The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

Similar documents
Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

THE PROBLEM WITH SOCIAL TRINITARIANISM: A REPLY TO WIERENGA

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

A Rate of Passage. Tim Maudlin

Creation & necessity

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

EXTRACTS from LEIBNIZ-CLARKE CORRESPONDENCE. G. W. Leibniz ( ); Samuel Clarke ( )

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aboutness and Justification

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

Is the Identity of Indiscernibles refuted by Max Black's thought experiment? What is the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII)?

1/6. Space and Time in Leibniz and Newton (2)

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

William Ockham on Universals

Skepticism and Internalism

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

The Leibniz Review, Vol. 11,

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

5 A Modal Version of the

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Title Interpretation in the English-Speak.

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Evaluating Arguments

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

The cosmological argument (continued)

Anti-intellectualism and the Knowledge-Action Principle

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Structural realism and metametaphysics

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Reply to Robert Koons

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Immortality Cynicism

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Kant and his Successors

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley. Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University. 1. Introduction

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

The Principle of Sufficient Reason in Spinoza

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Theories of propositions

Transcription:

Reply to Cover Dennis Plaisted, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation ofleibniz's views on relations is surely to be found in Jan Cover's (and John Hawthorne's) outstanding book, Substance and Individuation in Leibniz. Not surprisingly, Cover's review of my book sets forth a number of objections to the view I develop. Despite my resistance to his objections in what follows, I found his charges to be both challenging and instructive, and I am grateful for the overall friendly tone with which he expressed them. Cover decries the absence from my book (and from anti-reductionist literature generally) of any detailed account of the structure of relational accidents in general, and the lack of any detailed account of how individuals form part of the content of such accidents (e.g., how Helen is involved with Paris' accident 'lover of Helen') in particular. His way of driving home the need for such an account in Substance and Individuation in Leibniz was to ask: "... are we to believe that lleibnizj rejects accidents with one leg in one substance, the other in another, but welcomes accidents with one leg in one substance and a full-nelson hug around another."l The worry seems to be that the inherence of relational accidents in substances would somehow run afoul of Leibniz's doctrine of individual accidents, and would perhaps do so in an especially egregious way. How so? The answer is not easy to see. The view I ultimately impute to Cover in my book is that if Helen is a constituent of 'lover of Helen' and if 'lover of Helen', as my view maintains, inheres in Paris, then Helen, by transitivity, gains an impermissible foothold in Paris. Apparently laboring under a delusion, I spend much of my chapter three showing that this consequence does not occur. I argue that if we take Helen's constituency in the accident as her being included (in Leibniz's formal sense of that notion) in it, then she is not a constituent of the accident, as Leibniz's conditions for inclusion are not met in her case or in the case of any other individual's being included in any other relational accident. But in his review Cover states that he never intended to argue that Helen steps into Paris in this way; his intent with the full-nelson charge was only to press for the need of an account of how Helen is involved in 'lover of Helen', perhaps so we can be assured that nothing metaphysically suspect (like Helen's having a leg in Paris) is going on. 109

DENNIS PLAISTED Now, I grant that I never offer an affirmative account of the structure of relational accidents,2 but I believe this counts for little against my view. For anything one could say about Leibniz's views on this would be largely speculative. Leibniz appears to have realized that the concepts of relational accidents could not be formed by the concept-joining operation he understood best-real addition. Instead, he seems to say that such concepts must be formed by an operation he refers to as oblique addition. 3 However, Leibniz has little to say about the structure of such oblique sums. Of course, these are concepts of relational accidents and not the accidents themselves, but Leibniz's failure to develop his view of the former is, I believe, a good indication that his view of the latter was undeveloped as well. Nevertheless, my argument in chapter three does show that by Leibniz's own logic of concept-inclusion the concepts of individuals are not included in the concepts of relational accidents. The relation of individual concepts to concepts of relational accidents is something other than containment or inclusion. I strongly suspect that Leibniz would adhere to an analogous result with respect to the relation of individuals to relational accidents. That being so, then although I am unable to offer an affirmative characterization of this relation, I can't find any reason to fear that allowance of relational accidents will transgress the doctrine of individual accidents or lead to anything else that Leibniz would regard as metaphysically unacceptable. Cover also finds details missing in my response to the world-apart objection, the objection that Leibniz cannot have countenanced relational accidents because it would have violated his view that each monad is like a world-apart. Siding with D' Agostino,4 I maintain essentially in the book (p. 9) that the world-apart doctrine only forbids causal influence between monads, it does not bar logical dependence between them. Cover chides, and in this case I think rightfully so, for my failure to explicate the nature of this logical dependence relation, for if it is as strong as Cover suspects it is, it will "make hash" of the world-apart doctrine. Rather than wishing I had offered an account of the notion, however, I wish I had simply not invoked it at all. For I don't think it's needed to respond to the world-apart objection. The world-apart doctrine is primarily a claim that monads do not causally influence one another and that each one's states unfold by means of its own internal law. So, as long as a monad's relational attributes, along with all of its other attributes, unfold via its own internal law and not the causal influence of other monads, then no culinary, or other, violence to the worldapart doctrine occurs. Could a thing have relational attributes arise in this man- 110

