Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity. As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s

Similar documents
The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Plato s Concept of Soul

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Introduction to Philosophy

Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Dr. Jason Sheley

Ancient History Sourcebook: Plato: The Republic - The philosopherking

Full file at

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Practical Wisdom and Politics

On the Relationship between Moral Virtue and Philosophy in Republic

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

First, let me briefly indicate what I mean by Platonism by recalling a few aspects of the Republic s Parable of the Cave.

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Introduction to Philosophy Practice Exam One. True or False A = True, B= False

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Does Marilyn Strathern Argue that the Concept of Nature Is a Social Construction?

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

e x c e l l e n c e : an introduction to philosophy

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Collection and Division in the Philebus

Mitigating Operator-Induced Vehicle Mishaps

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Department of Philosophy

ETHICAL THEORIES. Review week 6 session 11. Ethics Ethical Theories Review. Socrates. Socrate s theory of virtue. Socrate s chain of injustices

Honours Programme in Philosophy

1/12. The A Paralogisms

[Glaucon] You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners.

The Goodness of God in the Judaeo-Christian Tradition

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Why Plato's Cave? Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY MEANING NATURE SCOPE GOALS IMPORTANCE BRANCHES EPOCH

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Framingham State University Syllabus PHIL 101-B Invitation to Philosophy Summer 2018

Internalization and the Philosophers Best Interest in Plato s Republic

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Theories of the Self. Description:

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Introduction to Ethics

Introduction to Ethics Part 2: History of Ethics. SMSU Spring 2005 Professor Douglas F. Olena

Montreat Honors Program Scholar s Day Class Discussion Preparatory Reading

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

National Quali cations

Voegelin and Machiavelli vs. Machiavellianism. In today s day and age, Machiavelli has been popularized as the inventor or

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

Nicomachean Ethics. Book VI

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Christianity. and the Role of. Philosophy

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

W E D N E S D AY, M A R C H 9,

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Pablo Ruiz Picasso Spain. Whenever I have wanted to express something, I have done so without thinking of the past or the future

Doctrine of God. Immanuel Kant s Moral Argument

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

Plato s Republic. Important Terms

PLATO. The Allegory of the Cave. Translated by Shawn Eyer

Transcription:

Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity Geoffrey Plauché POLI 7990 - #1 September 22, 2004 As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s interpretation of Plato, I have realized a combination of growing fascination and unease. To be sure, the so-called politics of transcendence has an enticing appeal. Yet in Platonic idealism there lies a dangerous passivity that results from, in a sense, setting the bar too high. A lucky internet search produced an article by Claes Ryn in Humanitas entitled The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism 1 that I find mirrors my thoughts on the matter and helped to clarify them. Though I think it is possible that Ryn goes too far in ascribing to Plato the intention of rationalizing his aversion to the politics of his day, I do agree that Plato sets too high a moral standard for political activity (and perhaps other forms of activity as well). I will argue further that Plato sets too high a standard for what qualifies as knowledge, and that this at least partly explains why he sets too high a standard for political ethics as well as for philosophers and rulers. Plato is left with an irresolvable paradox: the good polis requires philosopherkings to rule because the people are incapable of ruling themselves, yet the philosopher s moral scruples prevent him from entering politics. The epistemological problem that Plato had to deal with was the issue of how dialectic can objectively discover knowledge about basic premises and ultimate ends. In other words, Plato had to defend, against the Sophists, the position that rationality is not only procedural but also substantive, i.e., that rationality can not only evaluate inferences 1 Claes G. Ryn, The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism, Humanitas, Volume XII, No. 2, 1999; http://www.nhinet.org/ryn12-2.htm. 1

from basic premises but the basic premises themselves (theoretical rationality) and not only the means to ultimate ends but the ultimate ends themselves (practical rationality). Dialectic takes as its starting point our initial, unreflective beliefs. As such they are not systematic and are consequently full of error. The dialectic process, through questioning and answering, traces the implications and resolves the conflicts between our beliefs. The problem that a defender of substantive rationality has to face is that whatever results from the dialectic process, it would still seem to rest upon the flimsy foundation of our initial, unreflective beliefs. Our conclusions can only be as reliable as our premises. Yet surely we do not want to admit the conclusion that reason is incapable of discovering true knowledge of basic premises and ultimate ends. Plato s solution to this problem is to view our starting beliefs not as premises but as stepping stones or ladders that we use to climb to the height where we can somehow grasp the basic premises and ultimate ends, and then descend to ultimate conclusions based on them (511b). The dialectic method is the only one that can proceed in this manner, of acquiring true knowledge on the basis of what is not known (533c-d). How it does so is a mystery, however. Plato can but describe the process, through Socrates, by way of a metaphor. The dialectic process is akin to a turning around of the eyes from night that seemed day to true day. As the luminosity of the sun not only makes sight possible but also the generation and growth and nurture (509b) of life, so does the Form of the Good (Beautiful) allow the philosopher not only to see truth and know true knowledge but it is itself what gives the objects of knowledge their truth (508b-509b). Epistemologically, the Form of the Good is the first principle of theoretical and practical reason, because metaphysically it is the first principle of being and value. 2

