alan richardson and thomas uebel

Similar documents
Alan Richardson is professor of philosophy at the University of British Columbia.

145 Philosophy of Science

Vienna Circle Mauro Murzi

Ayer and the Vienna Circle

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

B OOK R EVIEWS 557 is Jeremy Heis work on the connections between Ernst Cassirer, Lewin, and Reichenbach a topic which surfaces again in Milkov s pape

EMPIRICISM AND SOCIOLOGY

NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS. Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition. Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Naturalism Fall Winter 2004

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

The Vienna Circle's 'Anti-Foundationalism'

This book is mis-titled. Amuch better title would be Don t Expect Philosophers ofscience

From Kant to Quine: Reading List

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Introduction Logical Empiricism in North America. Logical Empiricism in North America

An Introduction to Logical Empiricism and the Unity of Science Movement in the Cold War

Logical positivism, the enfant terrible of twentieth-century philosophy, began around

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

Dr. Peter Olen Lake-Sumter State College 9501 U.S. Highway 441 Leesburg, FL

Introduction The Science Wars in Perspective

Skepticism, Naturalism, and Therapy

THE VIENNA CIRCLE IN THE NORDIC COUNTRIES

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE

HUL 841: Philosophy of Science IInd Semester,

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

GRC 362E (38400) SQUARING THE VIENNA CIRCLE

Department of Philosophy. PHIL 3130 Contemporary British and American Philosophy Fall 2005 MWF 11:30 12:20, MacKinnon 228

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Nordic Wittgenstein Review 6 (2) 2017 pp DOI /nwr.v6i A Tapestry

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

WORKING PAPER SERIES. Università di Torino

COURSE OUTLINE Please read this outline carefully and retain it for future reference.

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Held at Philadelphia for Promoting Useful Knowledge

PHIL 3150 Philosophy of Science Fall 2016 PHIL 6015 Theory of Knowledge

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

THE PROBLEM OF TRUTH IN THE CLASSICAL ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Hempel, Carnap, and the Covering Law Model 1

Philosophy Courses in English

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Recap. Contents EMPIRICISM. Reductionism and Idealism. Early Carnap. Game plan. Reading and final essay. Recap: Russell s phenomenalism

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

6AANA026 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION. (2011 Admn. onwards) VI Semester B.A. PHILOSOPHY CORE COURSE CONTEMPORARY WESTERN PHILOSOPHY

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

G. H. von Wright (1916 )

Realistic Claims in Logical Empiricism

Epistemology Naturalized

Logical Content and Empirical Significance

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

2 Logic Plus Empiricism

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

POSITIVISM AND CHRISTIANITY A STUDY OF THEISM AND VERIFIABILITY

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

The Changing Role of Language in Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames

EMBEDDING LOGICAL EMPIRICISM INTO THE HISTORY OF EPISTEMOLOGY: EINO KAILA ON HUMAN KNOWLEDGE

Wittgenstein versus Carnap on physicalism: a reassessment. 1

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Cambridge University Press Defending Einstein: Hans Reichenbach s Writings on Space, Time, and Motion Edited by Steven Gimbel and Anke Wa

The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: , ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994).

Changing Society by Scientific Investigations? The Unexpected Shared Ground Between Early Sociology of Knowledge and the Vienna Circle

How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science

AUSTRIAN PHILOSOPHY PAST AND PRESENT

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 110A,

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

7AAN2075 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Communicating Christ in a Multicultural World

Philosophy Courses-1

Bayesian Probability

The linguistic turn and other misconceptions about analytic philosophy

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Ever since W. V. O. Quine wrote his famous Two Dogmas of

Philosophy Courses-1

MATHEMATICS ITS FOUNDATIONS AND THEIR IMPLICAT

Does Philosophy Investigate Language or Reality?

Philosophy 370: Problems in Analytic Philosophy

Curriculum Vitae. Other Areas of Interest: Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind, and History of Philosophy.

