Collection and Division in the Philebus

Similar documents
Plato s Rationalistic Method. Hugh H. Benson. (please cite that version)

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Plato's Introduction of Forms (review)

Knowledge in Plato. And couple of pages later:

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

A Priori Bootstrapping

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Plato versus Aristotle

What God Could Have Made

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

MENO. We must first define Platonic Dialogue and then consider the Meno.

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

The Priority of Definition. Continuum Companion to Socrates Edd. Bussanich and Smith. Hugh H. Benson

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Skepticism and Internalism

Overview Plato Socrates Phaedo Summary. Plato: Phaedo Jan. 31 Feb. 5, 2014

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Socrates Young and Old: From the Parmenides to the Phaedo. The Parmenides is the earliest of Plato s Socratic dialogues (I mean the dialogues in which

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Dr. Jason Sheley

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

D. The Truth as a Surd

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977)

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Reading a Platonic Dialogue. Dramatic Structure Substantive Issues Methodological Issues

7AAN2004 Early Modern Philosophy report on summative essays

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

The Death of Socrates & the Theory of the Forms (6/27-7/1) Phaedo (entiredialogue; available online)

The Question of Metaphysics

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Scanlon on Double Effect

Metaphysics, science, and religion: a response to Hud Hudson

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

1/12. The A Paralogisms

AQUINAS: EXPOSITION OF BOETHIUS S HEBDOMADS * Introduction

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Transcription:

Collection and Division in the Philebus 1 Collection and Division in the Philebus Hugh H. Benson Readers of Aristotle s Posterior Analytics will be familiar with the idea that Aristotle distinguished roughly between definitional and non-definitional propositions 1, and even that he may have recognized distinct methods for acquiring knowledge of these sorts of propositions. 2 I hypothesize that a roughly similar understanding of Plato provides a resolution to a longstanding difficulty in Platonic scholarship. 3 The difficulty arises from the following observations: 1. The hypothetical method described and practiced in the Meno, Phaedo, and Republic is distinct from the method of collection and division described and/or practiced in Sophist, Politicus, and Philebus. 2. The hypothetical method is Plato s recommended method for knowledge acquisition in the Meno, Phaedo, and Republic. 4 3. Collection and division is Plato s recommended method for knowledge acquisition in the Philebus. 5 4. Collection and division introduced in the Phaedrus is roughly identical to collection and division described and/or practiced in the Sophist, Politicus, and Philebus. 5. The Phaedrus was composed roughly around the same time as the Republic. If these five observations are correct, we have three options. First, we might suppose that Plato endorses at roughly the same time two distinct methods of acquiring the same knowledge. 6 Second, we might suppose that Plato abandons one method of knowledge acquisition and proposes a new one in short order. 7 And, third, we might suppose that Plato distinguishes two different sorts of knowledge, one to be acquired by the hypothetical method of the Meno, Phaedo, and Republic, and the other to be acquired by collection and division of the Phaedrus, Sophist, Politicus, and Philebus. The third option leads in the direction of my hypothesis. I will not here defend or even develop such a hypothesis. My goal here is more circumscribed. My goal is to consider the observations that generate the difficulty that the hypothesis attempts to resolve. Specifically, it is to consider observation [4] as it pertains to the Philebus. I maintain that Socrates description of the finer way at Philebus 16c-17a is a fairly explicit 1 See Posterior Analytics II.1 89b24-27. 2 See Posterior Analytics II. 3 A version of this difficulty is what Stenzel (1973), 149, calls the shibboleth of Platonic scholarship. 4 I have been attempting to defend this observation in a series of recent papers. 5 See Philebus 16c2-3 and 16e3-4. 6 See Hackforth (1952), 135. 7 See Kahn (1996).

