In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

Similar documents
From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Agency and Responsibility. According to Christine Korsgaard, Kantian hypothetical and categorical imperative

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Ethics is subjective.

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

O Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Kant and his Successors

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers


Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

5 A Modal Version of the

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1)

1. The Regress Argument

Kant's Moral Philosophy

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

The Philosophical Value of Reflective Endorsement

Kihyun Lee (Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University)

CONSTRUCTIVISM IN ETHICS

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

PHIL 202: IV:

Natural Goodness, Rightness, and the Intersubjectivity of Reason: A Reply to Arroyo, Cummisky, Molan, and Bird-Pollan

The Grounding for Moral Obligation

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity.

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

The Tempering of a Defense: Further Critiques Against Error Theory in Light of Russ Shafer- Landau s Ethical Nonnaturalism

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

A number of epistemologists have defended

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

The Problem of the External World

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Transcription:

Aporia vol. 26 no. 1 2016 Contingency in Korsgaard s Metaethics: Obligating the Moral and Radical Skeptic Calvin Baker Introduction In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical project as offered in her book, The Sources of Normativity. In brief, Korsgaard attempts to demonstrate that people who value anything incur moral obligations. Korsgaard s system thus purports to answer the moral skeptic, who believes she can value without incurring moral obligations, but not the radical skeptic, who values nothing at all. I agree that Korsgaard cannot answer the radical skeptic and argue that Korsgaard s system can answer some but not all moral skeptics, for there are people who can value but not incur moral obligations in the manner Korsgaard describes. I will first provide a sketch of Korsgaard s position to ground my discussion. According to Korsgaard, normative values are not mind-independent facts woven into the fabric of reality. Values are instead human creations that exist only within human viewpoints (or perhaps the viewpoints of other creatures with similar capacities of rational deliberation), which is why Korsgaard is sometimes categorized as a metaethical constructivist (Korsgaard 161). Despite their contingent status, values and morals approach objectivity by giving Calvin Baker is a junior studying philosophy and international relations at Stanford University. His philosophical interests include ethics and human flourishing. He will graduate in 2018.

40 Calvin Baker answers to practical problems in the genre of how ought I to live? and what is the right action in this case? (Korsgaard 161). Such answers are solutions to normative questions, and yet are not correct in virtue of necessary, intrinsic features of reality (Bagnoli 2.2 ). They instead owe their validity to the method used to arrive at them (Korsgaard 36). This method is the process of reasoning through practical normative questions (Bagnoli, 2.2 ). Korsgaard holds that this reasoning process itself contains nearly objective steps, in virtue of which the normative conclusions it provides are valid (Bagnoli 2.2 ). The essential claim is that the method of practical reasoning yields the following conclusion: if an agent values anything, he must have moral obligations and values (Korsgaard 92). The Moral Skeptic and the Process of Reflective Deliberation Korsgaard s moral skeptic denies just this conclusion: he believes he can value certain things without incurring moral obligations (Korsgaard 163). To refute the moral skeptic, then, Korsgaard must establish that the act of valuing generates moral obligations. Her defense of this position lies in an account of reflective, practical reasoning. 1 Korsgaard begins with a problem that motivates her account of practical reasoning. 2 Noting the self-conscious nature of the human mind, Korsgaard highlights the capacity of self-reflection. Humans can question whether their impulses and desires are proper reasons for action. This ability to question ourselves triggers a problem: to act on impulses and desires, we must reflectively endorse them as legitimate reasons. If I am tired and desire to take a nap, I must decide that my desire to nap is a good reason to nap before climbing into bed. Such endorsement is a first-person enterprise: each person assesses, endorses, and rejects desires from within her own perspective 1 Two lectures by Carlos Núñez shaped my understanding of Korsgaard s account, especially its ascending, dialectic nature. These are Philosophy 90N: Lecture 12 and Philosophy 90N: Lecture 13, respectively given at Stanford University on October 29, 2015 and November 3, 2015. 2 For the problem and its explanation, see Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity, 92 93.

