITY MANŒUVERS

Speaking of Knowing PATRICK RYSIEW 1. INTRODUCTION

Lecturer: Xavier Parent. Imperative logic and its problems. by Joerg Hansen. Imperative logic and its problems 1 / 16

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Non-Catastrophic Presupposition Failure 1

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Transcription:

In Defense of Truth functional Theory of Indicative Conditionals Ching Hui Su Postdoctoral Fellow Institution of European and American Studies, Academia Sinica, Taiwan SELLC 2010

Outline Truth functional account Counterexamples Semantic approach Non truth functional account No truth value account Pragmatic approach Three steps analysis Conclusion

Truth functional account A common treatment of if in many textbooks of logic is to take if as truth functional: A i di i di i l if A C i if d An indicative conditional if A, C is true, if and only if, it is not the case that A is true and C is false.

Counterexamples (1) If the sun disappears, everything will go as usual. (2a) If New York is in New Zealand, it is not the case that 2 + 2 = 4. (2b) If the weather is good, 2 + 2 = 4.

Semantic approach To accommodate those counterexamples, we should not take if as truth functional. Stalnaker proposed a possible world semantic of if : If A, C is true at w, if and only if, C is true at the closest A world. V(α > β, w) = T iff V(β, s(α, w)) = T Adams proposed a probabilistic account of if : the assertibility condition of (the degree of belief) of if A, C is the probability of C given A. A(if A, C) = b(if A, C) = p(c/a)

Explain counterexamples (1) and d(2 (2a) will be false, for a world where the Sun disappears is not a world where everything goes on as usual and dthat t2 + 2 = 4i is true in all possible worlds. The probability of (1) is low, for the conditional probability of that everything will go on as usual given that the sun disappears is low. As to (2a), since the probability of that New York is in New Zealand is 0, the probability bilit of (2a)is undefined. d Thus, we shouldn t take (2a) as true.

Unrelatedness problem (2b) If the weather is good, 2 + 2 = 4. Intuitively, (2b) is odd, whether the weather is good or not. Neither Stalnaker nor Adams can explain (2b) away, for 2 + 2 = 4 is true in all possible worlds and the probability of 2 + 2 = 4 is 1. Grice s theory of implicature can help them escape the unrelatedness problem.

Pragmatic approach Three steps analysis: First: To check the relationship between the antecedent and consequent. Second: To check whether we conflate truth with acceptance. Third: To check whether the conditional in question is involved in reasoning. The idea is that something other than if may affect our attitudes toward conditionals.

First step to check the relationship between the antecedent and consequent ϕ entails ψ =df. Necessarily, if ϕ is true, ψ is true. ϕ presupposes ψ =df. ψ will be true, even though not ϕ and possibly ϕ. ϕ conversationally implicates ψ =df. the audience can derive ψ from ϕ and some cooperative principles and conversational maxims. Besides, ψ is cancellable in the following conversation. ϕ conventionally implicates ψ =df. ϕ literally means that ψ.

Second step to check whether we conflate truth with acceptance In most cases, truth will conflate with acceptance, for people are apt to accept truth and reject falsity, and I call this phenomena epistemic requirement. However, some examples show that a conflict between truth and acceptance may arise, for epistemic requirement is not always fulfilled. On the one hand, under certain situations, given all the evidence we have, we may have knowledge by luck, which is demonstrated by Gettier s famous paper Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? On the other hand, in history of science we can find lots of instances of justified false beliefs. In this case, people accept falsity.

In my opinion, i we can learn a lesson from history, for acceptance doesn t mean truth. Here I think we can find out a criterion, i which h helps us in distinguishing truth from acceptance; that is, changing with time or not. As history taught us, based on all evidence available at a certain moment, we may accept a certain claim at that moment, for our acceptance is established on our evidence had at a time. In other words, acceptance goes by evidence at t.

Third step to check whether the conditional in question is involved in reasoning In classical llogic, a way to determine whether h an argument is valid or not is to conjoin all its premises and use to connect tits conclusion. By doing so, we have a conditional in structure, once we treat if as. Then, if the conditional is true, the argument is valid; if not, invalid. In my opinion, this strategy will mislead people, and make them confuse conditionals with logical consequences, for it conflates conditionals with the notion of logical consequence.

Thus, a problem of failing to catch our intuition i i of reasoning becomes a problem of conditionals. I agree that truth preserving doesn t always stand for a good feature of reasoning, for we won t think that all instances of paradoxes of material implication are good. Thus, what we need to do here is either to revise the notion of validity or keep the notion of validity unchanged and appeal to the notion of reasonableness to accommodate our intuition of reasoning, just like Stalnaker.

Counterexamples revisited apply first step analysis (3a) If neither Kate nor Daria answered the phone, then the phone was not answered by Kate. (3b) If neither Kate nor Daria answered the phone, then the phone was answered by Kate. (4a) If the king of France is bald, he exists. (4b) If the king of France is bald, he doesn t exist. Our intuition behind them has nothing to do with if, for we can replace if with and and our attitudes toward them remain the same.

Some conditionals, like (1), are due to similar reason, for their antecedents with some implicitly assumed laws can entail, presuppose, or conventionally implicate their consequents or the negation of their consequents (such as (1)).

Counterexamples revisited apply second step analysis Since speakers violate the conversational maxims Be relevant while asserting (2a) and (2b), audience obviously refute to accept it. However, our refuting to accept (2a) and (2b) doesn t mean that they are false. Therefore, (2a, b) are instances that are based on a conflation of truth and acceptance.

Counterexamples revisited apply third step analysis (5a) John will arrive on the 10 o clock plane. (5b) If John misses his plane in New York, he will arrive on the 10 o clock plane. The reason why we apt to take (5b) as false is that arriving on the 10 o clock plane is the logical consequence of not missing the plane.

Conclusion The goal here is to show that it is too rash to see if as the only suspect while explaining phenomena by arguing that counterexamples can be explained away by these three steps. Thus, truth functional theory of indicative conditionals is defensible on pragmatic grounds.