In rescuing substantive rationality, however, Plato consigns it to the realm of mysticism. At the highest level, when one grasps the Form of the Good, the process less resembles reason than simply seeing by some sort of intuition. It cannot be taught. A teacher does not implant knowledge lacked by the student. The teacher can only adequately prepare the soul of his student, or lead it around, so that the soul focuses on the knowledge it had been overlooking (518b-d). 2 It may help to briefly contrast Plato s epistemology with Aristotle s. Aristotle lowers the standard for what qualifies as knowledge to a more reasonable level by classifying commonly held yet reputable beliefs (or endoxa) as knowledge. From these, we dialectically ascend to first principles and then deductively back down to conclusions based on these first principles. The grasp of first principles and the conclusions derived from them, he calls scientific understanding. On this view, we are justified in holding our reputable beliefs, while not as precise or fully understood as scientific understanding, to be knowledge so long as our beliefs cohere with one another (i.e., do not conflict). Plato s excessively high standard for what qualifies as knowledge can be seen to affect his political ethics in the following passage: At least, what appears to me is, that in the world of the known, last of all, is the idea of the good, and with what toil to be seen! And seen, this must be inferred to be the cause of all right and beautiful things for all in the world of mind, herself the queen produces truth and reason; and she must be seen by one who is to act with reason publicly or privately. (517c) If one is to act wisely in public or private life, then one must be able to see the Good and only the true philosophers have that level of understanding. Among the traits necessary to be a true philosopher are: being in love with learning (485a-b), to love the truth and be without falsehood (485c), temperance (485e), lacking too great an esteem for life and fear 2 See also, Plato s Seventh Letter, 344b. 3

of death (486a-b), lacking a cowardly and mean nature (486b), just and gentle (486b), teachable (486c), not forgetful (486c-d), a naturally well-proportioned and graceful mind (486d). When such men have been perfected by education and the experience of age, they will be ready to rule as philosopher-kings and to them alone should rule be granted (487a), for the uneducated and those lacking experience of truth could never properly supervise a city (519c). However, outside of the good polis, those who could become true philosophers are easily corrupted (492a-b, 495a-c). Consequently, only a rare few will have the fortitude and insight to remain true, uncorrupted philosophers. Once the philosopher has ascended to an understanding of the Good, he will not want to come back down and return to the Cave, so to speak, to aid his fellow men by entering politics (516d, 517c). Socrates himself admits to such an aversion: My own case is not worth mentioning, the spiritual sign, for I believe that such a thing has never or hardly ever happened to anyone before. Those who belong to this little band have tasted how sweet and delectable their treasure is, and they have seen sufficiently the madness of the multitude; they know that in public life hardly a single man does any act that has any health in it, and there is no ally who would stand by anyone going to the help of justice, and would save him from destruction. Such a champion would be like a man fallen among wild beasts; he would never consent to join in wickedness, but one alone he could not fight all the savages. So he would perish before he could do any good to the city or his friends, useless both to himself and to others. When the philosopher considers all this he keeps quiet and does his own business, like one who runs under a wall for shelter in a storm when dust and sleet is carried before the wind. He sees others being filled full of lawlessness, and he is content if somehow he can keep himself clean from injustice and impious doings, and so live his life on earth and in the end depart in peace and good will with beautiful hopes. (496c-e) Clearly, Plato means this account to include not only Socrates but all true philosophers, yet this passage seems to contradict Socrates own behavior unless one excludes Socrates doings from the realm of politics. 4

In any case, if one restricts the definition of politics to governance, then Plato has no means of bringing about a good polis under the rule of philosopher-kings except by a historical fluke. Socrates notes that the philosopher will appear awkward and foolish to his fellow men (517d). It is not appropriate for true philosophers to seek out and woo those he would rule and build into a good polis; the people should come to them willingly as a patient does to a doctor (489b-c). However, neither option will bear fruit, for if the philosopher is morally restrained from entering politics, cannot solicit others to come under his rule, and appears useless if not dangerous to the public, then there is no reason to expect the public to seek him out as a ruler. Even the behavior that got Socrates executed would seem to be out of the question because it is too dangerous. And even the single remaining hope that Socrates holds out for the good polis, an existing ruler becoming a philosopher, is doomed to failure as it seems highly improbable that he will also possess subjects wise enough to accept his new policies. It is not impossible, as Socrates contends, but it is so close as to make the difference negligible. Plato, then, has set his standard for political ethics too high for philosophers to enter politics. This is at least in part attributable to his excessively high standard for what qualifies as knowledge. Also, due to his conception of knowledge, he views the people as being incapable of ruling themselves wisely as they are incapable of wisdom. If only the true philosophers are suited to rule but can only rule in the good polis, then Plato is left with an irresolvable paradox. He must rely upon a well-nigh impossible chance that incredibly complex historical forces will come together just so, and even then he admits that the good polis will not last long beyond the moment of its inception (545d-547c). Humanity thus seems consigned to perpetual injustice and barbarism, and the philosopher 5

to passive contemplation of the Good. If the Republic is concerned with transcendence, then transcendence for Plato appears apolitical and ahistorical, except insofar as it is a reaction against both politics and history. 6