Korsgaard s Metaethics 41 (Korsgaard 96). However, the problem remains of how and why we decide which specific desires to endorse. Korsgaard holds that we derive reasons for specific actions from more general principles, and that since humans have free will, they must construct and impose these principles on themselves (98). Action guiding principles are thus laws that free agents choose to follow (98). I might decide that my desire to nap is a good reason to get in bed because I ve chosen to follow the maxim <I will sleep when tired, barring any pressing needs to stay awake>. Humans need laws of this kind, for again, their reflective natures demand reasons for action, which as free agents can only come from themselves (103 4). The dialectic continues when we ask which action guiding laws to freely impose on ourselves. Korsgaard maintains that the reflective structure of human consciousness requires identification with our laws, and that is the source of normativity (104). Free will does not mean we can randomly impose and identify with laws, though, for we need to justify the laws to ourselves (and random choice would not pass the reflective test). De facto, the process of identifying with laws depends on self conception: if a law is consistent with my identity, I can impose it on myself (107, 110). For example, if I am a pacifist, I will follow the law <I will not fight in wars> and thus endorse my desire to not fight in World War III. When I endorse a practical identity (e.g., a pacifist, a friend, a student, etc.), I thus endorse it as a source of reasons (Bagnoli, 2.2 ). Korsgaard points out that many of our practical identities are contingent (they could have been different) and are subject to revision and renunciation (120). If the source of our endorsements is identification with contingent identities, however, the process of reflective deliberation will not yield an objective grounding of value and morality. For example, if A reflectively endorses her identity as a soldier and commits to World War III and B reflectively endorses her identity as a pacifist and commits to nonviolence, we will be unable to decide whose decision is correct if the story ends with identity endorsement. However, Korsgaard claims to have pinpointed one identity that almost all people must share: the identity of a reflective being who requires reasons for action (120 21). For, since practical identities provide reasons for action, if a person is not committed to any practical identity, he lacks reasons to act in one way over any other (121).

42 Calvin Baker That is, if a person is not governed by a conception of his identity, he will lack reasons to act and even to live (123). Most people find such a lack of reason for action and life unacceptable, for their reflective natures which are intrinsic features of humanity demand reason and justification. In a crucial argumentative step, Korsgaard deduces that in finding this lack of reason unacceptable we endorse our humanity itself as a practical normative identity (121). If we did not take our reflective humanity as normative, we would not demand reasons for actions, and so we would not find the lack of reason unacceptable. To take our humanity as normative in this way is to value our humanity itself. Moreover, valuing humanity in your own person rationally requires valuing it in the persons of others, and moral obligations arise when you value others humanity (121). Korsgaard thus concludes that demanding reasons for action entails moral values: to demand reasons for action is to affirm your reflective nature, which is to affirm your humanity, which requires you to value others humanity, which entails morality (121). We are now equipped to understand Korsgaard s response to the moral skeptic. Recall that the moral skeptic thinks he values and has reasons for acting, but does not believe he has moral obligations or values. Korsgaard denies this possibility via the above argument (123). Before assessing Korsgaard s response to the moral skeptic, I will consider her response to the radical skeptic, as it further clarifies her position. The Radical Skeptic The radical skeptic is someone who denies the existence of value itself. The radical skeptic embraces complete normative skepticism, so he must also deny that there is a reason for any action. Rather than acting for values or reasons, he follows his prevailing desires on a moment-to-moment basis, unable to even act on hypothetical imperatives. One must have an end in order to act on a hypothetical imperative, but ends are things people have reasons to pursue, and since the radical skeptic does not have reasons for action, he cannot have ends. Furthermore, if his ends are simply objects of momentary desires, there can be no practically incorrect

Korsgaard s Metaethics 43 action, since every action he takes will be in pursuit of a desire and thus an end. If there is no incorrect action, though, there is no normativity, so the radical skeptic cannot follow normative hypothetical imperatives (Korsgaard 162 64). Korsgaard links radical skepticism to suicide. Remember that in Korsgaard s view, valuing is an integral fact of life for reflective beings like humans: we confer value on certain things (our loved ones, happiness, success, etc.) and believe that our actions are backed by reasons. To reject value, therefore, is to reject life (161). Of course, radical skeptics do not have to kill themselves for internal rational consistency, as they have no reasons or values with which to be consistent. It is rather that continuing to live requires rational action, so lacking rational action points one towards suicide. If people kill themselves due to sincere radical skepticism, they have not violated any of their own values or reasons (for these do not exist), so they cannot be said to have done wrong. Unfortunately, radical skepticism is possible, and Korsgaard admits she is not equipped to answer the radical skeptic, judging that an answer which would involve convincing the skeptic that life and humanity are valuable would require more than philosophical argument. Korsgaard s system therefore does not prove that we must or should value anything. It simply says that most people do value, from which moral obligation follows. In assessing Korsgaard s response to the radical skeptic, the first item I note is that much philosophical skepticism is insincere. Consider archetypal skeptical scenarios in epistemology: how do we know that our entire life experience is not fabricated by an evil demon? How do we know that we are not dreaming when we think we are awake? How do we know that we are not brains floating in vats, controlled by neuroscientists to simulate real life experiences? Proponents of such skeptical scenarios (I should hope) do not truly believe in evil demons, dream lives, and brains in vats. They advance such skeptical arguments to test theories of knowledge: can the theory in question explain why the skeptical scenario is false or not a concern? If not, the theory requires improvement. This may at first appear to be a false analogy: epistemological skepticism is unlike moral skepticism, and certainly unlike the type of radical skepticism Korsgaard describes. I agree that epistemological