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

The Vicissitudes of Mathematical Reason in the 20th Century

Transcription:

Introduction If there is a movement or school that epitomized or typified analytic philosophy in the middle of the twentieth century, it was, by all odds, logical empiricism. 1 Logical empiricists such as Hans Reichenbach, Rudolf Carnap, Carl G. Hempel, and Herbert Feigl had, by 1950, influenced the major fields of analytic philosophy. They had been instrumental in creating a scientifically and technically informed philosophy of science, in establishing mathematical logic as a topic in and a tool for philosophy, and in creating the project of formal semantics. Logical empiricism provided an importantly new understanding of the nature of empiricism and a new rejection of metaphysics. Accounts of analytic philosophy written in the middle of the twentieth century give logical empiricism a central place in the project, often repeating for analytic philosophy the revolutionary rhetoric of early logical empiricism. Because of this importance of logical empiricism in establishing the project of analytic philosophy, philosophical innovations both within and outside the analytic tradition in the 1960s and 1970s often were at pains to distance themselves from one aspect or another of logical empiricism. Karl Popper s philosophy of science, for example, distanced itself from concerns about the meaninglessness of metaphysics, whereas Thomas Kuhn s historical philosophy of science distanced itself from the formalism and 1 Throughout this book logical empiricism is understood to be synonymous with logical positivism, or even neopositivism, unless it is clear in context that a distinction is being drawn. Some logical empiricists thought the names had different reference, but most did not; in any case, by the middle of the 1930s, logical empiricism was the preferred term for leading representatives of both camps. Thus, we have chosen it rather than the more well-known but more misleading logical positivism. 1 www.cambridge.org

2 ahistorical approach to philosophy of science that had become associated with logical empiricism. Similarly, in philosophy of language, Saul Kripke s semantics of modal logic and new theory of reference enforced a turn toward metaphysics in formal semantics, whereas Donald Davidson and W. V. O. Quine, each in his own way, moved semantics away from formalism and toward a naturalistic empiricism. Such moves away from (what were understood to be) central commitments of logical empiricism, whether explicit or implicit, were widely noted and embraced. By the 1970s, logical empiricism had few advocates, and the project became firmly associated with a set of discarded philosophical doctrines and methods. Further afield, the positivism associated with logical empiricism was widely decried in European philosophy and in the social sciences as too narrowly scientistic and, thus, able neither to illuminate the business of social science nor to serve as a proper basis for philosophy. The first wave of interpretative accounts of logical empiricism had placed it at the heart of analytic philosophy, and the second, therefore, was constructed to show how philosophy should progress or had progressed beyond logical empiricism. Since roughly the early 1980s a new literature has arisen that is less argumentative with or dismissive of logical empiricism, a literature that seeks to understand the place of logical empiricism in its historical, scientific, and philosophical contexts. This work proceeds in important ways on both sides of the Atlantic Ocean as scholars reconsider the origins of logical empiricism in Europe in the early twentieth century and its transmission to North America and throughout the world with the rise of fascism in Europe in the 1930s. This work has engaged not only philosophers but also intellectual historians, historians and sociologists of science, and researchers in intellectual migration and exile from Europe in the twentieth century. The purpose of this volume is to provide an entry into this new literature on the reappraisal of logical empiricism as well as suggestions for further reading. This new work in the reappraisal of logical empiricism seeks to be more fair and disinterested than previous work it is designed neither to sign up recruits nor to induce an act of intellectual homicide nor yet to preside over a funeral. Nevertheless, the work is not antiquarian. It agrees with both the early promotional and the later critical literature in finding logical empiricism central to analytic www.cambridge.org

Introduction 3 philosophy in the twentieth century. It is based, however, in the sensibility that the philosophical significance of logical empiricism has not been adequately judged and that this is to the detriment of contemporary philosophy generally. The work this volume introduces, then, seeks to be both historically accurate and philosophically informed; throughout an eye will always be open to questions of the significance of logical empiricism to contemporary projects in philosophy and to projects that might be available for tomorrow s philosophers to take up. Logical empiricism, whatever else it might be or have been, was a movement or program for philosophy that developed in Central Europe. A number of scientifically minded philosophers and philosophically minded scientists came together in various places throughout Europe to reflect on the current state of scientific and philosophical knowledge. The projects characteristic of logical empiricism developed primarily in Vienna and Berlin. The Vienna Circle, a group of researchers who met regularly from the mid-1920s to the mid-1930s under the leadership of Moritz Schlick, then the Chair for the Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences at the University of Vienna, counted among its junior members Rudolf Carnap and Schlick s student Herbert Feigl, and Hans Hahn, Philipp Frank, and Otto Neurath amongst its founders. In Berlin the Society for Scientific Philosophy was led by Hans Reichenbach and counted among its members and associates, besides Walter Dubislav and Richard von Mises, his student Carl G. Hempel. Connections were drawn also to various other centers of intellectual life in Europe in the 1920s and 1930s, such as Prague (where both Frank and Carnap worked at various times) and Warsaw (then home to the leading group working in mathematical logic, including Alfred Tarski). Reflection upon the list of names appearing above indicates that the logical empiricists numbered among themselves several of the leading philosophers of the twentieth century and they had substantial contact with other leading philosophers and scientists (Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Albert Einstein, Niels Bohr, Kurt Gödel, W. V. Quine, Karl Popper, David Hilbert, Hermann Weyl, et al.). Nonetheless, it was characteristic of the logical empiricists to stress the communal nature of philosophical research and the belief that philosophical results belonged to the community. For this reason, among other more quotidian ones, the editors have www.cambridge.org

