The Problem of Induction. Knowledge beyond experience?

Similar documents
Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

The Argument (for rationalism) from Induction. More than observation is needed

Are Scientific Theories True?

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

The Argument (for rationalism) from Induction. More than observation is needed

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

APEH ch 14.notebook October 23, 2012

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

APEH Chapter 6.notebook October 19, 2015

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

The Argument from Induction for Rationalism

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Relativism. We re both right.

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Scientific realism and anti-realism

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

The British Empiricism

1/12. The A Paralogisms

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 21

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

Bayesian Probability

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

A Priori Bootstrapping

The CopernicanRevolution

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

Cartesian Rationalism

Discussion Notes for Bayesian Reasoning

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Social Knowledge and the Role of Inductive Inference An Appraisal of Two Contemporary Approaches

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

What is science? Inflationary use of science. science < scientia < sciens < scio, scire

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

contrary to empiricism.

Class #3 - Illusion Descartes, from Meditations on First Philosophy Descartes, The Story of the Wax Descartes, The Story of the Sun

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

HIGH CONFIRMATION AND INDUCTIVE VALIDITY

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Transcription:

The Problem of Induction Knowledge beyond experience?

Huygens method One finds in this subject a kind of demonstration which does not carry with it so high a degree of certainty as that employed in geometry; and which differs distinctly from the method employed by geometers in that they prove their propositions by well-established and incontrovertible principles, while here principles are tested by the inferences which are derivable from them. The nature of the subject permits no other treatment. It is possible, however, in this way to establish a probability which is little short of certainty. This is the case when the consequences of the assumed principles are in perfect accord with the observed phenomena, and especially when these verifications are very numerous; but above all when one employs the hypothesis to predict new phenomena and finds his expectations realized.

Huygens argument has the following structure: H predicts phenomena E 1, E 2 and E 3 E 1, E 2 and E 3 are observed to occur --------------------- H is probably true

Simple test case E 1, E 2 and E 3 specify the outcomes of three tosses of a coin, say heads in each case. H 1 = this particular coin must always lands heads H 1 predicts phenomena E 1, E 2 and E 3 E 1, E 2 and E 3 are observed to occur --------------------- H is probably true (Premise 1 is true here. Also premise 2 is true. So is the conclusion true as well? Is H 1 (the claim that the coin always lands heads) probably true?

A priori improbable theory? Another argument against H 1 being probably true is the fact that it s hard to see how a coin could be made to land heads every time. The coin looks normal, let s suppose, with the Queen s head on one side and tails (no head) on the other. Before the coin is ever tossed, H 1 might seem unlikely or implausible in some sense.

Alternative hypotheses? Also, there are cases where two or more incompatible hypotheses predict the same data. E.g. if a person starts vomiting, then it could be food poisoning. Food poisoning predicts vomiting. But stomach flu also predicts vomiting, so it would be hasty to conclude that the person has food poisoning. Surely one cannot conclude that H 1 is probably true, without considering the alternatives to H 1 that predict the same data?

In other words, Huygens method is incomplete in two ways: 1. The scheme takes no account of the alternatives to H that might exist, and 2. The hypothesis H in question seems to have a low prior probability; it seems unlikely given our background information, or general knowledge of things.

Degrees of prediction In the coin-tossing example, there are many alternatives to H 1, such as the fair-coin hypothesis, that it lands head with propensity ½. Call this H 2. Does H 2 predict the data (3 heads in 3 tosses)? Sort of. But not with certainty. According to H 2, this observed outcome has probability 1/8. This probability is expressed as P(E H 2 ) and is called the likelihood of the evidence under H 2. I.e. P(E H 1 ) = 1, but P(E H 2 ) = 1/8.

Two important probabilities Prior (of the hypothesis) P K (H) = The probability of the hypothesis in the epistemic state K, prior to learning the evidence E. Likelihood (of the evidence) P K (E H) = The degree to which the hypothesis H predicts the evidence E. Assuming that H is true, how likely is E to occur?

The strength of a hypothesis According to Bayes theorem (1764), Huygens method is basically on the right track, but needs to be supplemented. To use Bayes theorem, one has gather the total data (call it E) and then enumerate all the possible hypotheses that could possibly explain E. Call the hypotheses H 1, H 2, H 3, (etc.) Then one has to calculate the strength of each hypothesis as an explanation of E. Strength(H i ) = P K (E H i )P K (H i )

Bayes thorem I.e. a strong explanation of E is both plausible (prior to the data) and predicts the evidence well. Bayes s theorem then can be expressed as: P K ( H 1 E) Strength( H 1 ) Strength( H Strength( H 2 ) 1 )... Strength( H n. )

Coin example again In the coin example, the always heads hypothesis H 1 beats the fair coin hypothesis H 2 in predicting the data. But perhaps the fair coin hypothesis has higher prior probability? For example, if P(H 1 ) = 1/100, but P(H 2 ) = 99/100, then which hypothesis is a stronger explanation of the evidence? What is the posterior probability of each hypothesis?

