DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

Similar documents
Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

John Stuart Mill ( ) is widely regarded as the leading English-speaking philosopher of

Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism, Multiplicity, and Liberalism

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Legitimacy, Democracy and Public Justification: Rawls Political Liberalism Versus Gaus Justificatory Liberalism

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

To link to this article:

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Utilitarianism JS Mill: Greatest Happiness Principle

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Rational choice theory: its merits and limits in explaining and predicting cultural behaviour

Policies and Procedures of the Evangelical Lutheran Church in America for Addressing Social Concerns

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Ethics is subjective.

Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to Critical Thinking M. Neil Browne and Stuart Keeley

Moral Communities in a Pluralistic Nation

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Epistemic Risk and Relativism

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification*

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Political Science 103 Fall, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

SYLLABUS. Department Syllabus. Philosophy of Religion

Political Science 603 Modern Political Thought Winter 2004

(naturalistic fallacy)

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Disagreement and the Duties of Citizenship. Japa Pallikkathayil

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Religious Freedom Policy

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Legend has it that a custodian put an image of a fly in a urinal in Amsterdam s Schiphol

Ethical Colonialism Joseph C. Pitt Virginia Tech

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Knowledge, Trade-Offs, and Tracking Truth

Lahore University of Management Sciences. POL 203 Introduction to Western Political Philosophy Fall

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Epistemic Akrasia. SOPHIE HOROWITZ Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Stout s teleological theory of action

ON THE DEMOCRATIC VALUE OF DISTRUST

David Enoch s Taking Morality Seriously (Oxford University Press 2011) is the latest in

GFS HISTORY Medium Term Plan Year 8 SPRING 1

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

What Should We Believe?

Government Neutrality toward. Conceptions of a Good Life: It s Possible and Desirable, But Perhaps Not so Important. Peter de Marneffe.

A note on reciprocity of reasons

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Moral Objectivity and Reasonable Agreement: Can Realism Be Reconciled with Kantian Constructivism?

Philosophical Review.

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015

Transcription:

1 Copyright 2005 Guido Pincione and Fernando R. Tesón DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón Cambridge University Press, forthcoming CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION CONTENTS 1.1. The Allure of Deliberation 1.2 Rational Choice and Political Discourse CHAPTER 2. THE EPISTEMIC ARGUMENT FOR DELIBERATION 2.1. Political Illiteracy: an Illustration 2.2. Discourse Failure 2.3. Patterns of Political Belief 2.4. Persuasive Definitions 2.5. Discourse Failure and Desert 2.6. The Cost of Dissent CHAPTER 3. THE RATIONAL CHOICE FRAMEWORK 3.1. Instrumental and Epistemic Rationality 3.2. Rational Choice and Morality 3.3. Why Our Argument Is Not Ad Hominem 3.4. A Note on Empirical Testing CHAPTER 4. THE RESILIENCE OF DISCOURSE FAILURE 4.1. Reliable Social Science and Opacity 4.2. Deliberative Institutions 4.3. Good Policies, Bad Reasons 4.4. Shortcuts 4.5. Deliberation, Free Speech, and Truth 4.6. Deliberation as a Regulative Ideal 4.7. Deliberative Democracy, Condorcet, and Bayes 4.8. Types of Discourse Failure: A Summary

2 CHAPTER 5. SYMBOLISM IN POLITICAL ARGUMENT 5.1. Self-Defeatingness as Symbolism 5.2. Symbolic Behavior in Politics 5.3. Symbolic and Causal Utility: Nozick s Challenge 5.4. Symbolizing as the Intended Outcome 5.5. Are Self-Defeating Reformers Rational? 5.6. Why Political Deliberators Appear to Neglect Consequences CHAPTER 6. DISCOURSE FAILURE AND POLITICAL MORALITY 6.1. The Moral Turn 6.2. Balancing, Deontology, and The Display Test 6.3. Direct Involvement in Evildoing 6.4. Split Responsibility 6.5. Causal Complexity in Political Argument 6.6. Moral Error 6.7. Enforcement and Causation 6.8. Summary and Caveat 6.9. A Note on Religious Morality 6.10. Appendix: Minimum Wages and Employment CHAPTER 7. NON-EPISTEMIC DEFENSES OF DELIBERATION 7.1. Deliberation as the Exercise of Autonomy 7.2. Sincerity in Deliberation 7.3. Deliberation and Social Conflict 7.4. Deliberation and Impartiality 7.5. Deliberation, Participation, and Equality 7.6. Is Discourse Failure Always Bad? CHAPTER 8. DELIBERATION, CONSENT, AND MAJORITY RULE 8.1. Consent and Reasonableness 8.2. Deliberation, Justice, and Rights 8.3. Deliberation and Majority Rule 8.4. Vote Indeterminacy 8.5. The Courtroom Analogy 8.6. Substantive Principles and Deliberative Politics

