KEVIN WILDES has argued in a recent note that the distinction be-

Similar documents
On Withdrawing Artificial Nutrition and Hydration

MEDICAL DILEMMAS AND MORAL DECISION-MAKING

Withholding or Withdrawing of Artificial Nutrition and Hydration

Ethical Issues at the End of Life Copyright 2008 Richard M. Gula, S.S., Ph.D.

Caring for People at the End of Life

NOTES THE DUTY TO PRESERVE LIFE

The Ethics of Withholding/Withdrawing Nutrition and Hydration

Ordinary & Extraordinary Treatment: An Ethical Perspective Dr Alan J. Kearns Beaumont Palliative Care Study Day

Preparing Now for the Hour of Our Death

SEMINAR ON HUMAN DIGNITY AND ETHICAL CHALLENGES IN THE BEGINNING AND END STAGES OF HUMAN LIFE PART TWO: DYING WITH DIGNITY AND IN CHRISTIAN SERENITY

Virtual Mentor American Medical Association Journal of Ethics May 2007, Volume 9, Number 5:

EUTHANASIA EUTHANASIA NEWS IN CANADA

Now and at the Hour of Our Death. A Pastoral Letter from the Roman Catholic Bishops of Wisconsin on End of Life Decisions

Chapter 13 Ten Errors Regarding End of Life Issues, and Especially Artificial Nutrition and Hydration

Discourse about bioethics is plagued by the appearance of simplicity. The

Rabbi Moshe I. Hauer

A lesson on end-of-life issues: The Grace of a Peaceful Death. Presented to a Franciscan Fraternity Robert Baral,MDiv,RN,BCC,OFS 7/15/2018

Iura et bona Declaration on Euthanasia Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, May 5, 1980

Ethical and Religious Directives: A Brief Tour

HAVING ONE S WORK READ CLOSELY and being taken seriously by one s

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

On the Alleged Incoherence of Consequentialism. by Robert Mckim and Peter Simpson

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Now and at the Hour of Our Death

John Paul II: Dying with Dignity

Romans: The Revealing of Righteousness (part 6 of 9) The Law and Judgment

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles

Caring for Those with Life-Threating Illness

With Whom Are We To Pray? [Delivered to the South Central Circuit Conference, April 25-26, 1978] By Randall J. Bartelt Whenever we pray together with

Spinoza s Ethics. Ed. Jonathan Bennett Early Modern Texts

Health Care A Catholic Perspective

The Basics on Advance Directives

FORCING COHEN TO ABANDON FORCED SUPEREROGATION

On Law. (1) Eternal Law: God s providence over and plan for all of Creation. He writes,

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

The Ethical Canary: Science, Society, and the Human Spirit (2000, ISBN )

Anthropology and death

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

GENERAL SYNOD OF THE CHURCH OF ENGLAND AMENDING CANON 38

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

I got a right! By Tim Sprod

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Loving Like Jesus #4 Being Self-Giving

DEFINITIONS GUIDELINES. and. for DISCIPLINE

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Muslim Perspectives on Hospice Care: Problems with Letting Go. Shahbaz Hasan Infectious Diseases Hospice and Palliative Care APPNA-July 2018, Dallas

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

Christian Conscience in Healthcare

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

EMPLOYMENT APPLICATION

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

Same-Sex Marriage, Just War, and the Social Principles

ACIM Edmonton - Sarah's Reflections. LESSON 135 If I defend myself, I am attacked.

PHILOSOPHY AND THE GOOD LIFE

Changing Roman Catholic Attitudes Toward Termination of Life-Sustaining Treatments

In most instances, the use of artificial nutrition

Sanctity of Life (Pikuach Nefesh)

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

ARTIFICIAL NUTRITION AND HYDRATION

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

4. Issues with regard to particular denominations

REVIEWS 36 The second chapter is entitled Blindness, Narrative, and Meaning. This chapter sets up a defense of three central normative claims: that we

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

INTERPERSONAL EFFECTIVENESS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

THE EUTHANASIA DEBATE: ASSESSING THE OPTIONS (Part Two in a Two-Part Series on Euthanasia)

Position Paper. Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

A Heart Which Sees : On Being Neighbor

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

UNDERCOVER POLICING INQUIRY

THE CENTRALITY OF THE GOSPEL: PART 1

FORGIVENESS CAN SET YOU FREE! (02/25/18) Scripture Lessons: Psalm 139: 1-6, Luke 7:36-50; 23:34

THE RIGHT TO DIE: AN OPTION FOR THE ELDERLY. Anonymous

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

by scientists in social choices and in the dialogue leading to decision-making.