4 not chosen to organize the volume by individual philosopher, featuring a chapter on Schlick, one on Neurath, etc. We have, rather, chosen a topical approach, in our belief that one achieves a better sense of the group s own philosophical self-understanding by studying the topics they investigated and the methods they employed than by reading a set of quasi-biographical-cum-quasi-philosophical remarks. Logical empiricism was a philosophy centrally concerned with science. Even when their interests moved them into areas such as semantics and metaethics, the logical empiricists sought both to understand and to promote the scientific understanding of the world. Science was, to their minds, both the locus of our best knowledge of the world and the source of hope for a brighter, less obscure and obscurantist future for philosophy. The Vienna Circle chose the term wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung scientific world-conception when, in 1929, they published their manifesto. Logical empiricism offered a scientific conception of the world in two senses, in fact: it offered a conception of the world that was deeply informed by science, and in doing so it sought to bring philosophy into the fold of genuinely scientific disciplines. Logical empiricism s form of scientific modernism flourished perhaps most brightly in Central Europe between the world wars and apparently lost its idealistic shine as it temporarily assumed a dominant role in post Second World War North American philosophy (a role it never attained in Britain). To reflect the importance of science as topic, method, and ideal among the logical empiricists, the essays in this volume are most centrally concerned with topics in general philosophy of science and in the philosophy of the special sciences. Where, for example, semantics is discussed, it is discussed in its central application for the logical empiricists the question of the meaningfulness of scientific theories and their relation to evidential reports. Similarly, the elimination of metaphysics and the verification criterion of meaning are discussed here not as central dogmas of logical empiricism but in their contexts as part of the historical narrative of the logical empiricists attempts to find a nonmetaphysical form of philosophy that could illuminate and reflect how science achieves knowledge of the world. Attention to then-contemporary science and its relations to then-contemporary philosophy is necessary to illuminate the philosophical moves characteristic of logical empiricism, including, www.cambridge.org

Introduction 5 of course, their joint sense that theirs was a philosophy entirely without doctrines, much less dogmas. The volume is, thus, divided into thematic sections. The first section, The Historical Context of Logical Empiricism, features essays that situate logical empiricism in the contexts of its development, first in Europe and then in the United States. Friedrich Stadler s essay examines the principal place of origin of logical empiricism, the Vienna Circle. Dieter Hoffmann s essay details the place of logical empiricism in the Berlin Society for Empirical/Scientific Philosophy. George Reisch looks at the development of logical empiricism in North America from the 1930s onward. These essays all bring new historical scholarship and historiographic subtlety to the question of the historical career and significance of logical empiricism. The second section of the book examines some of the large issues in general philosophy of science that animated the work of the logical empiricists. Michael Friedman s essay examines the career of the notion of an a priori element in knowledge in logical empiricism; he points out the many twists in the understanding of the a priori and the lingering significance of it in mature logical empiricist philosophy of science. Maria Carla Galavotti s essay examines a project that many would think to be the heart of mature logical empiricism, the foundations of probability theory and the theory of confirmation, topics absolutely central to the logical empiricist s account of the structure and basis of scientific knowledge. Thomas Mormann examines another set of issues central to all logical empiricist theories of science: their account of the nature and structure of scientific theories. Throughout the essays in this section, the logical empiricist concerns with elucidating the place of conventions in scientific theorizing, answering questions of the relations of scientific theories to sensory evidence, and illuminating the logical structure of theories as well as other central issues in the general approach to philosophy of science within logical empiricism are examined from various angles. The following section, Logical Empiricism and the Philosophy of the Special Sciences, speaks to specific themes in the logical empiricist understandings of particular scientific disciplines. Steve Awodey and A. W. Carus offer an account of the particular nature of logical empiricist concerns with the foundations of mathematics www.cambridge.org