44 Calvin Baker skepticism is unlike Korsgaard s radical skepticism, but I do think that the type of insincere skepticism I described will eliminate some people from the list of potential radical skeptics. But what about those who are skeptical on a deeper level those who claim to be radical skeptics, and not just for the purpose of testing moral theories? I think we can eliminate many of these people from the list of radical skeptics as well. My suspicion is that many of these people really do value something. If we were to assess their honest reactions to footage of the Holocaust, for example, or to tragic events happening to their families, friends, or even acquaintances, we would discover values, and not simply the momentary desire states Korsgaard attributes to the radical skeptic. In providing the above example I do not mean to be gauche or abrasive, but to show that the vast majority of people really do have values, even if extreme circumstances are necessary to reveal them. Even after eliminating these would-be radical skeptics, however, I concede that a small fraction of humanity might remain that values nothing whatsoever. What I have attempted to show is that the final list of radical skeptics contains very few names. Regarding this list, I agree with Korsgaard that philosophy alone is insufficient to overcome their skepticism. A somewhat tenuous analogy might compare the situation to trying to convince a determined Biblical literalist that the earth is older than four thousand and some odd years. A person in that situation could have the best possible philosophical arguments and still fail to convince the literalist. Of course, the flaw in the analogy is that whereas the literalist and his interlocutor disagree over an objective matter of fact, the radical skeptic and her interlocutor do not they disagree whether life is worth living and whether anything is worthy of value. What the analogy does illustrate is the intractable difficulty of convincing a resolute skeptic that his position is mistaken. Assessing Korsgaard s Response to Moral and Radical Skeptics Korsgaard s concession to the radical skeptic ushers in a related worry about her answer to the moral skeptic. The worry runs as follows: at most, Korsgaard shows that if you value anything or demand reasons for action, you are committed to valuing your own

Korsgaard s Metaethics 45 humanity, from which valuing others humanity and thus moral obligation follows. In logical form, then, Korsgaard s conclusion is a conditional of the form <(A v B) g C> where A is valuing anything, B is acting for reasons, and C is having moral values and obligations. However, as Korsgaard admits in her discussion of the radical skeptic, there is no proof that we ought to value anything or demand reasons. There is no proof for A or B; they are contingent. Therefore, Korsgaard s entire moral system and thus her response to the moral skeptic is groundless, for it rests on contingent features that we are not obligated to have. I do not think this criticism weighs too heavily in Korsgaard s disfavor. I agree that her moral system is in one sense groundless, since there is no objective necessity for A or B. However, as I argued in my treatment of the radical skeptic, I think that de facto almost everyone does fulfill A and B, so if Korsgaard s conditional is valid, it supplies the sought-after consequent (moral obligation) for the vast majority. Moreover, operating under the worldview presented to us by twenty-first century scientific progress, I think appealing to a nearly universal feature of humanity that is relatively uncontroversial (the facts of valuing and acting for reasons) is a palatable foundation for amoral system that binds almost everyone. Korsgaard sacrifices absolute moral objectivity (the radical skeptics are left out) but avoids appealing to more tenuous foundations like J. L. Mackie s queer entities (intrinsic values in the fabric of reality) or G. E. Moore s spooky non-natural properties. However, Simon Blackburn advances a similar worry in his essay Truth, Beauty, and Goodness that highlights the issue presented by the radical skeptic. The worry is that moral value and obligation must be of the same objective status as the rigid commands of logic and mathematics, and not, as Korsgaard has it, contingent on practical human standpoints (Blackburn 26). Blackburn explains that some people accordingly split ethical theorists between those who think humans somehow detect mind-independent values and those who think that humans create values (27). Falling into the latter camp, Korsgaard is subject to the criticism that morality depends on contingent human characteristics, and one need not go far out into logical space to find scenarios in which anything goes, and this upsets people (27). (Blackburn thinks that the motivation

