Phil 108, July 15, 2010

Similar documents
Philosophy 1100: Ethics

The Trolley Problem. 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases:

-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use:

Quinn s DDE. 1. Quinn s DDE: Warren Quinn begins by running through the familiar pairs of cases:

Intending Versus Foreseeing Harm

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2004

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2008

ETHICS. H istory, Theory, and Contemporary Issues. Steven M. Cahn. Peter Markie FOURTH EDITION. Edited by

Scanlon on Double Effect

Quinn s Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

18 Die Philippa Foot 1

Oxford Scholarship Online

Must Consequentialists Kill?

Judge s Two Options: he can (i) let the rioters kill the five hostages, or (ii) frame an innocent person for the crime, and have him executed.

Torture Does Timing Matter?

Thomson s turnabout on the trolley

The Additive Fallacy

Ethics is subjective.

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

So Close, Yet So Far: Why Solutions to the Closeness Problem for the Doctrine of Double Effect Fall Short 1

THOMSON S TROLLEY PROBLEM. Peter A. Graham

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

I may disappoint some of you when I say that the trolley problem I shall be talking about is not this one hard though it is, even after inspection of

Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Double Effect and Terror Bombing

inertia Moral Philos Stud (2008) 140: DOI /s x Sartorio Carolina

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

During the Second World War as V1 rockets rained down on London, Churchill made a fateful decision. He would protect the city center and its vital

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

DEFENDING DOUBLE EFFECT Ralph Wedgwood

Liability and the Limits of Self-Defense

Annotated models of disciplinary essays 3. Annotated Philosophy essay

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Self-Defense, Permissions, and the Means Principle: A Reply to Quong

Thresholds for Rights

Instructor: Niko Kolodny Office hours and contact info:

Scanlon s Investigation: The Relevance of Intent to Permissibility *

Instructor: Niko Kolodny Office hours and contact info:

THE BASIS OF MORAL LIABILITY TO DEFENSIVE KILLING. Jeff McMahan Rutgers University

Killing Innocent People

Life, Lottery, for the Pursuit of Organs

Moral. Dimensions. T. M. Scanlon PERMISSIBILITY, MEANING, BLAME

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

The Right to Cause Harm as an Alternative to Being Sacrificed for Others: An Exploration of Agent- Rights with a Special Focus on Intervening Agency

WORLD UTILITARIANISM AND ACTUALISM VS. POSSIBILISM

Introduction to. Ethics

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

Those of us who oppose torture, and who are acutely conscious of the grave

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Several influential court cases shaping our legal system over the year have

The Realm of Rights, Chapter 6, Tradeoffs Judith Jarvis Thomson

Animal Disenhancement

TWO DOGMAS OF DEONTOLOGY: AGGREGATION, RIGHTS, AND THE SEPARATENESS OF PERSONS

TOPIC 27: MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

The free will defense

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

Chapter 26: Causation And Ethics * ethical concepts, views, and problems. In particular, I discuss the role of causation in the family

CANCER CARE AND SAVING PARROTS. Hilary Greaves (Oxford) Philosophical foundations of effective altruism conference St Andrews, 30 March 2016

The Value of the Life of Reason ( ) Alonzo Fyfe

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Plato s Republic Book 3&4. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Aristotle and Double Effect

The Moral Significance of Animal Pain and Animal Death. Elizabeth Harman. I. Animal Cruelty and Animal Killing

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

A Platonic Theory of Reasons for Action. Ralph Wedgwood

The problem of evil & the free will defense

On Audi s Marriage of Ross and Kant. Thomas Hurka. University of Toronto

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

ON HARMING AND KILLING: REPLIES TO HANSER, PERSSON AND SAVULESCU, AND WASSERMAN

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

PHIL 202: IV:

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Maximalism vs. Omnism about Reasons*

Reductive Individualism and the Just War Framework

This handout follows the handout on Determinism. You should read that handout first.

