Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Similar documents
Skepticism and Contextualism

Knowledge and Presuppositions

A Closer Look At Closure Scepticism

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Skepticism and Contextualism

Comments on Lasersohn

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Ascribing Knowledge in Context: Some Objections to the Contextualist s Solution to Skepticism

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Knowledge, relevant alternatives and missed clues

MOORE, THE SKEPTIC, AND THE PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT * Wai-hung Wong

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Questioning Contextualism Brian Weatherson, Cornell University references etc incomplete

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

This discussion surveys recent developments

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Single Scoreboard Semantics

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

ACCOMMODATING THE SKEPTIC: A FRESH READING OF CONTEXTUALISM

Indexical Reliabilism and the New Evil Demon *

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

Epistemic Possibility

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Coordination Problems

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Knowledge, Safety, and Questions

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

HOW I KNOW I M NOT A BRAIN IN A VAT * José L. Zalabardo University College London

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

A Contrastivist Manifesto

Skepticism and Internalism

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Counter Closure and Knowledge despite Falsehood 1

Boghossian s Implicit Definition Template

Knowing and Knowledge. Though the scope, limits, and conditions of human knowledge are of personal and professional

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

External World Skepticism

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY. Contextualism and the Reference Class Problem. Masashi Kasaki A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES

Simplicity made difficult

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester


CLASSIC INVARIANTISM, RELEVANCE, AND WARRANTED ASSERTABILITY MANŒUVERS

Modal Conditions on Knowledge: Sensitivity and safety

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Inquiry and the Transmission of Knowledge

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Dogmatism and Moorean Reasoning. Markos Valaris University of New South Wales. 1. Introduction

Skepticism, Contextualism, and

What Should We Believe?

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Philosophy 370: Problems in Analytic Philosophy

Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. Guido Melchior. Philosophia Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN

Dretske on Knowledge Closure

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

A Priori Bootstrapping

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

No Royal Road to Relativism

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

KNOWING AGAINST THE ODDS

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Contextualism And The Factivity Problem

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

The Assumptions Account of Knowledge Attributions. Julianne Chung

Speaking of Knowing PATRICK RYSIEW 1. INTRODUCTION

The Question of Metaphysics

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Safety, sensitivity and differential support

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

Transcription:

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise Michael Blome-Tillmann University College, Oxford Abstract. Epistemic contextualism (EC) is primarily a semantic view, viz. the view that knowledge -ascriptions can change their contents with the conversational context. To be more precise, EC is the view that the predicate know has an unstable Kaplanian character, i.e. a character that does not map all contexts on the same content. According to EC, know is thus an indexical expression. Notwithstanding this purely linguistic characterisation of EC, contextualists have traditionally argued that their views have considerable philosophical impact, this being due to the alleged fact that their linguistic views about know provide the resources for a resolution of sceptical puzzles. In this paper I address an objection to EC claiming that, as a linguistic view about the term know, EC cannot be of any epistemological significance. Keywords: contextualism, knowledge, disquotation, presuppositions 1. Lewis Here is how David Lewis, one of the major figures in the contextualist scene, attempts to resolve sceptical puzzles. According to Lewis: (L) x satisfies knows p in C x s evidence eliminates every p-world, except for those that are properly ignored in C. 1 In addition to this definition of the satisfaction of know, Lewis stipulates a set of rules of relevance specifying which possibilities can be properly ignored in a given context. It is this set of rules that is meant to determine how the content of know is influenced by particular contextual factors. The rule doing the main explanatory work with regard to sceptical puzzles is Lewis s Rule of Attention (RA): (RA) If w is attended to by the speakers in C, then w cannot be properly ignored in C. Forthcoming in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. For discussion of earlier versions of this paper I am greatly indebted to Brian Ball, Dorothy Edgington and Tim Williamson. My research for this paper has been supported by the AHRC, the ANALYSIS Trust and the Old Members Trust of University College, Oxford. 1 Note here that Lewis considers one s evidence to be the contents of one s perceptual experiences and one s memories, assuming that these contents can be individuated narrowly. Cp. Lewis (1996), p. 224.

