A flaw in Kripke s modal argument? Kripke states his modal argument against the description theory of names at a number

Similar documents
Kripke s Naming and Necessity. Against Descriptivism

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

If I hadn t studied as much as I did, I wouldn t have passed my exams.

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Analyticity and reference determiners

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

A User's Guide to Proper Names, Their Pragmatics and Semantics Pilatova, Anna

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Generalizing Soames Argument Against Rigidified Descriptivism

Reply to Robert Koons

Against the Contingent A Priori

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Correspondence via the backdoor and other stories 1

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 73, No. 1; March 1995

An argument against descriptive Millianism

NAMING WITHOUT NECESSITY

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Varieties of Apriority

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Naming Natural Kinds. Åsa Maria Wikforss Stockholm University Department of Philosophy Stockholm

Act individuation and basic acts

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Epistemic two-dimensionalism and the epistemic argument

ROBUST BELIEF STATES AND THE RIGHT/WRONG DICHOTOMY. Robert Stainton

Logic & Metaphysics Allan Gibbard Contingent Identity Notes

Cognitivism about imperatives

Some T-Biconditionals

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

NAMES AND OBSTINATE RIGIDITY Brendan Murday Ithaca College

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Identity and Plurals

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Russell on Descriptions

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Leibniz and Krikpe on Trans-World Identity

Dispositionalism and the Modal Operators

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

ON CONSIDERING A POSSIBLE WORLD AS ACTUAL. by Robert Stalnaker and Thomas Baldwin. II Thomas Baldwin

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Constructing the World

Unnecessary Existents. Joshua Spencer University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

Que sera sera. Robert Stone

Constructing the World

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Theories of propositions

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Scott Soames Two-Dimensionalism

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem

Transcription:

A flaw in Kripke s modal argument? Kripke states his modal argument against the description theory of names at a number of places (1980: 53, 57, 61, and 74). A full statement in the original text of Naming and Necessity on page 61 is as follows: The [description theorist] would say that the name is simply defined synonymously, as the cluster of descriptions. It will then be necessary, not that Moses had any particular property in this cluster, but that he had the disjunction of them. There couldn t be any counterfactual situation in which he didn t do any of these things... Such a suggestion must clearly be false... Most of the things commonly attributed to Aristotle are things Aristotle might not have done at all. In a nutshell the intended argument is this. All proper names are rigid designators. Any descriptions (at least of contingently existent objects like Moses and Aristotle) which can be at all plausibly thought of as fixing their references, given what the users of the names believe and intend (in the case of Aristotle, descriptions referring to achievements commonly attributed to him) are accidental designators. So such descriptions are not substitutable salva veritate for proper names in modal contexts and hence a fortiori are never synonymous with them. The response to Kripke s modal argument I shall put forward appeals to the distinction between indicative descriptions, i.e., descriptions formed using indicative verb forms, and what I shall call subjunctive descriptions, descriptions formed using non-indicative verb forms used in subjunctive conditionals. The distinction is between the person who is richer than anyone else in the world and the book Mary is reading, on the one hand, and the person who would have been richer than anyone else in the world and the book Mary would have been reading on the other. The 1

response is that indicative descriptions are indeed always rigid designators and so do not contrast with proper names. 1 The distinction is noted by John Burgess (2006: 175). He comments that:... even when discussing a counterfactual situation in which Bill Gates has given all his wealth to Ivana Trump, it is not unambiguously the case that when we use the description the richest person in the world we must be referring to her and not to him. For the description contains an implicit verb, made explicit in the one person to be richer than anyone else in the world. And this verb is subject to inflection for grammatical mood to be may become the indicative is or the conditional would have been in a way that creates a flexibility of reference. Thus If Bill Gates had given all his wealth to Ivana, the richest person in the world would have been female is ambiguous between the truth If Bill had given all his wealth to Ivana, the one person who would have been richer than anyone else in the world... would have been female and the falsehood If Bill had given all his wealth to Ivana, the one person who is richer than anyone else in the world would have been female. Since the latter is unambiguously false the one person who is richer than anyone else in the world designates rigidly. The distinction between the two types of description can be confirmed by noting the difference between the questions If Bill had given half his money to Ivana, who would have been the person who would have had more money than anyone else in the world? and If Bill had given half his money to Ivana, who would have been the person who has more money than anyone else in the world? The answer to the first question may be, say, J.K. Rowling (suppose Bill 1 To insist on the significance of the distinction between subjunctive and indicative verb forms is, of course, not to deny entailments between subjunctive and indicative conditionals. If Mary came to the party she would have taken the car. Mary didn t take the car. So Mary didn t come to the party is valid since the first premiss entails if Mary came to the party she took the car. But it is not an instance of modus tollens. 2