Ethical Analysis: PRINCIPLISM. Patrick T. Smith, Ph.D.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Jewish Medical Directives for Health Care

Exodus 2:1-10 First Presbyterian, Pasadena John 19:25b-27 May 13, A MOTHER S LOVE James S. Currie

THE CHRISTIAN HOME. Agenda: What is our responsibility regarding physical health? What is our financial responsibility?

LUIGI GIUSSANI THE MEANING OF CHARITABLE WORK

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

FIGHT? FLIGHT? or something better? Grace Munro, Editor

In the name of Allah, the Beneficent and Merciful S/5/100 report 1/12/1982 [December 1, 1982] Towards a worldwide strategy for Islamic policy (Points

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Pastoral Code of Conduct

Submission to the Religious Freedom Review February Independent Schools and Religious Freedom

Occasional Paper 7. Survey of Church Attenders Aged Years: 2001 National Church Life Survey

Catholic Teaching Avoids Extremes

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

CANON 8 Of Parish Status and Oversight - DRAFT September 2017

The Trolley Problem. 11 Judith Jarvith Thomson Killing, Letting Die and the Trolley Problem (1976) 59 Oxford University Press 204-

THE ASSUMPTIONS OF THEOLOGY

Agreement-Based Practical Justification: A Comment on Wolff

Life, Lottery, for the Pursuit of Organs

Intubation of the Irreversibly Comatose: A Response to Robert Barry, O.P.

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

Transcription:

Theological Studies 58 (1997) QUAESTIO DISPUTATA ORDINARY AND EXTRAORDINARY TREATMENTS: WHEN DOES QUALITY OF LIFE COUNT? GILBERT MEILAENDER [Editor's Note: Kevin Wildes recently argued in this journal that the distinction between ordinary and extraordinary treatments requires judgments about quality of life. The author of this response suggests that Wildes is correct in his general claim about the nature of these judgments, but that he fails to note the important moral issues that arise when others must make treatment decisions for incapacitated patients. Then quality-of-life judgments are inappropriate; they must be avoided in order to respect that patient's actual condition.] KEVIN WILDES has argued in a recent note that the distinction be-. tween ordinary and extraordinary treatments involves judgments about quality of Ufe, that some recent statements by Roman Catholic bishops have failed to see this, and that, as a result, their judgments about feeding and hydrating patients in a persistent vegetative state have been flawed. 1 Wildes is correct, I believe, when he says that choices patients make about their own treatment involve judgments about quality of life, but he fails to take account of the substantially different moral situation that arises when others make treatment decisions for incapacitated patients. Once we see this, we may be considerably more sympathetic than he is to those episcopal statements that are critical of decisions to deny food and water to patients in a persistent vegetative state. The basic distinction between ordinary and extraordinary treatments is nicely expressed by Wildes in a summary statement: "A treatment is morally obligatory if and only if it offers a benefit and does not impose burden. Neither condition is sufficient by itself." 2 Putting it in terms of what is nonobligatory, we can say that a treatment may be refused if it is either useless or burdensome. Both of these judgments GILBERT MEILAENDER received his Ph.D.fromPrinceton University. He currently holds the Board of Directors Chair in Christian Ethics at Valparaiso University, Indiana. He has recently published two books in the area of his specialization, Body, Soul, and Bioethics (Notre Dame, 1995) and Bioethics: A Primer for Christians (Eerdmans, 1996). 1 Kevin W. Wildes, S.J., "Ordinary and Extraordinary Means and the Quality of Life," TS 57 (1996) 500-12. 2 Ibid. 511. 527

