Relativism. We re both right.

Similar documents
appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

What is Justification?

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

What is knowledge? How do good beliefs get made?

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Why is proper function needed for knowledge?

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Critical Scientific Realism

Skepticism and Internalism

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

What Should We Believe?

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

The Problem of the External World

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988.

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Transition: From A priori To Anselm

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Naturalism and is Opponents

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

The Problem of Induction. Knowledge beyond experience?

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Relativism, Truth and Implicit Commitments 1

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN 1. AGAINST ANALYTIC METAPHYSICS

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

Rationality and Truth. What is objectivity?

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Realism and Idealism Internal realism

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Relativism and the Nature of Truth

PHIL 181: METAPHYSICS Fall 2006 M 5:30-8:20 MND-3009 WebCT-Assisted

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Transcription:

Relativism We re both right.

Epistemic vs. Alethic Relativism There are two forms of anti-realism (or relativism): (A) Epistemic anti-realism: whether or not a view is rationally justified depends on your paradigm s rules. There are no objective rules that transcend all paradigms. (Feldman discusses this.) (B) Alethic anti-realism: There is no objective truth, no world out there that is independent of theory. Reality is in fact a mental or social construct. (Allen Wood discusses this.)

Wood on alethic relativism: Here I want mainly to discuss (and to criticize) a view I have encountered among students in philosophy courses, who say things like this: What anyone believes is true for that person. What you believe is true for you, what I believe is true for me. We can call the view expressed in such statements relativism because it denies that there is any such thing as absolute truth, holds that all truth is relative to the person who believes it. (Wood) Are there such people? Are there any grounds for such an attitude?

The world is a social construct? Objects do not exist independently of conceptual schemes. We cut up the world into objects when we introduce one or another scheme of description. (Hilary Putnam s internal realism, in Reason, Truth and History, 1981, p. 52). If, as I maintain, objects themselves are as much made as discovered, as much products of our conceptual invention as of the objective factor in experience, the factor independent of our will, then of course objects intrinsically belong under certain labels because those labels are just the tools we use to construct a version of the world with such objects in the first place. (Putnam, 1981, p. 54, italics his).

Logic (the science of thought) regards the world as consisting of objects, with properties and relations. But surely the world itself isn t conceptual! So the world itself cannot contain objects with properties and relations. Putnam: objects themselves are products of our conceptual invention as much made as discovered

Thus, Putnam denies that there are natural kinds, and even mind-independent objects. E.g. does the Southern Ocean really exist? Isn t it just a human construct, pieced together from bits of 3 other oceans?

Classification changes with paradigm Celestial bodies for Ptolemy

Copernican taxonomy

Putnam s internalism I shall refer to it as the internalist perspective, because it is characteristic of this view to hold that what objects does the world consist of? is a question that it only makes sense to ask within a theory or description. Many internalist philosophers, though not all, hold further that there is more than one true theory or description of the world. Truth, in an internalist view, is some sort of (idealized) rational acceptability some sort of ideal coherence of our beliefs with each other and with our experiences as those experiences are themselves represented in our belief system and not correspondence with mind-independent or discourse-independent states of affairs. There is no God s Eye point of view that we can know or usefully imagine; there are only the various points of view of actual persons reflecting various interests and purposes that their descriptions and theories subserve. (49-50)

Internalism is not a facile relativism that says, Anything goes. Denying that it makes sense to ask whether our concepts match something totally uncontaminated by conceptualization is one thing; but to hold that every conceptual system is therefore just as good as every other would be something else. If anyone really believed that, and if they were foolish enough to pick a conceptual system that told them they could fly and to act upon it by jumping out of a window, they would, if they were lucky enough to survive, see the weakness of the latter view at once. (p. 54) Qu.: Can an internalist explain why the data and epistemic norms priviledge some conceptual systems over others?

The world is conceptual? Quite literally, men of those days lived in a different world because their instruments of intellectual interpretation were so different [C. I. Lewis, 1929, p. 253]. [the switch to a radically new scientific view] produces disciples forming a school, the members of which are separated for the time being by a logical gap from those outside it. They think differently, speak a different language, live in a different world, [Michael Polanyi, 1958, p 151].