has 100 billion dollars, J.K. 80, Ivana 20, and no one else is close). The answer to the second question is, trivially, Bill. For another illustration consider the case of Mary, an elderly Englishwoman, and her elderly English husband Tom. Mary s parents had contemplated emigrating to Australia before her birth. On the balance of probabilities, the following is true: (1) If Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth, the man she would now have been married to would have been an Australian as is: (2) If Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth, the man she is now married to would never have met her. But the following is false: (3) If Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth, the man she would now have been married to would never have met her as is: (4) If Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth, the man she is now married to would have been an Australian. On the other hand if Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth her current husband would have been an Australian and if Mary s parents had emigrated before her birth her current husband would never have met her are ambiguous, since her current husband, like the richest man in the world is a flexible designator. Consequently, Mary s current husband might not have been Mary s current husband is ambiguous. But the man Mary is now married to might not have been the man Mary is now married to is false, whilst the man Mary is now married to might not have been the man Mary was now married to is true, since the man Mary is now 3

married to would not have been the man Mary was now married to if her parents had emigrated before her birth. So it appears that present tense indicative descriptions in English, like the ones given, or, for example, the book Mary is now reading are rigid designators. The same is true of all future tense indicative descriptions, e.g., the person who will give the John Locke Lectures in 2150, the book Mary will be reading next month. Past tense descriptions, e.g., the book Mary was reading last month, are ambiguous: If Mary had joined a different book club, the book Mary was reading last month would not have been have been the book Mary was reading last month, has a true interpretation because the past tense is ambiguous between an indicative and subjunctive reading. This also accounts for the ambiguity of If Mary had been sicker on Monday than Jane was on Tuesday (contrast the unambiguous If Mary had been sicker on Monday than Jane is today which unambiguously makes a crosscomparison between how things would have been in a counterfactual circumstance and how things are). Past tense descriptions are rigid on the indicative reading. In the case of the rigid present tense description the book Mary is now reading flexibility can be introduced by change to the passive voice and omission of the tensed verb: If she had changed book clubs the book now being read by Mary would not have been have been the book now being read by Mary has a true interpretation (note that the temporal indexical does not impose modal rigidity and can also occur in subjunctive descriptions like the man Mary would now have been married to, the book Mary would now have been reading ). Hence, in Kripke s terms, the book Mary is now reading, if there is such a thing, is the book now being read by Mary expresses a contingent a priori truth. Insertion of the rigidifying adverb actually to yield the book actually being read by Mary now brings back rigidity. The only descriptions 4

which can be non-rigid, then, are ones, like Mary s current husband, the richest person in the world and the inventor of bifocals, not containing tensed indicative verbs. If this is correct Kripke s modal argument in Lecture One of Naming and Necessity fails, since rigid descriptions constructed using tensed indicative verbs will always be available, if any descriptions are, as equivalents for proper names. If this is accepted what is to be the response to the refined Preface version of the modal argument in Naming and Necessity? Here the modal argument goes as follows, adapted to Burgess s example. Suppose I fix the reference of a name Richie by the description the person who has more money than anyone else in the world. Then the simple, non-modal, sentence Richie is a female unambiguously expresses something that could not have been true. On the other hand the simple, non-modal sentence the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is a female does not. Hence the name and description differ in a way that the description theorist cannot accommodate. But why think that Richie is female unambiguously expresses something that could not have been true? Presumably because Richie is Bill Gates and so it couldn t have been that Richie was female (assuming one s gender is an essential property). But then it couldn t have been that the person who has more money than anyone else in the world was female (though it could have been that the richest person in the world/the person who had more money than anyone else was female, as it would have been if Bill had given all his money to Ivana). And both It could have been that Richie is a female and It could have been that the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is a female are ungrammatical (contrast the grammatical It could be that Richie/the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is 5

a female ). But, a defender of Kripke s argument may rejoin, is it not the case that with respect to certain counterfactual circumstances, e.g., if Bill Gates had given all his money to Ivana, what Richie is a pauper says would have been true, whereas with respect to those circumstances, what the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is a pauper says would not have been true? But why say that with respect to those circumstances what Richie is a pauper says would have been true? Because it is unambiguously true that if those circumstances had obtained Richie would have been a pauper. But, equally, it is unambiguously true that if those circumstances had obtained the person who has more money than anyone else in the world would have been a pauper, though, of course, it is not the case that if those circumstances had obtained the person who would have had more money than anyone else in the world would have been a pauper. When asked whether what Richie is a pauper says might have been true I answer the question by asking whether it might have been true that Richie was a pauper, i.e., whether there is a way things could have been such that if things had been that way it would have been that Richie was a pauper. When asked whether what the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is pauper says might have been true I answer the question by asking whether it might have been true that the person who has more money than anyone else in the world was a pauper, i.e. whether there is a way things could have been such that if things had been that way it would have been that the person who has more money than anyone else in the world was a pauper. In both cases I must answer affirmatively, though, of course, I acknowledge that there are no ways thing could have been such that if things had been those ways it would have been the case that the person who had more money than anyone else in the world was a pauper. Consider the following passage (Kripke 1977: 259-60): 6