Exploring Philosophy - Audio Thought experiments

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

The Trolley Problem. 11 Judith Jarvith Thomson Killing, Letting Die and the Trolley Problem (1976) 59 Oxford University Press 204-

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

A Discussion on Kaplan s and Frege s Theories of Demonstratives

Sentimentalism, Blameworthiness, and Wrongdoing

The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing II: The Moral Relevance of the Doing Allowing Distinction

A Contractualist Reply

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

The Nature of Death. chapter 8. What Is Death?

Welcome, everyone, and thank you for being here, as we gather together to. worship together, to join with each other in adoration of our heavenly

HOW TO BE RESPONSIBLE FOR SOMETHING WITHOUT CAUSING IT* Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

Jesus Alone. Session 6 1 JOHN 5:1-12

Transcription:

Phil 108, July 15, 2010 Foot on intending vs. foreseeing and doing vs. allowing: Two kinds of effects an action can have: What the agent merely foresees will happen because of his action. What the agent intends. His end, and what he believes are means to that end. The Doctrine of Double Effect: In some cases, it is not wrong to X if one merely foresees that Y will happen, even though it would be wrong to X if one intended for Y to happen. The DDE is important in Catholic teaching. The DDE does not say that this is true in all cases. For example, just as it is wrong for gravediggers to give away poisonous oil in order to have more people to bury (intending their deaths), so too it is wrong for merchants to sell poisonous oil in order to make money (merely foreseeing their deaths). What is the difference? Perhaps: the DDE applies only when X-ing brings about a better state of affairs. Note that consequentialism requires us to bring about a better state of affairs, and does not treat intending any differently from foreseeing. The DDE can be thought of as a constraint on consequentialist reasoning. We may not bring about a better state of affairs if we intend to harm others, but we may, at least in some cases, if we only foresee that others will be harmed. Problems for the DDE: The DDE gives the intuitively right answer that it is permissible to remove a uterus even though it is foreseen that this will kill the fetus. But it gives the intuitively wrong answer that it is not permissible to crush the fetus s skull in order to save the mother s life. (Or, at least, it seems intuitively incorrect that the one action should be permissible, but the other action impermissible.) Objection: The DDE does not lead to the wrong answer, since the death of the fetus is not a means to saving the mother s life. If the fetus could somehow survive the operation, it is not as though our end would not be achieved. Reply: This makes the DDE too permissive. For example, we can say about the fat man in the mouth of the cave, We don t intend to kill him, only to blow him to small bits. Moral: To close this loophole, we need to specify when effects that are not strictly necessary for the intended end (such as breaking the fat man into smaller pieces) are still so closely related to the intended end that they should count as intended means. What is this relation of closeness? The appeal of the DDE: How do we distinguish the framing case from the trolley case? The DDE gives us an answer: In the trolley case, we are diverting the trolley from the five, merely foreseeing that it will hit the one. In the framing case, we are framing the one in order to save the five. Likewise, how do we distinguish the case of using the medicine we have to save five instead of one from the case of killing one in order to make a serum from his body to save five? Foot s diagnosis of the appeal of the DDE: We confuse the intending/foreseeing distinction with the doing/allowing distinction. It is really the doing/allowing distinction that matters morally. The two distinctions can also come apart: One can intend to allow something to happen (e.g., allowing it can be a means to one s end, as in the case of using the beggar for medical research below).

