First- or Second-Order Logic? Quine, Putnam and the Skolem-paradox *

Similar documents
Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Potentialism about set theory

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Wittgenstein and Gödel: An Attempt to Make Wittgenstein s Objection Reasonable

Realism and the Infinite. Not empiricism and yet realism in philosophy, that is the hardest thing. -Wittgenstein

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Completeness or Incompleteness of Basic Mathematical Concepts Donald A. Martin 1 2

The Gödel Paradox and Wittgenstein s Reasons. 1. The Implausible Wittgenstein. Philosophia Mathematica (2009). Francesco Berto

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

TWO PICTURES OF THE ITERATIVE HIERARCHY

Russell's paradox. Contents. Informal presentation. Formal derivation

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013.

On Quine, Ontic Commitments, and the Indispensability Argument. March Russell Marcus

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

LOGIC AS CALCULUS AND LOGIC AS LANGUAGE

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Full-Blooded Platonism 1. (Forthcoming in An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, Bloomsbury Press)

Semantics and the Justification of Deductive Inference

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

By Hans Robin Solberg

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Fictionalism, Theft, and the Story of Mathematics. 1. Introduction. Philosophia Mathematica (III) 17 (2009),

13 The model-theoretic argument: from skepticism to a new understanding

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

Gödel's incompleteness theorems

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Nominalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics First published Mon Sep 16, 2013

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

THE LIAR PARADOX IS A REAL PROBLEM

REALISM AND THE INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS IN KURT GÖDEL S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. Honors Thesis. Zachary Purvis. Spring 2006

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Beyond Symbolic Logic

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

subject are complex and somewhat conflicting. For details see Wang (1993).

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Jaakko Hintikka IF LOGIC MEETS PARACONSISTENT LOGIC

Truth and Disquotation

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Deflationism and the Gödel Phenomena: Reply to Ketland Neil Tennant

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Russell on Plurality

International Phenomenological Society

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

The Principle Of Excluded Middle Then And Now: Aristotle And Principia Mathematica

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity.

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Constructing the World

On Tarski On Models. Timothy Bays

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

The Failure of Leibniz s Infinite Analysis view of Contingency. Joel Velasco. Stanford University

Philosophy 308 The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Hamilton College, Fall 2014

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious

What kind of Intensional Logic do we really want/need?

August 8, 1997, Church s thesis, formal definitions of informal notions, limits of formal systems, Turing machine, recursive functions - BIG

Oxford Handbooks Online

Great Philosophers Bertrand Russell Evening lecture series, Department of Philosophy. Dr. Keith Begley 28/11/2017

On Naturalism in Mathematics

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Introduction. Agustín Rayo and Gabriel Uzquiano 1.1 THE PROBLEM OF ABSOLUTE GENERALITY

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: , ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994).

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

THE PROBLEM OF TRUTH IN THE CLASSICAL ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE

The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Defending the Axioms

HOW FINE-GRAINED IS REALITY?

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Honors Thesis ************************* PASS WITH DISTINCTION

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

When does everything mean everything?

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Presentation to the panel, Does mathematics need new axioms? ASL 2000 meeting, Urbana IL, June 5, 2000 Solomon Feferman

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Transcription:

First- or Second-Order Logic? Quine, Putnam and the Skolem-paradox * András Máté EötvösUniversity Budapest Department of Logic andras.mate@elte.hu The Löwenheim-Skolem theorem has been the earliest of the great theorems of metalogic. In 1922, Skolem recognized the (apparent) paradox connected with it. 1 The (LS) theorem and the paradox had a long and important later history in model theory; but for philosophy, it had had a half century long dream of a sleeping beauty 2 until it was awakened by two fundamental papers of contemporary metaphysics: by Quine s Ontological Relativity 3 and by Putnam s Models and Reality 4. The theorem itself says (in its original and simplest form) that if a set of propositions of some first-order language has a model, then it has a countable (i.e. finite or countable infinite) model, too. Consequently, if we know that a first-order theory has no finite models and we suppose that it is consistent (and therefore, by the completeness theorem, it has a model) it follows that our theory should have a countable infinite model, too. The paradox can be made clear by a special case. The first order theory of real numbers includes a special case of Cantor s theorem about power sets: we can prove within the theory that the set of all real numbers, i. e. the set of individual objects the theory is about is not countable. But by the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem we know that the theory has a model in which the universe, the set of all real numbers of the model is countable. This is not a real antinomy but just an apparent paradox, of course; but it has the important moral for the mathematician that some of our concepts are not absolute but model-dependent: a set that is countable according the countability-concept of one model may be uncountable according to the concept of another model. In this case, the basic set is countable in the model of ZFC we live in but uncountable in the model we can build up following the demonstration of the LS theorem. (ZFC is the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice.) The theorem is significant because it is a negative categoricity result: it shows that by first-order theories we can t characterize the objects we scrutinize (the models of our theories) up to isomorphism if our theory has uncountable models. * The research leading to this paper was supported by OTKA, projects No. T 34861 and TS 40899. I thank to Hajnal Andréka, István Németi Ildikó Sain (Budapest), and the members of the Logic Seminar of the Philosophical Institute of the Erlangen University for their comments and suggestions. 1 The theorem was published in that general form which is relevant for us here by Th. Skolem, Logisch-kombinatorische Untersuchungen, Videnskapsselskapets skrifter, I. Matematisk-naturvidenskabelig klasse 4(1920), pp. 1 36. The paradox was presented by him in the paper Einige Bemerkungen zur axiomatischen Begründung der Mengenlehre, in: Matemetikerkongressen in Helsingfors den 4 7. Juli 1922, Akademiska Bokhandeln Helsinki, 1922, pp. 217 232. 2 One of the rare discussions of the theorem is to be found in :Academic Freedeom, Logic and Religion (ed. Morton White, University of Pennnsylvania Press, Philadelphia, 1953). where the two speakers of a symposium about the ontological significance of the LS theorem, Berry and Myhill aggree that the theorem have no such significance. (Professor Christian Thiel (Erlangen) called my attention to this discussion.) 3 In: Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Columbia University Press, New York, 1969, pp. 26-68. 4 Journal of Symbolic Logic 45(1980), pp. 464-482. 1

All that I m saying now is formulated in the language of the naïve Platonist mathematician (NPM): e.g. that we live in a model of ZFC as formulated in the metalanguage (although we can t know in which one), that our theories have objects, etc. NPM believes that the real world is identical with some model <V, > of MetaZFC and therefore, truth for some proposition ϕ means that <V, > ϕ. For NPM, the problem with the Skolem paradox is not that we may have rival theories contradicting to each other and we can t have any rational reason by which we could choose among them. For him, the problem is that we may have substantially different models for the very same theory and we can formulate the difference in the metalanguage but we can t express it in the language of the theory (just that s why the rival models are equally warranted models). The problem of equally warranted rival theories is well known for him at least from the discovery of non-euclidean geometries. NPM knows that the case of the continuum hypothesis (CH) just repeats the situation with the different geometries: we have no reason to decide either for ZFC+CH or for ZFC+ CH. Such rival theories give alternative pictures about the world (if we suppose with NPM that set theory is about the world in some way); but the novelty following from (this simple form of) the LS theorem is that neither of the alternative theories can describe the world in the sense that it would imply all the substantial properties of the world. In Quine s Ontological relativity the LS theorem appears in the context of the indeterminacy of reference. His whole argument shows that semantic questions can t be put in an absolute way but only with reference to some background theory. So propositions like s refers to Socrates, the extension of A consists of the animals, ϕ is true are all context-dependent propositions in the sense that they depend on the background theory but we can t fix the reference of the terms of the background theory in an absolute way, either. The LS theorem reinforces this consequence in that it shows that terms of a mathematical theory like number, set, countable etc. may have very different interpretations if the background theory changes. Putnam s Models and Reality connects the problem of equally warranted models with the problem of equally warranted theories. Let us suppose that we can extend our knowledge to an ideal theory T I, i.e. to a theory that fits to all observational and theoretical constraints we may accept at any time. We can t get rid on this way from the problem that T I may have different models, and consequently from that T I may have different, even contradictory extensions by propositions undecidable in T I. (E.g. if we extend it by the continuum hypothesis (CH) or by its negation.) Putnam concludes in Models and Reality that with respect of T I, the question of the truth of such a proposition is meaningless. 5 I have just mentioned and not explained the argument this time; it is known in the recent literature as Putnam s model theoretic argument. His proposal is to give up realist semantics for a verificationist one, but not to give up realist mathematics for the intuitionistic one: we should understand the 5 Professor Putnam has remarked to this point that he had changed his mind in this respect. See his Paradox revisited II: Sets A Case of All or None, in: Sher, G. R. Tieszen (eds.): Between Logic and Intuition. Essays in Honor of Charles Parsons, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2000, pp. 16 256. esp. pp.23-24., and Wittgenstein, Realism and Mathematics (manuscript), where he writes on p. 2.: crucial difficulties for the view that mathematical truth cannot transcend provability can be discovered from an examination of the ways in which mathematics is used in mathematical physics. I thank to Professor Putnam for this remark and for the sending of the manuscript. 2