2 Michael Blome-Tillmann As Lewis points out, (RA) eventually boils down to the apparent triviality that a possibility not ignored at all is ipso facto not properly ignored. 2 How are (RA) and (L) intended to resolve sceptical puzzles? Firstly, note that when confronted with sceptical arguments, one inevitably attends to sceptical possibilities, for sceptical hypotheses, i.e. sentences expressing sceptical possibilities, form an integral part of sceptical arguments. Thus, it follows from (RA) that any context in which one considers sceptical arguments is a context in which one cannot properly ignore sceptical possibilities. Secondly, since, by definition, sceptical possibilities resist elimination by one s evidence, it follows from (RA) and (L) that, for all propositions p about the external world, one doesn t satisfy knows p in contexts in which one considers sceptical arguments. Such contexts are, as I shall put it henceforth, sceptical contexts. Thirdly, note that even though Lewis s account entails that we don t satisfy knows p in contexts in which sceptical arguments are at issue, it also entails that we do so in quotidian contexts: in quotidian contexts we don t attend to sceptical possibilities and thus often satisfy knows p for various propositions p about the external world. Lewis s views can thus be seen as accounting for both our Anti- Sceptical Intuitions (ASI) and our Sceptical Intuitions (SI), which are to be represented as follows: (ASI) People often speak truly when they assert I know p. (SI) People sometimes speak truly when they assert Nobody knows p in contexts in which sceptical arguments are discussed. However, if the semantic value of know can change in a way allowing for both (ASI) and (SI) to be true, why then are we puzzled by sceptical arguments? Lewis replies that the puzzle arises because we are often unaware of the relevant contextual shifts in the content of know. We simply don t always realise that our everyday knowledge -ascriptions express propositions that are perfectly compatible with the propositions expressed by knowledge -negations in sceptical contexts. 2. Sosa s Objection If EC is a linguistic view as outlined above, i.e. a view about the word know and its content, what is its epistemological relevance? Considering Lewis s attempt to resolve sceptical puzzles, this question may appear somewhat surprising. However, Ernest Sosa thinks that EC, 2 Lewis (1996), p. 230.

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise 3 even though true, has only little epistemological relevance, if any at all. Sosa: The main thesis of [EC] has considerable plausibility as a thesis in linguistics or in philosophy of language. In applying it to epistemology, however, it is possible to overreach [... ]. 3 Prominent epistemologists such as Keith Lehrer and Hilary Kornblith join Sosa in his assessment of EC, Kornblith declaring straightforwardly that EC is largely irrelevant to epistemological concerns. 4 Irrelevance with regard to epistemological concerns, however, is not the only charge the contextualist faces from Sosa s side. In a more recent paper Sosa even wonders whether epistemology [can] survive contextualism. 5 Epistemology providing jobs for philosophers around the world jobs which may go lost, if epistemology won t survive any kind of contextualism there is considerable practical reason for a defender of EC to take a closer look at Sosa s objection. What, then, is Sosa s objection? Firstly, note that Sosa seems to concede both the truth of EC and that EC explains what I have called the anti-sceptical intuition. Moreover, note that Sosa assumes with the standard contextualist that philosophical contexts such as the context of his paper are inevitably sceptical contexts: in epistemological contexts, Sosa assumes, one attends to sceptical possibilities, this having as a consequence that contexts of epistemological enquiry are sceptical contexts. This fairly standard assumption then leads Sosa to the criticism that [from (ASI)] it is not even clearly inferable that people are ever right when, in ordinary contexts, they claim to know things. This will not follow if only because it will not follow that people ever do claim, in an ordinary context, that they know things, as opposed to making utterances of the form I know such and such. The contextualist line deriving from EC hence does not much support, for us philosophers, the claim that people do in ordinary contexts after all know things. Nor does it even much support the claim that speakers are often enough right when they say that people know things. This limits the epistemological interest and relevance of [EC], however interesting and important it may remain as a thesis in linguistics. 6 We can make more obvious what is going on in this passage by introducing some technical language. Let KQ express the content of know in quotidian contexts and let KS express the content of know in sceptical contexts. Now consider (1), which we derive from (ASI) by disquotation: 3 Sosa (2000), p. 3. 4 See Lehrer (2000) and Kornblith (2000), p. 24. 5 See Sosa (2005). 6 Sosa (2000), p. 4; (Sosa s emphasis).