If definite descriptions, ιxφ(x), are taken as primitive and assigned reference, then the conventional non-rigid assignment assigns to such a description, with respect to each possible world, the unique object, if any, which would have φ d in that world. For example, the number of planets denotes eight, speaking of a counterfactual situation where there would have been eight planets. Another type of definite description, ιxφx, a rigid definite description, could be introduced semantically by the following stipulation: let ιxφx denote, with respect to all possible worlds, the unique object that (actually) φ s (then the number of planets is odd, as interpreted, expresses a necessary truth). Both kinds of definite descriptions can be introduced, theoretically, into a single formal language... Some have suggested that definite descriptions, in English, are ambiguous between the two readings. Note that in the semantic stipulation for the rigid description Kripke makes use of a merely parenthetical and optional actually and uses a present tense indicative verb form φ s. In the stipulation for the non-rigid description the form would have φ d is used and there is an implicit counterfactual conditional would have φ d if that world had obtained. The two stipulations are thus: ιxφ(x) is to denote, with respect to any world w, the object which would have φ d if w had obtained, ιxφx is to denote, with respect to any world w, the object which φ s. My contention is that the suggestion that definite descriptions in English are ambiguous between the two readings is partly right. Some are. Descriptions formed from indicative tensed verbs, like the person who has more money than anyone else in the world, are unambiguously rigid. But descriptions not containing tensed verbs (unless they are de facto rigid, like the square of four ), whether or not they contain 7

temporal indexicals (so long as they contain no actually rigidifier), like the richest person (at present) in the world, are ambiguous between rigid and non-rigid readings (only 2 in the sense that modal and subjunctive conditional sentences containing them have multiple readings). No descriptions capable of occurring outside subjunctive conditionals (as the person who would have had more money than anyone else in the world is not) are unambiguously non-rigid. Hence there are apparent examples, in Kripke s terms, of contingent a priori truths formed using descriptions alone: the person who has more money than anyone else in the world, if there is such a person, is the richest person in the world ; and also examples of necessary a posteriori truths formed using descriptions alone: the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is the person who owns more cars than anyone else in the world (assuming Bill Gates is both), and the person who has more money than anyone else in the world is male (assuming that Bill Gates could not have been female). Of course, the reply to Kripke s modal argument in this paper only speaks to Kripke s challenge to the descriptivist to come up with descriptions in English which may plausibly thought of as equivalent to proper names, given that such names function as rigid designators. Languages can be imagined, and of course languages actually exist, in which there is no distinction between indicative and subjunctive forms and no descriptions function as required by this response. But it is no part of the descriptivist position to deny the possibility of such languages. This is obviously so since the descriptivist can acknowledge the possibility of a language in which proper 2 To infer anything stronger would be like inferring an ambiguity in some man from the ambiguity of some man might have been immortal. Note that the ambiguities discussed in the text are present here also. If the Gods had so decreed, some man would have been immortal is ambiguous between If the Gods had so decreed, something that would have been a man would have been immortal and If the Gods had so decreed, something that is a man would have been immortal which differ in the powers they ascribe to the Gods. The same ambiguity affects If the Gods had so decreed, every man would have been immortal. 8

names occur but there are no definite descriptions at all (what Kripke (1977) calls a strong Russell language ); indeed, a descriptivist who follows Russell, for whom definite descriptions are a mere abbreviatory convenience, must insist on the possibility of such languages, expressively equivalent to languages in which definite descriptions can be formed. Thus the possibility of such languages is irrelevant to the issue between Kripke and the descriptivists. If definite descriptions formed in English using indicative verb forms are rigid designators it suffices to refute the modal argument since the second premiss of that argument is that no descriptions (at least of contingently existent objects) that can be at all plausibly thought of as synonyms of proper names (leaving aside the additional epistemological and semantic arguments given later in Naming and Necessity) are rigid designators. But indicative descriptions, like the book Mary is reading, form an extremely large class of commonplace English expressions and, notwithstanding Kripke s modal argument, are plausibly available to users of proper names as their equivalents. References Burgess, J. 2006 Saul Kripke Naming and Necessity in J. Shand (ed.) Central Works of Philosophy vol. 5. Chesham, Acumen, 166-186 Kripke, S. 1973 Naming and Necessity, in D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.). Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, 252-355. Reprinted in revised form as a monograph by Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1980. Kripke, S. 1977 Speaker s reference and semantic reference Midwest Studies in Philosophy II, 255-276 9