One can do things that one does not intend (e.g., one kills the one by diverting the trolley, but one intends only to divert it from the five, and merely foresees that it will kill the one). Positive and Negative Duties: What we allow to happen to people is governed by our positive duties, which say what we owe people in terms of aid. What we do to people is governed by our negative duties, which say what owe people in terms of noninterference, noninjury. In general, negative duties are stronger than positive duties. How the doing/allowing distinction handles the cases: In the trolley case, we have a conflict of a negative duty not to kill the one vs. five negative duties not to kill each of the five. In the framing case, we have a conflict of a negative duty not to frame the one vs. many positive duties to aid each person in danger of the mob. So it is not inconsistent to hold that it is wrong to frame the one, but not wrong to send the trolley to roll over the one. In the case of merely distributing the medicine, we have a conflict of a positive duty to aid the one vs. many positive duties to aid each of the others. In the case of turning the one into medicine, we have a conflict of a negative duty not to kill the one vs. many positive duties to aid each of the others. So it is not inconsistent to hold that it is wrong to turn the one into medicine, but not wrong to give the medicine to others. Rescuing one or five from torture by the tyrant: conflict of positive duties. Torturing one oneself in order to save the five from torture by the tyrant: conflict of a positive with a negative duty. Not inconsistent to say that it is not wrong to rescue the five, but is wrong to torture one oneself. To refrain from inflicting injury ourselves is a stricter duty than to prevent other people from inflicting injury, which is not to say that the other is not a very strict duty indeed. A case that the positive/negative distinction and DDE treat differently: Suppose, for instance, that there are five patients in a hospital whose lives could be saved by the manufacture of a certain gas, but that this inevitably releases lethal fumes into the room of another patient whom for some reason we are unable to move. Wrong, because we violate a negative duty to that patient in order to fulfill positive duties to the others. But we do not intend to kill that patient, merely foresee that he will die. In an interesting variant of the model, we may suppose that instead of killing someone we deliberately let him die. (Perhaps he is a beggar to whom we are thinking of giving food, but then we say No, they need bodies for medical research. ) Here it does seem relevant that in allowing him to die we are aiming at his death, but presumably we are inclined to see this as a violation of negative rather than positive duty. But if so, doesn t it suggest that the negative/positive distinction is not the same as the doing/allowing distinction, and that the negative/positive distinction is the one that matters? Why is this as a violation of a negative duty? After all, it s a refusal to aid.

Isn t it plausible to say that the difference is that one intends the beggar s death in this case, but does not intend the death of the one when one gives medicine to the five? Doesn t the DDE explain this case? Perhaps the intending/foreseeing distinction is a further factor. One may fail to fulfill one s positive duty to the one in order to fulfill positive duties to others, but not if one intends that the one will be harmed as a result. Allowing someone to die of starvation before one s eyes is just as wrong as poisoning him. Why? Perhaps because, in these cases, the positive and negative duties do not conflict with any other duties. But this does not explain why allowing people in other countries to die of starvation is not as wrong as poisoning them. Other factors that may matter: Strict duty vs. charity: our own children vs. children in other countries Is the person not already threatened? Is the person himself the threat? Three abortion cases: Assume that the fetus has the same rights as an adult. 1. Nothing can be done to save the fetus, but by killing the fetus we can save the mother. Here the DDE says we may not kill the child in order to save the mother, which seems wrong. (Doesn t the positive/negative distinction say the same thing? We are violating our negative duty to the fetus in order to fulfill our positive duty to the mother. Isn t the explanation of why it is permissible to kill the fetus that it has no strong interest in not being killed, because it will die anyway very soon?) 2. Either we kill the mother to save the fetus, or kill the fetus to save the mother. The fact that we would be killing one in order to save the other does not resolve the conflict of interests, since this is true whether we save the fetus or the mother. The question is just whom to save. (Why doesn t the positive/negative distinction say that we must let both die?) 3. The fetus will otherwise live, but by killing the fetus we can save the mother. The right answer is that we should not do this (again, assuming that the fetus is a person). The DDE gives the right answer, but for the wrong reason. The positive/negative distinction gives the right answer for the right reason: we may not kill one person in order to save another. The big questions: Is there a consistent distinction between aiding and noninterfering/noninjuring? Does it matter morally? If so, why? Thomson s solution to the Trolley Problem: The original puzzle: Why is the agent, in Trolley, permitted to turn the trolley onto the one, which will save the five but, in Transplant, not permitted to take the one s organs, which will save the five? What is the difference between Trolley and Transplant? Foot s answer: In Transplant, the choice is between a doing and an allowing: killing one and letting five die.