46 Calvin Baker behind this split between ethical theorists is deeply misguided, but it is not my aim here to assess Blackburn s quasi-realist project [27, 33]. I will simply consider the objection he raises.) This worry about the contingent status of Korsgaard s ethical system applies especially to the radical skeptic. Korsgaard says of the radical skeptic who kills himself that it is hard to say of one who commits such suicide that he has done wrong, for he has violated no value in which he believes (162 63). Further, Korsgaard denies radical skeptics can even follow hypothetical imperatives, for there is no normativity if you cannot be wrong, which the radical skeptic cannot be, as she simply follows her momentary desires (164). It seems, then, that the radical skeptic is exempt from morality under Korsgaard s system. However, moral exemption appears problematic, for if the radical skeptic has a momentary desire to physically assault someone and acts on that desire, the assault is still (at least prima facie) immoral. Here, the intuition discussed by Blackburn arises: unjustified physical assault is immoral, regardless of the perpetrator s status as a radical skeptic or not. If Korsgaard s system does not allow us to say that the radical skeptic behaves unethically in this situation and similar scenarios, I take it as a point against the system. A final worry about Korsgaard s system takes the form of a Euthyphro dilemma, which proposes that either the reflective human standpoint has moral obligations or it does not (Bagnoli 7.3 ). If it does not, we have no reason to assume that the moral principles it arrives at will properly ground ethics (Bagnoli 7.3 ). If it does, we are committed to moral realism and should abandon the constructivist project (Bagnoli 7.3 ). A parallel formulation of the dilemma proposes that Korsgaard s reflective, practical reasoning process either makes tacit moral assumptions, or it does not. If it does not, again, why would it ground ethics? If it does, it is circular a system that purports to ground ethics cannot make substantive ethical assumptions. Korsgaard s response to both versions of the dilemma is to claim that the reflective standpoint is not subject to mind-independent values but that reflective, practical reasoning makes no moral assumptions. The process of nonetheless outputs an almost objective groundwork for ethics, for it contains non-arbitrary structural elements and internal rules that appeal to common aspects of humanity (Bagnoli 7.3 ).

Korsgaard s Metaethics 47 To assess Korsgaard s response, we must scrutinize the conclusion of the reflective reasoning process in which she claims to derive morality. Up to this point in the dialectic, we are supposed to have realized that our practical identities give us reasons for action, and we now wonder: is there any identity that is not contingent? Korsgaard reasons that if we lack commitment to any practical identity, we lack reason to act in one way over the other (120 21). We thus commit to various practical identities to give us reasons to act. The cause of this commitment is our felt imperative to have reasons to act, which we feel insofar as we treat our humanity as a practical, normative, form of identity. In valuing ourselves as human beings we must value the humanity of others: a coherent Caligula, who has a robust set of reasons but cares not for others, is impossible. I d like to put pressure on Korsgaard s step where she claims that people only demand reasons for their actions if they treat their humanity as normative. Consider an egocentric hedonist who cares only about his own pleasure. Such a hedonist is not like the radical skeptic, for he does not simply follow his momentary desires. Instead, he carefully plans his life so as to maximize his own pleasure. He is capable of following hypothetical imperatives, for he can be wrong about his actions: he may be mistaken as to which path will maximize his pleasure. It is unclear that such a person must treat his humanity as normative or value his humanity. He may demand reasons for his actions only insofar as he cares about successfully maximizing his own pleasure not because his human nature demands a justification for this desire and therefore not care at all about his status as a human being. I think this is why critics see the step in question as a tacit realist commitment to the value of humanity and thus accuse Korsgaard of circularity (Bagnoli 7.3 ). My objection does not discount Korsgaard s system. It is still possible that some people do demand reasons and endorse their reflective natures as Korsgaard details. For these people, Korsgaard s link to morality stands. However, if my objection is valid, there may be people like the hedonist who demand reasons and value certain things without endorsing their humanity. As they do not endorse their humanity, they are not rationally compelled to endorse that of others, so the reflective chain to moral obligation is broken. Therefore, Korsgaard cannot answer all moral skeptics: she can only answer those who, when honest, admit that they take their human identity as normative.

Works Cited Bagnoli, Carla. 2.2: Procedural realism. In Constructivism in Metaethics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Spring 2015 ed. Accessed December 3, 2015.. 7.3: Constructivism and constitutivism. In Constructivism in Metaethics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Spring 2015 ed. Accessed December 3, 2015. Blackburn, Simon. Truth, Beauty, and Goodness. In Practical Tortoise Raising: And Other Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2010. Oxford Scholarship Online. Accessed December 7, 2015. Korsgaard, Christine M. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1996. Núñez, Carlos. Philosophy 90N: Lecture 12. Lecture, Stanford University, October 29, 2015.. Philosophy 90N: Lecture 13. Lecture, Stanford University, November 3, 2015.