E.g. What s up with Saturn? In 1610 Galileo looked at Saturn through his telescope and saw something like the image below. How do we best explain this data?

Competing Hypotheses H 1 : Saturn is a composite of 3 planets, with two equal small planets flanking the main one. H 2 : Saturn is a giant soup tureen, with handles. H 3 : Saturn has a flat ring around its equator

1 st Hypothesis: a triple planet On 30 July 1610 Galileo he wrote to his Medici patron: the star of Saturn is not a single star, but is a composite of three, which almost touch each other, never change or move relative to each other, and are arranged in a row along the zodiac, the middle one being three times larger than the lateral ones, and they are situated in this form:

2 nd Hypothesis: Giant Soup Tureen (Galileo never proposed this theory. But he did say that Saturn appeared to have handles, or ears.)

3 rd Hypothesis: A Ring In 1655, Huygens proposed that Saturn was surrounded by "a thin, flat ring, nowhere touching, and inclined to the ecliptic."

What is the strength of each hypothesis?

Does H 1 predict the data? Data 1 st theory prediction Somewhat, but not too great.

Does H 2 predict the data? data 2 nd theory prediction A better fit.

Does H 3 predict the data? data 3 rd theory prediction About as good as H 2.

Overall, which is best? Cause proposed? Cause is plausible? Cause predicts E? H 1 (triple planet) Yes Somewhat Poorly H 2 (handles) Yes No Well H 3 (ring) Yes Barely Well H 1 is weak because it fails to predict the evidence. H 2 is weak because it is implausible. H 3 is strongest because it is barely plausible and predicts the evidence. H 3 is the best explanation.

(The size of each square represents prior probability, and the green arrows represent logical inference)

Example: Copernicus s argument The diagram shows Ptolemy s geocentric model. The solar orbit, and all its duplicates, are shown in yellow.

Predicting retrograde motion The orbit of Mars according to Copernicus (left) vs. Ptolemy (right). (Image: Wikipedia)

Less ad hoc A heliocentric universe, viewed from a central planet, must generate these appearances (data): Epicycles Some planets stay close to the sun All the other planets move retrograde when in opposition. Copernicus s theory was much less ad hoc than Ptolemy s. Ad hoc = features of a theory driven by empirical data rather than rational argument.

Copernicus s key insight We thus follow Nature, who producing nothing in vain or superfluous often prefers to endow one cause with many effects. Copernicus, De Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium. Thomas Kuhn (Historian and philosopher of science) refers to this as Copernicus s argument from mathematical harmony.

Criticism of Copernicus argument Harmony seems a strange basis on which to argue for the earth s motion Copernicus arguments are not pragmatic. They appeal, if at all, not to the utilitarian sense of the practicing astronomer but to his aesthetic sense and to that alone. New harmonies did not increase accuracy or simplicity. Therefore they could and did appeal primarily to that limited and perhaps irrational subgroup of mathematical astronomers whose Neoplatonic ear for mathematical harmonies could not be obstructed by page after page of complex mathematics leading finally to numerical predictions scarcely better than those they had known before. Thomas Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution, p. 181.

What do you think of Copernicus s argument? Did it provide a good reason for accepting his theory? Or was it sophistry and illusion?

c.f. Hume s Fork If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion. David Hume, Enquiry (1748), Section 12 Part 3.

A priori knowledge? It appears that Copernicus s argument against Ptolemy is a priori. Is that true? However, in that case, it seems that a priori arguments can establish merely contingent truths. After all, if God wanted to make a Ptolemaic universe, could he do it? Would it be logically possible? As with Leibniz, Copernicus could only argue for his universe based on the wisdom of God, not logical necessity.

Hume s argument for induction not being based on reasoning An inductive inference has the form: Statements about what is directly observed -------------------------------------------------- Statements that go way beyond observation Hume says you need some sort of bridge premise to connect the two subjects. (Like inferences from Belgium to Portugal.) If there were nothing to bind the two facts together, the inference of one from the other would be utterly shaky. This seems to be true, just as a matter of logic.

Cause and effect According to Hume, what connects the two is the relation of cause and effect. (The cause-effect relation is the bridge.) Scientific inferences mostly infer causes from effects, but (as Hume points out) there are other patterns. So the inductive argument becomes: 1. Statements about what is directly observed 2. Statements about what causes what -------------------------------------------------- 3. Statements that go way beyond observation

E.g. hypothesis evidence 34

E.g. 1. This valley is observed to be U-shaped 2. Glaciers cause U-shaped valleys ---------------------------------- This valley was formed by a glacier 35

Now add empiricism knowledge about causes is never acquired through a priori reasoning, and always comes from our experience of finding that particular objects are constantly associated with one other. But now, if premise 2 is entirely derived from experience, then it adds no information at all to premise 1, and so cannot act as an inferential bridge. This is, I think, Hume s central argument for inductive scepticism, in pp. 15-16 of the Enquiry (Bennett edition).