528 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES are relative to the condition of a particular patient at a particular point in time. What is useless treatment for one patient may be useful for another; what was once useful treatment for a patient may cease to be so when progression of the disease has made a marked change in his or her condition. A burden that one person considers too great to bear may not seem unbearable to another. Thus, we can rightly say, as Wildes does, that deciding to refuse a treatment is not necessarily deciding to end one's life. It may, rather, be a decision about how to live. Of the several life choices available to patients, they may choose a life that is shorter but relatively less burdened by treatments. But still, they choose life. Nor is there any need to object to Wildes's desire to characterize such choices as "quality of life" choices. Several life choices are available. The character and duration of these lives differ in various ways which might reasonably affect a person's preference for one or another. And from these the patient chooses one that will be his or her life. So far so good. What Wildes does not explore, however, is how best to characterize such choices made by patients. Insofar as he occasionally turns to the language of "proportionate or disproportionate" treatments and the language of "weighing" burdens and benefits, he uses a metaphor that may deceive us. Patients making such choices may consider the importance to themselves of personal aspirations still unrealized, the burden and expense of proposed treatments, their responsibilities to others and countless other factors significant in their lives. But these competing factors are not being "weighed," for they are incommensurable, and the scale on which they could be weighed does not exist. In short, when such patients choose to accept or refuse treatment, they are not making a discovery about some single right choice to make in their circumstances. Precisely because these determinations are, as Wildes underscores, patient-relative, such patients are making a decision. The patient determines, within the limits available, his or her being. Two people similarly situated may make different decisions; yet both may be choices of life. He chooses a life that is shorter but relatively free of painful treatments. She chooses a life that is somewhat longer but more painful. Neither makes a discovery about what everyone in similar circumstances must choose or even about what he or she must choose. Both make decisions about who they will be. Or, if we insist on using the language of "discovery" and "weighing," we must mean that the relative weight of the conflicting goods is known and known only for the person deciding after the decision has been made. The only discovery we make in such circumstances is a discovery of something about ourselves, the kind of people we will be because we have so chosen. A life of "poor quality" is simply a life that we would not, given alternatives, choose for ourselves. Because this is what it means to take seriously the patient-relative character of decisions about treatment, a large gap opens up in Wildes's argument. He consistently blurs the important distinction

ORDINARY AND EXTRAORDINARY TREATMENTS 529 between refusing treatment for oneself or refusing it for another. If Wildes's refusal of treatment expresses something of the person he has chosen to be, it does not tell us what treatments I ought to accept or refuse. And, more important here, it does not tell us anything about what treatments should be given to or withheld from patients who are unable to participate in their own treatment decisions. To suppose that decisions about their treatment should somehow mirror his choices or mine is merely to impose one vision of a choiceworthy life upon a subject who has not, and cannot, make that vision his own or her own. Once we begin to see where Wildes's argument takes us, we might wish to pull back from it and, indeed, I think we should pull back just a little. Pulling back, we will be less skittish than Wildes is about "objectifying" treatment decisions. If, for example, at age 25,1 refuse on the ground that "I just don't like needles" the antibiotics that promise to cure the pneumonia threatening my life, others should not suppose that I am simply choosing one life (a rather short one) from among the several life choices still open to me. They should quite rightly have a hard time imagining my decision to be anything other than a choice of death, which, on the position Wildes accepts, is a morally forbidden choice. So I am not utterly free (morally) to determine my being in any way I wish, and in order to make that clear we must, to a limited extent, "objectify" treatment decisions. In doing so, I do not believe we misrepresent traditional teaching. Or if we do, we do so in order to provide it with a needed corrective and development. But a still more important "objectification" of treatment decisions is needed and appropriate. When patients are unable to participate in decisions about their treatment, when they are unable to determine their being in that way, we must decide how they should be treated. We cannot decide who they will be, not because we ought not, but simply because we cannot. All we can do is take the criteria for refusal of treatment developed by Wildes himself that refusals are appropriate only if treatment is either useless or excessively burdensome and apply them as best we can to decisions about treatment for patients who are unconscious or incompetent. We must objectify these decisions because we are not the subjects involved. And our own judgment about what life we would choose for ourselves from the available alternatives ought not to be imposed on subjects who cannot speak for themselves. From this perspective the issue of providing nourishment to patients in a persistent vegetative state looks rather different. We must ask: Is the provision of such nourishment useless? Is it burdensome? How can nourishment that sustains the life of a human being be considered useless? Wildes needs to face that question squarely. Here is where the importance of the episcopal statements' references to patients who are not "imminently terminal" is important. Wildes's response that the ordinary/extraordinary distinction does not traditionally apply only to patients who are terminal is here beside the point. The point, rather, is that for a patient who is not a dying patient who may, in fact, live