2 Hugh H. Benson reference to the method introduced in the Phaedrus. That is, the method of knowledge acquisition endorsed by Plato in the Philebus is roughly identical to the method of knowledge acquisition endorsed in the Phaedrus. My argument has the form of a Moorean argument against skepticism. The allusions in the Philebus passages to the Phaedrus passages are sufficiently striking that any evidence we have against the identification of the two methods is weaker than the evidence we have in favor of the identification. While there are reasons to doubt the identification, those reasons generally depend on controversial interpretations of difficult texts, and consequently are considerably less manifest than the identity they are offered to debunk. After quickly rehearsing the evidence for the identity, I will look at the most troubling objections. Of course, to maintain that the finer way of the Philebus is roughly identical to collection and division in the Phaedrus is hardly shocking or unique. But it should suffice to discourage a common misunderstanding of collection and division deriving at least in part from Robinson s groundbreaking study of Platonic method - Plato s Earlier Dialectic. As title of the book suggests, the absence of any discussion in the book of collection and division is a consequence of Robinson s view that this method characterizes Plato s later dialectic. 8 Unless we are to follow Robinson and others of an earlier generation of scholarship by placing the Phaedrus among the later dialogues (contrary to observation [5]), we must abandon the idea that collection and division is a new method of dialectic distinct from the method of dialectic discussed in middle dialogues like the Meno, Phaedo, and Republic. While Plato does indeed develop this method in late dialogues, his discussion of it in the Philebus indicates that the method is roughly the same as the method introduced in the Phaedrus. One final preliminary before turning to the description of collection and division in Phaedrus. I will be focusing on the descriptions of the method in the Phaedrus and the Philebus as opposed to its applications. Collection and division is undeniably employed predominately in Plato s so-called later dialogues - see especially the Politicus and Sophist - rather than in the so-called middle dialogues, while its application in the Phaedrus is suspect. Why this should be so is an interesting question that needs to be pursued elsewhere. But if the thesis of this essay is correct it cannot be because Plato has not yet introduced and endorsed the method. A Quick Review of the Phaedrus The following features of collection and division are immediately apparent from the three passages in which Socrates introduces the method in the Phaedrus (265c-266c, 273d-e, and 277b). Collection and division consists of two movements of thought [i] seeing together things that are scattered about everywhere and collecting them into one kind (mian idean) [ii] be[ing] able to cut up each kind according to its species (kat eidê) along its natural joints. Socrates is an erastês of these divisions and collections (266b3-4). Whenever he encounters anyone able to to discern a single thing that is also by nature capable of encompassing many he follows him as though he were a god (266b5-7). He calls those who practice this method dialecticians (266b8-c1). Collection and division is necessary for composing speeches with technê (277b5-c6). Socrates recommends this method and attempts to emulate it or practice it. 8 Perhaps also see Kahn (1996), 298, McCabe (2000), 198 199, and Silverman (2000), 9.

Collection and Division in the Philebus 3 The Finer Way in the Philebus After Socrates criticizes those who delight in puzzles concerning one-many in statements Protarchus asks Socrates to find a finer way to pursue the logos. In response Socrates offers perhaps the longest description of collection and division in the dialogues at 16c5-17a5. 9 Socrates follows this exposition with a series of examples of this finer way. In response to puzzles about the one-many the gods handed down a method that consisted of two stages - positing a single form (mian idean) for everything and looking for it and having grasped the one, looking for two or three or however many there are. This latter inquiry does not end until the inquirer knows that the one arrived at by the first inquiry is one, many, indefinite, and how many. Plato here suggests that the finer way consists of two stages or movements - a movement toward unity or the one and a movement away from unity or the one, just as collection and division as described in the Phaedrus consisted of similar stages. Lest we miss this similarity, Plato appears adamant in calling our attention to it. Plato suggests the divine nature of both methods - obviously in the Philebus by providing it with a divine pedigree, but only slightly less obviously in the Phaedrus when he testifies to following around anyone who practiced it as though he were divine. Plato also highlights the salience of both methods to technê. In the Phaedrus, he makes clear that speech making is only expert insofar as it employs collection and division and here in the Philebus Plato makes clear that the finer way is responsible for bringing to light everything that has been discovered in the domain of any skill (technês) [16c2-3; Gosling trans.]. And, of course, just as he calls those who practice collection and division in the Phaedrus dialectical or dialecticians, so in the Philebus he distinguishes between those who practice the finer way incompletely and those who practice it completely by describing the former as behaving eristically and the latter as behaving dialectically. But perhaps most dramatically, just as he has Socrates describe himself as an erastês of collection and division in the Phaedrus, so here in the Philebus he has Socrates describe himself as an erastês of the finer way. It is difficult to imagine in light of these allusions that Plato does not intend the reader of the Philebus to have the Phaedrus collection and division in mind. Distinct Ontologies Nevertheless, not everyone would be sympathetic with this identification of the finer way of the Philebus with Phaedrus collection and division. In particular, at least two difficulties stand in the way of a simple identification - first, that the ontology underlying the two methods appears to be importantly different, and second that collection may have disappeared from the Philebus. Exactly how the first difficulty is supposed to go is not always clear, but the general point seems to be that Platonic ontology is intimately related to his epistemology and so presumably to his method of acquiring knowledge. 10 Consequently, a change in ontology entails a change in methodology. Sometimes this is put by claiming that collection and division in the Phaedrus is ontologically committed. It is, so to speak, a method of collecting and dividing forms, or forms of a specific type. The finer way of the Philebus, however, does not depend on forms or forms of the relevant type. It cannot. Forms or forms of the relevant type are missing from the Philebus. Other times this objection is put by claiming that the finer way of the Philebus depends on the fourfold ontology of Philebus 23c-27c. Collection and 9 Plato exemplifies the method at length in the Politicus and the Sophist (and perhaps in the Philebus), but he does not describe the method to the extent he does here in the Philebus. 10 See Thomas (2006).