4 Michael Blome-Tillmann (1) People often speak truly when they assert that they know p. Depending on whether the epistemic standards of our present context are those of quotidian contexts or those of sceptical contexts (1) expresses either (2) or (3): (2) People often speak truly when they assert that they KQ p. (3) People often speak truly when they assert that they KS p. Since Sosa assumes with Lewis and other standard contextualists that contexts of epistemological enquiry are inevitably sceptical contexts, Sosa thinks that (1), in the context of both his paper and this presentation, expresses the proposition expressed by (3). The alleged problem for EC is now that (3) is clearly wrong, for it suggests that people in quotidian contexts assert that they KS p. However, when people in quotidian contexts use the word know, its semantic value is always KQ rather than KS. Thus, Sosa complains that contextualists convey a falsity, when they assert (1) in a context of epistemological discussion. 3. A Closer Look Is Sosa s point really damaging to EC? Note that the fact that Sosa exploits to develop his objection is the rather trivial fact that disquotation fails across contexts for indexical expressions: Sosa points out correctly that contextualists, in their own contexts of philosophical enquiry, cannot disquote (ASI). But why should contextualists be interested in disquoting (ASI) in the first place? Sosa, Lehrer and Kornblith do not give an argument in support of the assumption that they should, but they clearly think that the disquotation of (ASI) is an important epistemological goal for the contextualist. The most plausible way to make sense of this requirement is by assuming that Sosa et al. consider it impossible to be faithful to our anti-sceptical intuitions unless we can disquote (ASI). In reply to this assumption, however, the contextualist can insist that the anti-sceptical intuition is merely an intuition about the truth-values of certain utterances and as such is to be formulated meta-linguistically, as in (ASI). In failing to formulate the intuition meta-linguistically, the contextualist can argue, Sosa is methodologically inaccurate, and only this methodological inaccuracy leads him to require disquotability of (ASI) across contexts. An analogy helps illustrate this point. The first person pronoun I is obviously indexical: it changes its content with the context of utterance, depending on who is the speaker

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise 5 in the context of utterance. Now, here is a datum that we want our semantics of I to respect, call it the Fish Lovers Intuition (FLI): (FLI) People often speak truly when they assert I like fish. Any semantic theory of I that entails the negation of (FLI) is flawed. Now, since (FLI) contains the indexical I within quotes, (FLI) cannot be disquoted offhand. In the context of this talk, for instance, I cannot disquote and infer (4) from (FLI): (4) People often speak truly when they assert that I like fish. The problem with (4) is not only that it is false: since I am allergic to fish, nobody ever speaks truly when he or she asserts that I like fish. It is rather also the case that, analogously to Sosa s case about know, when somebody asserts the sentence I like fish that person does not express the proposition that I, MB-T, like fish, for in that person s mouth, I does not refer to me. Thus, disquotation of (FLI) fails across contexts. From these considerations, however, it finally follows that if Sosa s argument against EC were viable, then we should be able to complain analogously about contextualism about I that from (FLI) it is not even clearly inferable that I like fish. This is, however, an absurd objection to contextualism about I : contextualism about I merely has to respect (FLI), but it does not have to be able to establish that I like fish. Analogously, EC merely has to respect (ASI), but it does not have to be able to establish that people know that they have hands. Another point to be mentioned here is that the failure of contextualists to distinguish between meta-language and object-language is to a large part responsible for Sosa s misunderstanding of EC. Here is a quote from Sosa: Quite often contextualism is thought to show that even if we fail to know about ordinary matters in philosophical contexts, such as whether one has hands, we do often enough know those same matters in ordinary contexts. But this simply does not follow from the contextualist position, even though the advocates of contextualism speak as if it does. 7 Sosa is clearly right here. Contextualists such as Cohen and Lewis usually write as if it were an entailment of EC that we know all sorts of things in quotidian contexts. Here is a quote from Cohen (1999): [I]n everyday contexts, I can know that I don t see a cleverly-disguised mule, on the basis of the inductive evidence I have against such a scenario. In sceptical contexts where the standards are higher, I fail to know, on the basis of the inductive evidence, that I do not see a cleverly-disguised mule. 8 7 Sosa (2000), p. 8. 8 Cohen (1999), p. 66.