530 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES for years if fed it is difficult to claim that such feeding is useless. Is it burdensome? It is rather hard to argue that patients in a persistent vegetative state will experience feeding as burdensome. But, then, if we withdraw care that is neither useless nor burdensome, it looks as if we are rejecting not the treatment but the life. We are deciding not to nourish these patients so that they will die. Perhaps, of course, it is a burden to the rest of us to feed them. Wildes sometimes seems to flirt with such possibilities when he speaks of treatments that are burdensome to the patient or to others, but I think he means only to suggest that patients who are competent may rightly think about how much burden they want to impose on others. It is quite a different matter if we say, "We should stop feeding these patients because doing so burdens us." It is hard to think ofthat as, in any sense, choosing life. On the contrary, we cease to nourish them so that they will die and thereby relieve us of the burden their continued lives constitute. I think, therefore, that it is quite appropriate to "objectify" treatment decisions for patients who cannot speak for themselves, and I doubt whether episcopal statements that do so are, in fact, departing from the traditional meaning of the distinction between ordinary and extraordinary treatments. That historical question, however, I must leave to others more qualified. If such statements do in fact depart from the tradition, they are wise to do so. For such a departure is necessary in order to respect the moral limit Wildes himself acknowledges, namely, our "perfect" obligation not to take innocent human life intentionally. It is also mistaken to suggest that those opposing removal of feeding and hydration are somehow in thrall to "an incomplete model of medicine" or "a modern secularized view of medicine." On the contrary, rather than abstracting the body from the person, they assume that where the living body is the person must also be. Rather than neglecting the subjective, they assume that where it is absent the choices of another subject ought not to be imposed. The person is respected precisely in his or her actual condition. In short, Wildes's explication and application of the traditional distinction goes astray because it fails to take seriously the difference between patients who can participate in their own decisions and patients (such as those in a persistent vegetative state) who cannot. One might, of course, argue that this gap can and will be bridged as people are encouraged to enact advance directives. We may settle for that as a social and legal compromise, but I doubt whether a satisfying defense of it can really be offered. 3 If, as Wildes suggest, we ought not to isolate any single treatment decisionfrom the context of a patient's entire life, neither ought we to isolate one moment in life and suppose that it can 3 I try to make this case at much greater length in Body, Soul, and Bioethics (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1995) chap. 2.

ORDINARY AND EXTRAORDINARY TREATMENTS 531 or should be determinative of the rest of the life. But that is an argument for another time. Here I am concerned only to suggest that when Wildes writes that choices to refuse either useless or burdensome treatments are decisions "by a patient or a designated decision-maker about the quality of life" he confusingly conflates the cases of those who can speak for themselves and those who cannot. For those who can, decisions about quality of life, as long as they can honestly be understood as life choices, should be relatively unproblematic. But for those who cannot, such quality-of-life judgments made for them by others constitute a failure to honor the place they occupy and the time they have. "...one of the journals that has to be read..." PACIFICA JOURNAL OF THE MELBOURNE COLLEGE OF DIVINITY Volume 10 Number 3 October 1997 God, Church, and Context Suzanne Boorer, "The Dark Side of God? A Dialogue with Jung's Interpretation of the Book of Job". David Rankin, "Tertullian and the Crucified God". Beth R. Crisp, "Seeking the Feminine: An Exploration of the Spiritual Writings of Hildegard of Bingen and Julian of Norwich". James T. Bretzke, "Cracking the Code: Minjung Theology as an Expression of the Holy Spirit in Korea". Neil Ormerod, "Church, Anti-Types, and Ordained Ministry: Systematic Perspectives". Geoffrey Lilburne, "Contextualising Australian Theology: An Inquiry into Method". Annual Subscription: $40.00 Pacifica, P.O. Box 271, Brunswick East, Vic 3057, Australia