6 and logic, an extraordinarily rich field both technically and philosophically, given the prominence of logic in the methods employed by the logical empiricists throughout their philosophy. Another rich field is mined by Thomas Ryckman in his detailed account of the philosophy of physics offered by logical empiricism, a philosophy both inspired by and seeking to explain the revolutionary developments in relativity theory and quantum mechanics in the early twentieth century. Logical empiricism is famous (or infamous) for its interventions in the methodology of psychology, the topic of Gary Hardcastle s essay. Thomas Uebel offers an account of the philosophy of social science embedded in the project of the physicalistic unity of science pursued especially by Otto Neurath in the 1930s and 1940s. Elisabeth Nemeth considers the hitherto scarcely explored relations between logical empiricism and contemporaneous history and sociology of science. The final section of the book considers the relations between logical empiricism and some of its main critics. David Stern illuminates the vexed relations between the logical empiricists and Ludwig Wittgenstein through an examination of Wittgenstein s claim in the early 1930s that Carnap had plagiarized his work. Richard Creath examines the significance of the Carnap-Quine dispute regarding analyticity, the single most important episode in the turn of analytic philosophy from logical empiricism. Alan Richardson s essay details some historical puzzles surrounding the relations of Thomas Kuhn s historical philosophy of science and logical empiricist philosophy of science. The editors would like to thank many people and institutions without whom this volume would not have been possible. The volume was substantially aided by a workshop sponsored by the International Society for History of Philosophy of Science (HOPOS) and the Vienna Circle Institute and held at the University of Vienna. Early encouragement was offered also by the late Cambridge University Press editor Terence Moore. Research assistantship was ably provided at various stages by University of British Columbia graduate students Alex Harmsen, Michael Waters, Stephen Friesen, and Roger Clarke; funding for these students was provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the UBC Hampton Research Fund, and the UBC Humanities and Social Sciences Large Grant fund. The contributors were notable for their www.cambridge.org

Introduction 7 good will and patience throughout this project. Deeply grateful to them, each editor also absolves the other for all faults that remain in the work. further reading (in english) Bibliographies of members of the Vienna Circle, the Berlin Society, and selected associates are given, along with short biographies in Stadler (2001, pp. 610 865). Extensive bibliographies of Anglo-American analytic philosophy during logical empiricism s heyday are featured in Ayer (1959, pp. 381 447) and in Richard M. Rorty (ed.), 1967. The Linguistic Turn. Essays in Philosophical Method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rev. ed. 1992, pp. 375 407. early motivating literature from (and about) the logical empiricists Hahn, Hans, Otto Neurath, and Rudolf Carnap. 1929. Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung. Der Wiener Kreis. Vienna: Wolf. Trans. by P. Foulkes and M. Neurath as Scientific World-Conception: The Vienna Circle in O Neurath (ed. M. Neurath and R. S. Cohen), Empiricism and Sociology. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1973, pp. 299 318. Feigl, Herbert, and Alfred O. Blumberg. 1931. Logical Positivism. Journal of Philosophy 28: 281 96. Reichenbach, Hans. 1935. Logical Empiricism in Germany and the Present State of Its Problems. Journal of Philosophy 33: 141 60. Nagel, Ernest. 1936. Impressions and Appraisals of Analytic Philosophy in Europe, Journal of Philosophy 33. Repr. in Nagel. 1956. Logic without Metaphysics and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, pp. 191 246. retrospective accounts of the development and significance of logical empiricism Frank, Philipp. 1949. Introduction: Historical Background. In his Modern Science and Its Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 1 52. Jorgensen, Jorgen. 1951. The Development of Logical Empiricism. Foundations of the Unity of Science, volume 2, number 9. Chicago: University of Chicago Press pp. 845 946 of volume 2 of the combined www.cambridge.org