(Hume doesn t explicitly make this argument, at least in the Enquiry. But the main idea of his argument, I believe, is the logical insufficiency of purely empirical knowledge to take us beyond experience.) All that past experience can tell us, directly and for sure, concerns the behaviour of the particular objects we observed, at the particular time when we observed them. But if you insist that the inference is made by a chain of reasoning, I challenge you to produce the reasoning. Where is the intermediate step, the interposing ideas, which join propositions that are so different from one another?

Hume s second argument Later, starting on the right-hand column of page 16 in the Bennett edition, Hume considers how we actually make these arguments, in reality. How do we make these inferences? From causes that appear similar we expect similar effects. And For all inferences from experience are based on the assumption that the future will resemble the past, and that similar powers will be combined with similar sensible qualities. But, once again, Hume says, it s quite obvious that we can t learn this from experience. For example, to use induction: since induction worked in the past, it will work again would be circular.

Feldman s version Feldman seems to skip Part 1 of Section 4, as well as the first couple of pages of Part 2. The focus of the Feldman-Hume argument is (PF) The future will be like the past. There s nothing in Feldman about the cause-effect relation providing the crucial inferential bridge from experience to theory, or about our knowledge of cause and effect being entirely from experience.

Responses to Hume s argument 1. Rationalism Rationalism (e.g. of a modest sort) would cut Hume s argument off at the roots. Hume: It would take a very clever person to discover by reasoning that heat makes crystals and cold makes ice without having had experience of the effects of heat and cold! E.g. Maxwell discovered electromagnetic waves (e.g. radio waves) by reasoning. (This is but one of many examples of this kind.)

A Bayesian rationalist (= objective Bayesian) has, I would say, a very strong response to Hume s argument. Bayes theorem shows how a small amount of a priori knowledge can combine with empirical data to give pretty strong (though fallible) theoretical knowledge. When Hume says, I challenge you to produce the reasoning. the objective Bayesian replies, Here you are.

Interestingly, Bayesian reasoning fully supports Hume s claim that, in the absence of a priori knowledge, statements about experience cannot tell us about anything else. For example, suppose an urn is known to contain a large number of balls, each either black or white. (But we know nothing else.) Then we draw (say) 100 balls at random, and see that they are all black. According to Bayes theorem, what is the probability that the next ball selected will be black? Bayes theorem says: No idea. In the absence of any prior probability distribution over the possible colourings of the balls, Bayes theorem is helpless. If we assign equal prior probability to every possible colouring, then P(next ball black) = ½, regardless of previous experience, according to Bayes theorem.

Objections to Hume 1. Hume assumes that a priori knowledge would be certain. If this were based on reason, we could draw the conclusion as well after a single instance as after a long course of experience. Objective Bayesians reply that a priori knowledge comes to us in the form of prior probabilities, so that experience is also needed in most cases. 2. Based on #1, Hume reasons that since experience is necessary for a particular kind of knowledge, it follows that that kind of knowledge comes purely from experience. 3. Hume claims that a priori reasoning about causes would be arbitrary, idle imagination, but the history of physics suggests otherwise.

Email with Paul Russell RJ this collision problem was important in physics since Descartes proposed a solution to it. Huygens later solved the problem in the 1650s using a priori principles like symmetry conservation. On the face of it then, Hume is just wrong to say that reason has nothing to say about cause and effect, and that it must arbitrarily invent or imagine the effect. Does Hume respond to this objection? PR: These billiard ball example features prominently in Locke s Essay, which is, I think, an important source for Hume (and his contemporaries). I am not aware of Hume having knowledge or interest in Huygens. I think that Hume s primary sources relating to induction and inference were Hobbes, Locke and Butler. Again, I am not aware of Hume directly responding to Leibniz in relation to this matter

A pragmatic defense of induction (without a priori knowledge) Believing is closely tied to betting. Probability theory even defines degrees of belief in terms of subjectively fair gambles. Betting on a proposition p means performing some action that will reap a benefit if p is true, but be costly is p is false. (In this sense we bet on propositions all the time.) A pragmatist tries to show that betting on inductive conclusions makes pragmatic sense, since induction is the only game in town. Either you bet on induction, or you re paralysed by inaction.