3 CHAPTER 9. OVERCOMING DISCOURSE FAILURE: VOLUNTARY COMMUNITIES 9.1. A Contractarian Society 9.2. Contracts and Truth 9.3. Contracts and Compromise 9.4. The Paradox of Contract 9.5. Further Objections and Replies 9.6. Discursive Advantages of Voluntary Communities 9.7. Loose Ends

4 OUTLINE OF THE BOOK EXCERPT FROM FROM SECTION 1.1. One reason given in favor of civic deliberation is epistemic: deliberation improves the (empirical or normative) soundness of our beliefs. Indeed, it would be odd for one to promote political deliberation if one thought of it as an exchange of ideas and arguments unrelated to the search for the truth. The idea of deliberation as a vehicle to truth is old and venerable. It was best put by John Stuart Mill in his defense of free speech: vigorous and lively discussion leads to the survival of the better ideas in society. 1 Deliberative democrats regard deliberation as a means to enhance the legitimacy of political coercion by, among other things, approaching truth in politics as closer as can be feasibly done. 2 Though perhaps neither necessary nor sufficient for the legitimacy of political coercion, on this view deliberation contributes to that legitimacy by enlightening political discourse. Deliberation might enlighten us on two counts. On the one hand, it might enable us to reach factual truths. This is a central theme in the philosophy of science. By constantly probing into alternative hypotheses, the scientific community moves science in the direction of truth. 3 On the other hand, deliberation might enable us to reach moral truths. 4 If we believe that moral progress is possible, then we will endorse continuous discussion, revision, and refinement of our moral beliefs, thus again improving our practical reasoning with a view to behaving correctly or virtuously. Deliberative democracy may also be defended on non-epistemic grounds. Thus, some writers value the symbolic function that deliberation can fulfill. Others claim that deliberation embodies recognition of citizens autonomy or their equal moral standing, or that it helps prevent social conflict. In this book we show that none of these arguments or others we will address in due course provide a satisfactory defense of political deliberation. We will proceed in the following sequence. In the next section, we locate our argument within the rational choice tradition in social science. In chapter 2, we diagnose the pathologies that affect political deliberation. We introduce the key notion of discourse failure to explain those pathologies. Chapter 3 discusses the place of moral judgment within the rational-choice framework, indicates how our use of rational choice assumptions combines with principles of epistemic 1 See John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (1859) Mill defends political deliberation in Considerations on Representative Government (1861), not on epistemic grounds but by reference to the value of participation. See chapters II and VI. His view that institutions should ensure that the superior of mind should govern, however, does not seem particularly congenial to modern deliberativism. See Representative Government, especially chapter VIII. At least one specialist claims that Mill inclined to the view that the mass or multitude was not in a position to acquire a clear understanding of the appropriate criteria for public conduct. R. J. Halliday, John Stuart Mill, (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1980), p. 69. As Gaus suggests, Mill s opposition to democratic equality is grounded in epistemic considerations. See Gaus, Contemporary Theories of Liberalism, p. 165. It seems fair to conclude that Mill was worried about the epistemic infirmities of political deliberation, notwithstanding his defense of the practice against non-participatory institutions (e.g., absolute monarchy and aristocracy.) 2 See references in chapter 2, note.we explore in section 4.5 to what extent deliberative democrats can trade on arguments for free speech. We will also address (chapter 8, sections 1 through 4) the view that deliberation may mitigate, if not eliminate, the otherwise coercive nature of majority rule. 3 Similar views obtain if higher predictive power and other notions that need not be given a realist interpretation substitute truth. Our assessment of the epistemic defense of deliberation will not turn on which of these accounts of science we adopt. 4 Here again (see note 7), by writing moral truths we do not mean to endorse moral realism. The deliberative argument, and our critique, can be cast in realist, coherentist, expressivist, and perhaps other conceptions of moral judgment, provided that they allow for degrees of moral plausibility.

rationality, and suggests directions for empirical testing of our theory. Chapter 4 replies to various attempts to save the epistemic credentials of deliberation. In chapter 5, we show that standard rational choice assumptions accommodate apparently self-defeating political positions; in particular, we argue that counterproductive positions cannot be vindicated as symbolic behavior. Chapter 6 fends off attempts to save such positions as nonconsequentialist moral outlooks. In chapter 7, we reject non-epistemic defenses of deliberation, such as those relying on autonomy, impartiality, or equality. In chapter 8, we explore the obscure relationships between deliberation, majority rule, and consent, and show why theories of deliberative democracy find it difficult to bring those notions into a coherent whole. Finally, in chapter 9 we outline an institutional structure capable of overcoming discourse failure; we explain why, unlike the utopian features of deliberative democracy, the utopian features of our proposal are innocuous. We also underscore why allowing people to actually consent to institutional arrangements (in contradistinction to the non-consensual features of modern democracy) will help reduce discourse failure. 5