REPLY TO COVER ner if only it and God existed? I think such a scenario fully coheres with these well-known remarks: There would be no deception of rational creatures, however, even if everything outside of them did not correspond exactly to their experiences, or indeed if nothing did, just as if there were only one mind; because everything would happen just as if all other things existed... (G II 496) Cover was right, therefore, to red-flag the talk oflogical dependence, but I don't believe any harm to my view results once the notion is, as I think it fairly can be, put aside. Cover also asserts that a trivialization of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles results if, as my view maintains, relational attributes are genuine features of things. 'Distinct from B' is a relational attribute which, if it were regarded as actually being in A, would distinguish A from B, but would do so in a glaringly hollow way. I believe that such a situation would trivialize the identity of indiscernibles principle only if 'distinct from B' were the only difference that obtained between A and B. If, on the other hand, this difference was always accompanied by other differences, then such a trivialization need not occur. Such is the case. If two things are distinct, their spatial positions will differ and their differing positions will give rise to numerous other differences in the relational attributes that each one possesses. In section 47 of his fifth letter to Clarke, Leibniz famously explains that a thing's place, though not an accident itself, is founded upon the relations of coexistence that the thing has to other fixed existents. If two things differ in place, then each will have a distinct set of relations of coexistence. Further, Leibniz appears to assert to Clarke that these relations of coexistence are accidents in substances. I realize that Cover remains unimpressed by such passages as proof texts for anti-reductionist views. Be that as it may, the passage does show Leibniz's view that differences in position will always be accompanied by differences in relations of coexistence. Thus whether one regards the relations of coexistence themselves as accidents or whether one believes that they ultimately reduce to non-relational accidents, one can equally well say that, on Leibniz's view, no two things will differ in just their places (which, since place is not a genuine accident, would not constitute a real difference) or solely in one's having a relational attribute of being distinct from the other. From his remarks in the review, I suspect that Cover will not accept differences in relations of coexistence as sufficient for avoiding the trivialization of the identity of indiscernibles principle either. That is, he may have us imagine two dis- 111

DENNIS PLAISTED tinct substances A and B which are alike in every respect save their relations of coexistence, and then assert that the imagined scenario secures the principle in a trivial way as well. Presumably, this is the point of his mention of Leibniz's argument from the fourth letter to Clarke (G VII 364), which Cover paraphrases as: "If ours were a world W in which there are distinct indiscernibles a and b, there would be a numerically distinct world W* in which a and b are spatially 'switched' such that God could have no sufficient reason for preferring W over W*." But this passage would only count against my view if Leibniz would extend the notion of distinct indiscernibles (i.e., of two things that are equal and perfectly alike) to things which are alike in every respect except in their relations of coexistence, and I am far from convinced that he would. I don't see why differences in relations of coexistence fail to count as non-trivial differences between two substances. It is surely far from clear that two things which are alike in every respect save their relations of coexistence (assuming such relations were genuine accidents) can reasonably be said to be, from the standpoint of God's wisdom and choice, equal and perfectly alike. It is my contention, then, that Leibniz's argument against Clarke does not concern a situation like the foregoing; rather, it concerns a scenario under which two things are alike in every respect. And if that were the case, then (as place itself is not an accident of things) a bare difference in the places of the things, under the assumption that the things are alike in every internal respect (not even differing in relations of coexistence), would not be accompanied by any actual difference in the things, and God would have no reason for placing them in one arrangement rather than another. This is the thrust of Leibniz's argument, and I believe that, contrary to what Cover alleges, it makes sense under my view. Lastly, I must take exception to Cover's overall assessment that my Leibniz floats too near the linguistic surface of the topic, while his Leibniz resides at the deeper (and presumably truer) metaphysical foundations of it. The central project of my book is to develop a more plausible reading of Leibniz's claim that there are no purely extrinsic denominations (NPE) by examining both Leibniz's arguments for NPE from other of his doctrines and his argument from NPE to the doctrine of expression. Leibniz employs his predicate-in-subject principle, the principle of the interconnection of all things and the identity of indiscernibles principle to establish NPE. I argue in a fair amount of detail (see chs. 2, 4 and 5) that on no plausible reconstruction of these arguments can the reductionist view of NPE be seen as Leibniz's intended result, whereas the version of NPE I pro- 112

REPLY TO COVER pose is clearly implicated in each one. The reductionist rendering of NPE, at best, can be made to cohere with these doctrines, but it doesn'tfollow from them, as Leibniz so often asserts that NPE does. Nor can reductionist NPE serve as a plausible premise for the doctrine of expression (see ch. 6). Again, expression can cohere with a reductionist construal of NPE, but it is not at all clear how it can be inferred from it. These are some of Leibniz's central metaphysical doctrines, and if the reductionist reading of NPE does not follow from them (or function well as a premise for them, in the case of the expression doctrine), then that is evidence against its being the view of the true metaphysical Leibniz. And if my view succeeds far better in these contexts, then that is evidence in its metaphysical favor. I do not primarily rest my case on the fact that Leibniz often refers to extrinsic denominations as 'predicates' or 'accidents', or the "adverb-dropping inference" Cover refers to at the beginning of section II of his review. These linguistic-surface-type considerations are a part of the case for an anti-reductionist reading of Leibniz and I treat them as such in the book, but they are certainly not the heart of my case. Thus, for all Cover says, I see no reason to concede the metaphysical high ground to him. Dennis Plaisted Department of Philosophy and Religion University of Tennessee at Chattanooga 232 Holt Hall 615 McCallie Ave Chattanooga, TN 37403 dennis-plaisted@utc.edu Notes I Cover and Hawthorne, Substance and Individuation in Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 73. 2 I say that such is not my aim on p. 38. I refer the reader to my remarks on that page for more response to Cover on this issue. ] See General Inquiries about the Analysis of Concepts and of Truths, C 356-359. See also my discussion of this on pp. 42-45. 4 D' Agostino, F. (1976). "Leibniz on Compossibility and Relational Predicates." Philosophical Quarterly 26: 125-138. 113