Thomas Kuhn on scientific progress We may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them closer and closer to the truth (p. 170) (Note the weasel word may here!) Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal? (Note the rhetorical question, rather than statement, here!)

Kuhn claims that he can t even make sense of talk about what is really there in the world itself, as opposed to what is there according to some theory or paradigm. There is, I think, no theory independent way to reconstruct phrases like really there ; the notion of a match between the ontology of a theory and its real counterpart in nature now seems to be illusive in principle (p. 206).

Alethic Relativism is self-refuting? The problem arises as soon as Protagoras tries either to assert relativism or believe it. If Protagoras asserts relativism, then he asserts that relativism is true, and that those (such as Plato) who deny relativism say and believe something false. But relativism denies that anyone can say or believe anything false. Is this too simple? Wood assumes that it s true for me = I believe it, and I believe it = I believe it s true. Is this fair?

Fundamental problem for relativism Does the concept of belief make any sense, except as an attempted representation of the truth? E.g. if you call something a map, are you not committed to the existence of a territory that the map is at least intended to represent?

Alethic Relativism vs. Scepticism people are often attracted to relativism by the feeling that others are too confident in the absolute truth of what they believe Wood says that relativism is perhaps attractive as an antidote to dogmatism (p. 24). But scepticism shows that realism doesn t entail dogmatism. Skepticism does not deny that some beliefs are (absolutely) true, it denies only that we can ever be sure which beliefs these are.

Absolute truth authority? If a relativist catches you audaciously suggesting that there is such a thing as (absolute) truth, then you are bound to be asked the rhetorical question: But who is to decide what the truth is? Apparently the relativist thinks that if you hold that there is an absolute, objective truth, then you have to believe there is some authority whose word on that truth must not be questioned. Wood says that the possibility of scepticism shows this is all wrong.

Alethic relativism is a rejection of epistemic authority? I think Wood is perhaps a bit hasty here. I wonder if, in these anti-authoritarian times, the core of alethic relativism is the rejection of epistemic authority? Recall that the truth (or the actual world ) functions as the highest (non-defeasible) epistemic authority. Appeals to truth, fact and reason are deconstructed as appeals to the viewpoint of colonial powers, Western hegemony, logocentrism, male supremacy, white supremacy, etc.

N.B. Wood repeatedly says things like, For it is still true that to believe that p is to believe p is true (absolutely). But if the whole notion of absolute truth is unmasked as a bogus appeal to epistemic authority, I don t think a relativist is likely to agree with this. Surely I can believe p without (in so believing) seeing myself as being aligned with some oppressive metanarrative? It s my belief, my truth, not that of colonial powers, science, God, etc.

Richard Rorty on truth Worries about cognitive status and objectivity are characteristic of a secularized culture in which the scientist replaces the priest. The scientist is now seen as the person who keeps humanity in touch with something beyond itself. [I.e. the objective truth RJ] As the universe was depersonalized, beauty (and, in time, even moral goodness) came to be thought of as subjective. So truth is now thought of as the only point at which human beings are responsible to something nonhuman. A commitment to rationality and to method is thought to be a recognition of this responsibility. The scientist becomes a moral exemplar, one who selflessly expresses himself again and again to the hardness of fact. (Rorty, Science as Solidarity)

Richard Rorty on truth Rorty seems to regard the notion of objective truth as inherently religious. He disparages the idea that: Truth is out there waiting for human beings to arrive at it. This idea seems to us an unfortunate attempt to carry a religious conception over into a secular culture. He thinks this desire for objectivity is: the desire to be in touch with a reality which is more than some community with which we identify ourselves 21

there is nothing to be said about either truth or rationality apart from descriptions of the familiar procedures of justification which a given society ours uses in one or another area of inquiry. Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism and Truth (1991): 23 Here, Rorty endorses epistemic as well as alethic relativism.

Epistemic relativism In trying to get a handle on epistemic relativism, Feldman (p. 180) quotes SSKs (sociologists of scientific knowledge) Barry Barnes and David Bloor: For the relativist there is no sense attached to the idea that some standards or beliefs really are rational as distinct from merely locally accepted as such. Because he thinks that there are no context-free or super-cultural norms of rationality he does not see rationally and irrationally held beliefs as making up two distinct and qualitatively different classes of things. (1982) (Feldman summarises this in his proposition R6.)