Since doings are worse than allowings since negative rights not to be injured, not to have harms done to you are stronger than positive rights to be saved from harms, not to have harms allowed to befall you killing the one is wrong. In Trolley, the choice is between two doings: killing one and killing five. Here the fact that negative rights are stronger than positive rights is irrelevant. The agent will kill someone, and violate negative rights, no matter what he does. So killing the one is (at very least) not wrong. An objection to Foot s answer: In Bystander at the Switch, the choice is between killing one and merely letting five die. So, as far as Foot s answer is concerned, it should be impermissible to turn the trolley, just as it is impermissible to take the organs in Transplant. But it is not impermissible to turn the trolley. It seems more or less equivalent to the original Trolley case. So (assuming that our intuitions do not mislead us) there must be some other morally relevant difference between Bystander and Transplant. In Repentance, the doctor intentionally caused the organ failure in the five, but now repents. So his choice is between killing five and killing one. So, as far as Foot s answer is concerned, it should be permissible to take the one s organs, just as it is permissible to turn the trolley in Trolley. But it is not permissible to take the one s organs. It seems more or less equivalent to the original Transplant case. The new puzzle: What is the difference between Bystander and Transplant, and between Repentance and Trolley? Objections to some attempted answers: 1. Transplant uses the one as a means to save the five, whereas Bystander does not. Objection: Loop uses the one as a means to saving the five, but this is still permissible. It seems more or less like Bystander. 2. Transplant infringes a right, whereas Bystander does not. Objection: One infringes a right in Bystander also. Suppose one turns the trolley toward the one when there were no others to save. Surely this would infringe a right. And even when there are others to save, and turning the trolley is permissible, one still wrongs the one. For example, one might be expected to apologize to his family. The relevant differences between Transplant and Bystander: (1) The Bystander saves the five by making something that threatens them instead threaten one. He only diverts an existing threat; he does not create a new threat. (2) The Bystander does not do (1) by means which themselves constitute an infringement of any right of the one s. Condition (1): only diverting an existing threat: The bystander who proceeds does not merely minimize the number of deaths which get caused: He minimizes the number of deaths which get caused by something that already threatens people, and that will cause deaths whatever the bystander does. The bystander who proceeds does not make something be a threat to people which would otherwise not be a threat to anyone; he makes be a threat to fewer what is already a threat to more.

An illustration: Recall Foot s Hospital: There are five patients in a hospital whose lives could be saved by the manufacture of a certain gas, but that this will inevitably release lethal fumes into the room of another patient whom for some reason we are unable to move. Making the gas is impermissible. But now consider a case in which lethal fumes are being released by the heating system in the basement of a building next door to the hospital. The fumes are headed towards the room of five. We can deflect them towards the room of one. Deflecting the gas is permissible Condition (2): not infringing the rights of the one Why do we need this restriction? In Fat Man(!), we push the fat man off of the footbridge in order to stop the trolley. We make what threatens the five (i.e., the trolley) threaten the one instead. But this still seems impermissible. Explanation: Pushing someone off a footbridge is an infringement of his rights. By contrast, turning the trolley in Bystander does not infringe the rights of the one. Another explanation? We don t divert a threat onto the fat man? Objection: What about wobbling the handrail? That doesn t infringe his rights. Reply: But wobbling isn t the entire means to saving the five. The entire means requires somehow knocking him off of the footbridge, which does infringe his rights. Objection: Isn t it permissible to steal a nailfile from the one, or to trespass his property, or to break a promise to him in order to turn the trolley? Reply: Maybe (2) should require that the infringed right be particularly stringent. Question: According to this theory, it is impermissible to kill the one in Repentance. (Why?) But suppose that a doctor faces a similar choice in the present. He must choose between poisoning the five or killing the one. Here it is permissible to kill the one. Why should the present tense matter so much? Reply: The present tense matters because the question for the agent at the time of acting is about the present: Which of the alternatives here and now open to me may I choose? Question: What do you think Unger would say about these intuitions? Reply: Take your own guess, based on what you have already read. (If you are interested, you can read what Unger says, by accessing the rest of his book online.)