4 Hugh H. Benson division of the Phaedrus, however, does not. Again, it cannot. The fourfold ontology is missing from the Phaedrus. 11 On behalf of the first version of this difficulty it must be admitted that the language of forms is abundant in the Phaedrus passages. In two of the three Phaedrus passages Socrates describes the collection stage as culminating in one form (mian idean; mia idea), while all three passages mention dividing according to forms (kat eidê). But similar language occurs in the relevant passages of the Philebus. At 16d1 Socrates describes the first stage as positing one form (mian idean) and at 20a6 and 20c4 Socrates appears to be referring to the second stage as distinguishing forms (eidê, eidôn). 12 So, language alone does not require a different ontology and so methodology. Nevertheless, the obscurity of the phrase at 16c9-10 with which Socrates introduces the finer way may suggest that the objects on which the two methods are employed are importantly distinct. The things that are said to be one and many here in the Philebus have been variously interpreted as ordinary sensible objects, 13 forms, 14 both, 15 and a variety of other things. 16 So, if collection and division in the Phaedrus is restricted to forms, and if the Philebus phrase is taken to be referring to anything other than those forms, then the two methods will depend on distinct ontologies. But each conjunct of the antecedent of this conditional is controversial. The allusions in the Philebean description to the Phaedrus s description are considerably more straightforward. So, if the major premise of this objection is to be believed, viz. distinct ontologies entail distinct methodologies, the allusions ought to provide some evidence against those antecedents. So, we should not yet deny the identity of the two methods as a result of distinct ontologies. On behalf of the second version of the distinct ontologies objection, the reference to the peras/apeiria distinction in the obscure Philebus phrase might be thought to introduce an important ontological difference between the two dialogues and so the two methods. Certainly, the fourfold ontology of peras, apeiria, mixture, and cause introduced a few pages later in the Philebus at 23c-27c appears not to be anticipated in the so-called middle dialogues, and one would assume that the peras/apeiria distinction made use of in the finer way passage is identical to that distinction made use of in the fourfold ontology passage. But, despite the plausibility of this assumption, difficulties here abound. 17 So, once again we should hesitate to deny the identity of the two methods based on the denial of the identities of the two ontologies. Finally, the major premise on which both these versions of the distinct ontologies objection depends, viz. distinct ontologies entail distinct methodologies, is hardly self-evident. It is certainly true that Plato, especially, recognized a close relationship between ontology and epistemology and so presumably between ontology and methodology. Moreover, it is difficult to deny at least a subtle difference between the ontology of the Phaedrus and the ontology of the Philebus. But methodology identity conditions that require an identical ontology are too restrictive. More importantly, we have fairly good evidence that Plato would not require such restrictive identity conditions. Plato does not distinguish the method of hypothesis in the Meno from that method found in the Phaedo and/or the Republic simply because, as many 11 See, e.g., Waterfield (1980), 282, and Sayre (1983), 120. 12 See also 18c2 where Theuth is described as distinguishing a third form (eidos) of letter. 13 See Gosling (1975). 14 See Crombie (1962). 15 See Sayre (1983). 16 See, e.g., Benitez (1989), 42. 17 See most recently Dancy (2007).