Barry Barnes and David Bloor, for instance, have argued that different societies may have incompatible but internally coherent systems of logic because validity and rules of inference are defined by, and hence are relative to, the practices of a given community, rather than a priori universal restrictions on all thought. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Relativism.

Thomas Kuhn The whole field of SSK was strongly influenced by the earlier work of Thomas Kuhn, especially The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962). Thomas Kuhn has argued in the Structure that during a scientific revolution (= paradigm shift ) the available evidence + logic don t unambiguously show the new theory to be better than the old.

Kuhn s Structure E.g. in 1770 1800 scientists Priestly and Lavoisier had different theories ( paradigms ) of combustion (phlogiston theory and oxygen theory). But they had the same data! Kuhn argues that one s very standards of epistemic justification are part of one s paradigm, so that competing paradigms are both justified by their own lights. E.g. Lavoisier paid enormous attention to the masses of reactants and products, Priestly focused on heat, colours, and volumes.

No doubt this is the kind of case that Barnes and Bloor had in mind. In the first place, the proponents of competing paradigms will often disagree about the list of problems that any candidate for paradigm must resolve.... Lavoisier s chemical theory inhibited chemists from asking why the metals were so much alike, a question that phlogistic chemistry had both asked and answered. The transition to Lavoisier s paradigm had, like the transition to Newton s, meant a loss not only of a permissible question but of an achieved solution. (Kuhn, p. 148)

Kuhn compares paradigm shifts to gestalt shifts, political revolutions, and religious conversions, presenting them as essentially non-rational. the fact that a major paradigm revision was needed to see what Lavoisier saw must be the principal reason why Priestley was, to the end of his long life, unable to see it. (Kuhn, p. 56) E.g. during a political revolution, the constitution of the old regime no longer applies, so no rules govern how the revolution itself is to be carried out.

Summary of Kuhn s arguments Paradigm shifts in the history of science have always involved losses in explanatory power as well as gains. So there is no unambiguous improvement. E.g. Lavoisier could not explain why all metals are shiny, ductile, etc. Copernicans could not explain why bodies fall. All standards of epistemic justification are local to a particular paradigm, so they cannot justify one paradigm over another. (Paradigm shifts are nonrational.) E.g. Copernicus appealed to the standard that scientific theories should be economical, not ad hoc, etc.

Feldman s responses 1. (R6) is difficult to interpret and assess. 2. It s hard to see any reason why we should accept (R6). No doubt our views about rationality are influenced by our culture, experiences, etc. But it doesn t follow that there are no facts about rationality. 3. (R6) seems to imply the absolutist claim (A1) that: It is always really rational for a person to conform to the locally accepted standards of rationality.

Feldman writes (p. 181): Response #3 Finally, it is difficult to see why someone who defends (R6) is not committed to a form of absolutism anyway. Such a person thinks that all there is to rationality is local standards. Why not say, then, that what is really rational for a person is whatever is demanded by local standards. That is, (R6) seems to be equivalent to (A1) This seems really bizarre. Barnes and Bloor are saying that rational norms are mere social constructs. There is no such thing as what is really rational for a person!!

What do we think about (R6) epistemic relativism? (Are there better criticisms than Feldman s?) My thoughts: Kuhn says that since paradigm shifts result in losses as well as gains, logic and experience alone do not determine which of two competing paradigms is superior. But Duhem s good sense might. Not all rational norms are local to the paradigm. (E.g. avoidance of ad hocery.) A priori knowledge to the rescue again. (This is just another way of looking at the problem of induction.)

Subjective Bayesianism According to Subjective Bayesianism, rationality is just a matter of one s beliefs conforming to the probability calculus (and hence Bayes theorem). There are no rational constraints on priors. Two scientists with the same evidence, but different priors, can reach very different conclusions. And both be rational. So this view is epistemically relativist, up to a point. (This is partly why I advocate Objective Bayesianism.)

Epistemic relativism alethic? While it is helpful to separate alethic from epistemic relativism, they are not wholly unrelated just as rationality and truth are not unrelated. Rationality is a key guide to truth, especially in scientific questions that go far beyond experience. If we have no access to reality, and can t say what s true, then how is the notion of truth even meaningful to us? If there s no truth, then the insistence on rationality as a means to truth is bogus.