Finally, if what was sought is a case for the epistemic rationality of (PF), the defense seems to fall short. It does not show that we have good reason to believe that (PF) is true. At most, it shows that we are at least as well off using (PF) as we are using any alternative to it. And that is less than what was sought. (p. 137) There s more about this in the option BonJour reading.

Feldman s a priori Defense of Induction Feldman considers case of what is called the statistical syllogism : There are 1,000 marbles in a jar, 999 are black, 1 is white and 1 has been randomly selected ------------------- the selected ball is black Feldman notes that the conclusion isn t a logical consequence of the premises. Yet a slightly different argument is logically valid

There are 1,000 marbles in a jar, 999 are black, 1 is white and 1 has been randomly selected ------------------- Prob(the selected ball is black) = 0.999 Not everyone agrees that this is logically valid, but some do (e.g. objective Bayesians do). If the argument is valid, the probability in the conclusion would be an example of logical probability, i.e. degrees of belief that are fixed by logic alone.

By analogy to the statistical syllogism, Feldman thinks that, while (PF) isn t a logical truth, the claim that PF is logically probable is perhaps a logical truth. (PFR) The future will probably be like the past Is (PFR) a logical truth, i.e. analytic, or true by definition? Of course not. Reasoning about the random selection from an urn of known constitution is nothing like the case of an urn with an unknown constitution.

An empirical argument for the a priori? 1. A priori arguments have often anticipated new data. 2. If rationalistic arguments were mere sophistry and illusion then this empirical success would amount to a miracle. ----------------- Rationalistic arguments are not illusions Is this argument self-defeating? (N.B. Empirical arguments need not be purely empirical. The rationalist isn t betraying herself by making empirical arguments!)

IBE and a priori arguments IBE = Inference to the Best Explanation Many, perhaps most, philosophers of science now think that scientific reasoning is generally IBE. IBE involves formulating all the possible explanations of the existing total data, and judging that the best explanation is probably true.

What makes an explanation good? There s no exact, universally accepted measure of how good a particular explanation H is. In my view, the correct measure is the Bayesian one: Strength(H) = P K (E H) P K (H) = likelihood prior If you look in a critical thinking textbook you ll see a list like: Testability Fruitfulness Simplicity Scope Conservatism

Note that all such criteria go beyond mere empirical adequacy, to include things like: Fit with existing beliefs Simplicity, economy, etc. loveliness, beauty, etc. In other words, IBE is a form of reasoning that includes non-empirical factors.

Laurence BonJour Blurb: Most recent philosophers reject [rationalism] and argue that all substantive knowledge must be sensory in origin. Laurence Bonjour provocatively reopens the debate by presenting the most comprehensive exposition and defense of the rationalist view that a priori insight is a genuine basis for knowledge.

Laurence BonJour Appeal to natural necessities as IBE: What sort of an a priori reason might be offered, then, for thinking that a standard inductive conclusion is likely to be true when such a standard inductive premise is true? The intuitive idea behind the reason to be suggested here is that an objective regularity of a sort that would make the conclusion of a standard inductive argument true provides the best explanation for the truth of the premise of such an argument (p. 207)

Of course, it is logically possible that the results in question represent the operation of nothing more than mere random coincidence or chance, but it seems evident, and, as far as I can see, evident on a purely a priori basis, that it is highly unlikely that only coincidence is at work, an unlikelihood that increases rapidly as the number of observations is made larger. (p. 208) Note that this view has the consequence that empirical support for an a priori principle increases its epistemic probability.

In a similar way David Armstrong and Brian Ellis argue that observed stable patterns are best explained by the existence of essential properties of matter. These fixed essences give rise to uniform laws, which cause the stable patterns we observe. On a Humean view, where laws are no more than regularities (and hence the laws themselves cannot be explained) there is no possible inference from the past to the future.

How about Bayesian empiricism? How does one assign values to the priors? by experience. To some extent that s fair enough, as the priors at any given time are based on previous observations, at least in part. But there s a kind of regress problem here, as Bayes theorem doesn t allow probabilities to be determined by experience all the way down. It seems to require absolute priors.

Goodman laws E.g. Newton s laws are followed up to March 20, 2016, but after that <some other law> holds What does today s total empirical evidence have to say about this law? Are such laws logically impossible? Do any purely logical principles (e.g. the probability axioms) render them improbable?

Appeal to past experience 1. We ve never observed any such Goodman law to hold. 2. Standard, simple laws have a great track record ------------------- Goodman laws are improbable The argument is circular, says Hume (and Skyrms, BonJour, etc.)

Washing out the priors

Washing out the priors This is an important feature of Bayesian reasoning. But does it render a priori knowledge obsolete, in actual scientific practice? Or does it merely allow us to manage with less a priori knowledge, in favourable cases where the data are plentiful? After all, if one s priors are extreme enough (i.e. close enough to 0 or 1) then the actual data will be insufficient to wash them out.