Collection and Division in the Philebus 5 commentators believe, the ontologies of the Meno and the Phaedo/Republic are different. Further, the elenctic method as practiced in the early dialogues is the same method described in the Sophist as incapable of achieving positive results even though Plato s evaluation of the elenchus may be different in these dialogues and even though the ontology underlying the method has changed. So, Plato allows the method of hypothesis and the elenchus to be employed on distinct ontologies. Why, then, should we think that he would not permit collection and division to be employed on distinct ontologies? If it is thought that collection and division is essentially in some way tied to a specific ontology the allusions in the Philebus to collection and division in the Phaedrus and the differences in the two ontologies underlying these two dialogues ought to disabuse us of this thought. Jettisoning of Collection Of course distinct ontologies is not the only reason for denying the identity of collection and division in the Phaedrus with the finer way of the Philebus. Another common objection to this identity is that the finer way has jettisoned collection. 18 Now, whatever the subtleties of methodology identity conditions, one method that consists of two movements of thought - roughly from plurality to unity and from unity to plurality - and another method that consists of only one movement of thought - from unity to plurality - can hardly be considered to be substantially identical. But has the finer way of the Philebus been jettisoned collection? I think not. At 18a6-b4, when Socrates moves from the examples of letters and music to the example of Theuth, Socrates distinguishes two stages or movements of thought - a movement from unity to indeterminate nature which has been exemplified from 17a6-e5 and an opposite (to enantion) movement from the indeterminate to unity. (See 18a6-b4.) It is this opposite movement that the example of Theuth is supposed to illustrate. According to Socrates, Theuth began by notic[ing] the indeterminacy of vocal sound (18b6), and after distinguishing the vowels, from the semi-vowels, and from mutes, named them all element, the single link that makes them all one and knowledge of which is called grammatical technê (18c3-d2). Contrast what Socrates says in the Theuth example, with what he says about the example of music which precedes 18a6-b4. In the case of music the process apparently began by noticing sound as one (17c2), but leading to distinctions, e.g. low, high, and equal pitch, before arriving directly at the indeterminate plurality. These examples together with the transition passage between them suggest that Plato means to be contrasting two movements of thought - one from unity to indeterminate and one from indeterminate to unity. Having said this, I confess to running roughshod over a number of difficulties. Let me offer only the briefest response. First, phone, the terminus a quo so to speak of all three examples, is explicitly described as both indeterminate and one at 17b3-4. But that is precisely Plato s point, if the finer way is to be plausibly seen as a response to a one-many problem. Things like knowledge, pleasure, and phônê are both one and many/indeterminate. To resolve this apparent contradiction one should employ the finer way by considering the thing as a unity and moving toward the plurality until all of the intermediates are completely laid out and determined, or one can start by considering the thing as an indeterminate plurality (as Theuth did) and moving toward the unity, again until all of the intermediates are completely laid out and determined. Resolving 18 See all of those commentators who refer to the method of the Philebus and Politicus as division. Sayre (2006), 48 51 and 73 91, explicitly maintains that collection is replaced by paradigms in the Politicus.

6 Hugh H. Benson the apparent contradiction requires getting hold of the intermediates between the thing as a unity and the thing as a plurality. Whether one begins from the unity or the plurality is unimportant Second, I have without argument identified the indeterminate with plurality. The short answer to this is that if one does not, the finer way will be irrelevant as a solution to the onemany problem. Third, the familiar words for collection are absent in the Philebus. Two quick responses. First, while the language of collection is absent from the Theuth example, Theuth must collect the indeterminate phônê into groups of vowels, semi-vowels, and mutes, and ultimately these intermediates into elements. Second, the language of collection is not wholly absent from the Philebus. As Sayre (2006:49) has pointed out collections are called for by name no less than six times in the discussion of the fourfold ontology at 23c-27c; (see 23e5, 25a3, 25d5-6, 25d6-7 (twice), 25d8). There are further issues here, of course, but for now this must suffice. Conclusion In conclusion, I hope to have encouraged the belief that the method of knowledge acquisition described at Philebus 16c5-17a5 - the finer way - is the same as the method endorsed in the Phaedrus - the method of collection and division. Consequently, we can no longer read Plato as endorsing one method of knowledge acquisition in the so-called middle dialogues which he goes on to abandon in the later dialogues. Rather, Plato appears satisfied with endorsing two different methods of knowledge acquisition at roughly the same time. This calls for an explanation about which at present I can only speculate. So I won t.