6 Michael Blome-Tillmann Of course, if EC is correct, then both occurrences of know in this quotation take KS as their semantic values: they are used in a context of epistemological discussion and such contexts are, according to EC, inevitably sceptical. Thus, contextualists failure to distinguish rigorously between object-language and meta-language has certainly given rise to the impression that EC should allow for the disquotation of (ASI). 9 4. A New Approach The above considerations may still leave us somewhat uneasy. Can t Sosa s objection be more intuitively paraphrased as the objection that only claims in which epistemological terminology is used as opposed to mentioned can count as epistemological claims? According to this view, EC does not qualify as an epistemological theory, since it is only a view about knowledge rather than about knowledge. Now, the contextualist can, of course, plausibly reply that, due to the context-sensitivity of know, defining epistemology thus ultimately begs the question against EC. I shall, however, not pursue this line of argument any further here. Instead, let me rather present a slightly amended version of standard contextualism that will eventually allow us to make interesting usage of the word know in most epistemological contexts. The account of EC I have in mind is a broadly Lewisian account that differs from Lewis s original theory only in replacing his Rule of Attention (RA) with what I call the Rule of Conversational Presupposition (RCP): (RCP) If w is incompatible with the speakers conversational presuppositions in C, then w can be properly ignored in C (unless a rule other than (RCP) states that w cannot be properly ignored in C). 10 How does this new conversational rule help us out of the predicament generated by Sosa s objections? Clearly, if only changes in the speaker s conversational presuppositions rather than the mere attendance to a sceptical possibility can turn one s context into a sceptical context, then 9 Contextualists are, of course, aware of the formal shortcomings of their presentations. In fact, they typically give a warning that, for stylistic reasons, they do not properly distinguish between object-language and meta-language and apologise for their failure to do so. See Cohen (1999), p. 65 and Lewis (1996), p. 238. 10 The other Lewisian rules, such as the Rule of Actuality and the Rule of Resemblance, help avoiding obvious problems such as failure of the factivity of know.

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise 7 there are numerous contexts of epistemological enquiry in which we can satisfy knows p for all kinds of propositions p about the external world: in contexts of epistemological enquiry we can perfectly well presuppose that we aren t handless brains-in-vats, for instance. Thus, on my new presupposition-based account of EC, by asserting People know p in a philosophical context I can express exactly the same proposition as I do if I assert the very same sentence in a quotidian context, provided that I make the same or at least relevantly similar presuppositions in both contexts. Independently of my considerations in the previous section, Sosa s point does accordingly no harm to our new approach to EC. The new contextualists can, after all, in most cases legitimately disquote (ASI). 11 References Cohen, S. (1988). How to Be a Fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91-123. Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 57-89. Kornblith, H. (2000). The Contextualist Evasion of Epistemology. Philosophical Issues 10: 24-32. Lehrer, K. (2000). Sensitivity, Indiscernibility and Knowledge. Philosophical Issues 10: 33-37. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive Knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 649-567. Reprinted in: DeRose, K. and Warfield, T. A. (eds., 1999). Skepticism, a Contemporary Reader, OUP, pp. 220-242. (Page references to reprinted version.) Sosa, E. (2000). Skepticism and Contextualism. Philosophical Issues 10: 1-18. Sosa, E. (2005). Contextualism, epistemic, recent work on. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. E. Craig. London, Routledge: Retrieved November 09, 2005, from http://reproutledge.com/article/p061. 11 Note that (RCP) does not render impossible a contextualist resolution of sceptical puzzles, for my view predicts accurately that we have sceptical intuitions in only those contexts of epistemological enquiry in which we cease to conversationally presuppose the negations of sceptical hypotheses. This explains the datum that some epistemologists (Mooreans) are unmoved by sceptical arguments: they simply don t stop presupposing that they aren t brains-in-vats. Moreover, note that my new account entails that knowledge is not as Lewis puts it elusive : it doesn t as easily vanish because epistemic standards cannot be raised by merely alluding to sceptical hypotheses.