8 edition: Neurath, Otto, Rudolf Carnap, and Charles Morris (eds.), Foundations of the Unity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. Kraft, Viktor. 1953. The Vienna Circle. New York: Philosophical Library (orig. 1950). Ayer, Alfred Jules. 1959. Introduction. In A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism. New York: Free Press, pp. 3 28. Carnap, Rudolf. 1963a. Intellectual Autobiography. In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. LaSalle, IL: Open Court, pp. 3 84. Feigl, Herbert. 1969. The Wiener Kreis in America. In D. Fleming and B. Baylin (eds.), The Intellectual Migration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Repr. in Feigl, Inquiries and Provocations (ed. R. S. Cohen). Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981, pp. 57 93. Achinstein, Peter, and Steven F. Barker (eds.). 1969. The Legacy of Logical Positivism. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Suppe, Frederick. 1977. The Search for a Philosophical Understanding of Theories. In F. Suppe (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2nd ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, pp. 3 241. Hanfling, Oswald. 1981. Logical Positivism. Oxford: Blackwell. Gadol, Eugene T. (ed.). 1982. Rationality and Science. Vienna: Springer. Menger, Karl. 1994. Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the Mathematical Colloquium (ed. B. McGuinness and A. Sklar). Dordrecht: Kluwer recent historical scholarship Haller, Rudolf (ed.). 1982. Schlick and Neurath Centenary. Grazer Philosophische Studien 16 17. Rescher, Nicholas (ed.). 1985. The Heritage of Logical Positivism. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Proust, Joelle. 1989. Questions of Form. Logic and the Analytic Proposition from Kant to Carnap. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press (orig. 1986). Zolo, Danilo. 1989. Reflexive Epistemology. The Philosophical Legacy of Otto Neurath. Dordrecht: Kluwer (orig. 1986). Coffa, Alberto. 1991. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap. To the Vienna Station (ed. L. Wessels). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spohn, Wolfgang (ed.). 1991. Hans Reichenbach, Rudolf Carnap: A Centenary. Erkenntnis 35. www.cambridge.org

Introduction 9 Uebel, Thomas E. (ed.). 1991. Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Bell, David, and Wilhelm Vossenkuhl (eds.). 1992. Science and Subjectivity. Berlin: Akademieverlag. Sarkar, Sahotra (ed.). 1992. Rudolf Carnap Centenary. Synthese 93 nos. 1 2. Uebel, Thomas E. 1992. Overcoming Logical Positivism from Within. Neurath in the Vienna Circle s Protocol Sentence Debate. Amsterdam: Rodopi. Oberdan, Thomas. 1993. Protocols, Truth, Convention. Amsterdam: Rodopi. Salmon, Wesley, and Gereon Wolters (eds.). 1993. Logic, Language and the Structure of Scientific Theories. Pittsburgh/Konstanz: University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag. Stadler, Friedrich (ed.). 1993. Scientific Philosophy: Origin and Developments. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Cirera, Ramon. 1994. Carnap and the Vienna Circle. Empiricism and Logical Syntax. Amsterdam: Rodopi. Cartwright, Nancy, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck, and Thomas E. Uebel. 1996. Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics. Cambridge:. Giere, Ronald N., and Alan W. Richardson (eds.). 1996. Origins of Logical Empiricism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Nemeth, Elisabeth, and Friedrich Stadler (eds.). 1996. Otto Neurath: Encyclopedism and Utopia. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Sarkar, Sahotra (ed.). 1996. The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals. New York: Garland. Richardson, Alan W. 1998. Carnap s Construction of the World. Cambridge:. Friedman, Michael. 1999. Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge:. Friedman, Michael. 2000. A Parting of the Ways: Carnap-Cassirer- Heidegger. Chicago: Open Court. Fetzer, James (ed.). 2000. Science, Explanation and Rationality. Aspects of the Philosophy of C. G. Hempel. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stadler, Friedrich. 2001. The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins, Development, and Inflence of Logical Empiricism. Vienna: Springer (orig. 1997). Bonk, Thomas (ed.). 2003. Language, Truth and Knowledge. Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Hardcastle, Gary L., and Alan W. Richardson (eds.). 2003. Logical Empiricism in North America. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. www.cambridge.org

10 Parrini, Paolo, Wesley Salmon, and Merrilee Salmon (eds.). 2003. Logical Empiricism. Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Stadler, Friedrich (ed.). 2003. The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism. Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Awodey, Steve, and Carsten Klein (eds.). 2004. Carnap Brought Home. The View from Jena. Chicago: Open Court. Reisch, George. 2005. How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Creath, Richard, and Michael Friedman (eds.). 2007. Cambridge Companion to Rudolf Carnap. Cambridge:. For further individual essays, see also journals like Philosophy of Science, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, Perspectives on Science, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Synthese, History and Philosophy of Logic, Journal of the History of Philosophy, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Journal of Philosophy, American Philosophical Quarterly, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, European Journal of Philosophy, Philosophy and Phenomenalogical Review, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, Philosophical Topics, Grazer Philosophische Studien, and, last but not least, Erkenntnis. www.cambridge.org