language of normal mathematics as referring to operations, procedures, etc, and referring to objects not as they are in the Platonist heaven of mathematics but as they are given to us by procedures. Some people, e.g. van Fraassen 6 interpreted Putnam s model theoretic argument in a way that every proposition should be true which is modeled by any acceptable model (i.e. by any model that is coherent with our observational and operational constraints); therefore, the model-theoretic argument as a reductio of the metaphysical realist view should end with an explicit contradiction: CH is true because some models qualify it as true, but CH is also true according to some other models (and it is demonstrable that no extension of the constraints by knowable true propositions can help). This interpretation has an apparent similarity to NPM s view in that it uses the word true in an unqualified way (contrary to Quine s true to a background theory or to Putnam s internal realism). But the similarity is just apparent, because for NPM it is not the case that both CH and CH are true, but that the propositions M 1 CH and M 2 CH are both true (being M 1 and M 2 models of ZFC in which CH is true resp. false). M 1 and M 2 are inside models of ZFC relative to our real world <V, >; they can t be identical with the real world but it is possible that one of them is isomorphic with <V, >. If M 1 is isomorphic with the world then CH is true, if M 2 is such, then CH is true, and if none of them, then we can t say anything again. Therefore, the Skolem argument even together with the belief that we can use the word true in an absolute sense doesn t lead necessarily to a contradiction. The Skolem paradox is not an antinomy in formal logic neither for Putnam nor for NPM. The key point of the difference between NPM and Putnam lies somewhere else. For Putnam 1980, 7 for Dummett 8 and for several other philosophers propositions whose truth or falsity is unknowable for reasons of principle are meaningless and CH is a very good example for such propositions. NPM says it is all philosophical bullshit he knows very well what does he mean by CH. On this point, I need to stress that I m not identical or even isomorphic with NPM I rather suspend my judgment. I just want to quote some argument from NPM in favor of his view. If a sentence of mathematics is meaningless then it can t have a truth-value. But NPM has good reasons to believe that at least some of his undecidable propositions have a truth-value in the absolute sense. Let P 2 denote the set of second-order Peano axioms, 2 the (semantic) consequence relation of standard second-order logic and Con(ZFC) the formula of first-order arithmetic that expresses the consistency of ZFC by a fixed but arbitrary Gödel numbering. The sentence (A) P 2 2 Con (ZFC) 6 Elgin on Lewis s Putnam s Paradox, Journal of Philosophy XCIV(1997), pp. 85-87. 7 I. e. Putnam in Models and Reality ; but cf. again footnote 5. 8 For his view see The Logical Basis of Metaphysics (Duckworth, London, 1991, e.g. p. 316.) 3

is for NPM either true or false like any correct mathematical sentence that we can formulate within the language of MetaZFC it is just a presupposition connected with the use of this language. But in this case, NPM s conviction that (A) should have a truth-value has some clear intuitive grounds much more clear ones at least than in the case of CH or even in the case of the axiom of choice. Namely, Con(ZFC) is an arithmetical proposition, although not a very simple one: it contains quantifications that prevent us to verify it by simple calculation. (More exactly, it is a Π 2 proposition.) P 2 is a categorical system of axioms, and this fact entails that we can take any model M P2 of it (in fact, P 2 has only one model up to isomorphism) and put the question whether this model makes Con(ZFC) true or not; this question will be equivalent with the question of truth of (A). It seems that this question can be translated into a question about a potentially infinite series of simple signs on an infinite tape. We can say in a sufficiently clear sense that (A) is in principle although not in practice decidable. But the example of (A) differs e.g. from the problem of twin primes that Dummett uses as his example in the Logical Basis of Metaphysics. The truth-value of (A) is unknowable in a definite sense because of the Second Incompleteness Theorem (assumed that MetaZFC is consistent). To see this, let us translate the axioms P 2 into truths of first-order ZFC on the usual way; let us denote their conjunction by P 2*. Con(ZFC) will be translated into some proposition Con(ZFC) * of first-order set theory, too. The truth-value of Con(ZFC) * must depend on the interpretation of the non-logical constant of the language of set theory ( ), because otherwise this formula (or its negation) would be a semantical consequence of ZFC in first-order logic, and therefore, by completeness, it would be deducible in ZFC. Consequently, the truth of Con(ZFC) *, and hence the truth of (A) depends on set-theoretic properties of our world <V, > that are undecidable in (Meta)ZFC otherwise, we could prove the consistency of ZFC (or its contrary). ********** So NPM is a metaphysical realist: he believes (for good or wrong reasons) that there are unanswerable but meaningful questions like the question of the truth-value of (A). However, we shall see from this very example why does he agree with Quine and Putnam in another important question connected with the LS theorem and this is the alternative of first- and second-order logic. Maybe he has even better arguments for choosing first-order logic. LS is the single negative theorem of metalogic in which the fact that we work in first-order logic plays an apparently substantial role. The incompleteness theorems infect by incompleteness any theory whose language can express first-order Peano arithmetic. The Church-Turing theorem infects by undecidability every theory the decidability of which can be reduced to the stop problem of Turing machines and the case is similar with Tarski s theorem about the undefinability of truth. But with LS as a negative categoricity result, this is not the case. If we extend our first-order logic to second-order logic, 9 the impossibility of a categorical arithmetic disappears; even 9 A terminological digression: by second-order logic I mean here standard second-order logic with semantic consequence relation defined on the natural way unlike Putnam, who in Models and Reality 4

the second-order version of ZFC is very close to being categorical. It leaves only one question open: how large is the world? 10 The categoricity of second-order arithmetic may awake the illusion that accepting P 2, we fix the truth-value of any arithmetical proposition, or in other words, a propositon is a truth of arithmetic if and only if it is a semantical consequence of P 2, and this is in principle a finaél answer to any question concerning arithmetic. But this is just an illusion, as a little extension of the above argumentation shows. In fact, (A) reproduces the Skolem paradox in a funny way. Being P 2 a complete, even a categorical system of axioms, it determines the truth-value of any arithmetical formula, inclusive that of Con(ZFC). Therefore, Con(ZFC) should have an absolute truth-value. How is it possible, then, that Con(ZFC) may have different truth-values in different models as we observed above? Well, Con(ZFC) has an absolute truth-value relative to the given world <V, >. In other words, categoricity implies that in any model of P 2, Con(ZFC) will have the same truth-value in any model of P 2 constructed within the same world of sets. But if God changes the world <V, > around us for another model of ZFC, the truth-value of ZFC may get changed; and as we learned above, God can do this alteration without that we observe it on any intellectual or perceptual way. We could have a categorical arithmetic but we don t fix the truth-value of each arithmetical proposition by that because we can t fix the world of sets we live in. Therefore, by changing our logic to the second-order one we don t get rid of the discomfort that the impossibility of a categorical arithmetic, the unprovability of consistency etc. causes we just import the problems into the logical framework. On the very end, the logical consequence relation 2 depends from <V, > on a way that we can t control it is <V, >-dependent whether P 2 does entail Con(ZFC) or not. Let us accept a rather common but suitable picture about what should we expect from logic to tell the truth, the picture will involve some realist commitment. Pictures are not good as philosophical arguments; but sometimes they are comfortable tools to illuminate our wishes, fears, expectations etc. The world is large and difficult, full of unsolved, maybe unsolvable problems, full of information and we can comprehend a very little part of it, it is full of phenomena we can t keep under our control. But we have logic to elaborate the little information we can reach, and we can keep our logic pretty well under control as completeness and compactness shows. A change from first-order to second-order involves the loss of this control for just apparent advantages. identifiessecond-order logic with Henkin-style second-order logic that allows partial models. For me as well as for NPM logic is a language together with the rules for its interpretation; the language does not determinate in itself how it should be interpreted. Consequence should be characterized primarily on semantic way, with reference to models for the language. From a Platonist point of view, it is not a crucial problem in itself that the consequence relation gained on this way is not finitely axiomatizable; we know by the definition what logical consequence is and it is just another question that we don t have a complete method to reach the consequences. (Cf. S. Shapiro: Foundations witjout Foundationalism, Oxford University Press, Oxford etc., 1991, passim.) Second-order logic with interpretation rules that don t allow partial models i.e. standard second-order logic is therefore a possible candidate for our logical framework not a good one, however. 10 See E. Zermelo: Über Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche, Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16(1930), pp. 29-47. 5