PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Similar documents
Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Foundations of Bioethics

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Deontological Ethics

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Is Morality Rational?

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Tools Andrew Black CS 305 1

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Lecture 8: Deontology and Famine. Onora O Neill Kantian Deliberations on Famine Problems Peter Horban Writing a Philosophy Paper

The Pleasure Imperative

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Judging Subsistence Rights by their Duties Eric Boot

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Journalists have a tremendous responsibility. Almost every day, we make

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Introduction to Ethics

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

LYING TEACHER S NOTES

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2011 Class 26 - April 29 Kantian Ethics. Hamilton College Russell Marcus

CS305 Topic Introduction to Ethics

Lecture 23 Ethics Review

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Deontology. Marianne Talbot University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education

A primer of major ethical theories

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

5. John Akers, former chairman of IBM, argued that ethics are not important to economic competitiveness.

Ethical Dilemmas in Life and Society

acting on principle onora o neill has written extensively on ethics and political philosophy

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Quote. Analyzing Ethical Dilemmas. Chapter Two. Determining Moral Behavior. Integrity is doing the right thing--even if nobody is watching

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Against Individual Responsibility (Sinnott-Armstrong)

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder.

Duty Based Ethics. Ethics unit 3

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Legend has it that a custodian put an image of a fly in a urinal in Amsterdam s Schiphol

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Dr. Evangelia Papadaki. Curriculum Vitae

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

University of York, UK

Deontology. Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology

Transcription:

PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 13 March 22 nd, 2016 O Neill, A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

So far in this unit, we ve seen many different ways of judging right/wrong actions: Aristotle s virtue ethics said that right actions are generally those that hit the mean (midpoint) between two extremes (an excess & a deficiency) for that type of action wrong actions are at the extremes, or are of types which are simply wrong in themselves (like murder, theft, adultery) Hobbes contractarianism said that right & wrong actions are whatever the law permits/forbids John Stuart Mill s utilitarianism says right actions increase total pleasure, while wrong actions increase total pain Ø Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism, an approach to ethics where an action is judged right or wrong on the basis of its consequences.» Consequentialism is often contrasted with deontology, where an action is judged right or wrong on the basis of the morality of the rule one follows by performing that action. 2

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) presented his deontological ethical system in such works as Lectures on Ethics & Groundwork on the Metaphysics of Morals» He emphasizes duties to follow moral maxims (i.e., rules) as the basis for ethical action.» He insists that all moral judgments are made by using our reason, and that rational investigation leads us to discover objective laws of morality that apply universally. (Hence, he is very much a rationalist & a moral realist.)» Above all, he wanted a moral theory free from subjectivity & uncertainty, and criticized other systems for being too permissive. Onora O Neill (1941 present) is a British philosopher and politician (chair of the UK s Equality & Human Rights Commission) Her article A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics helpfully interprets and defends Kantian ethics. She will also outline some important differences between deontology & utilitarianism. 3

There s a reason we aren t reading Kant first-hand, by the way 4

O Neill explains the role of maxims (rules, principles) in Kant s ethics: According to Kant, each of our acts reflects one or more maxims.» The maxim of the act is the principle [according to] which one sees oneself as acting.» A maxim expresses a person's policy underlying the particular intention or decision on which he or she acts.» Whenever we act intentionally, we have at least one maxim and can, if we reflect, state what it is. (1-2) E.g., when I show up to give lectures, I follow maxims like Do your job & Share knowledge with others When we want to work out whether an act we propose to do is right or wrong, according to Kant, Ø we should look at our maxims, - not at how much misery or happiness the act is likely to produce, and whether it does better at increasing happiness than other available acts.» (Doing the latter would follow the Greatest Happiness Principle.) 5

For Kant, maxims function as imperatives, i.e. commands either to perform a particular action, or to refrain from performing an action. E.g., if you have a policy of giving away 10% of your income to charity, it s as if the maxim Give away 10% of your income commands you to behave accordingly. He says imperatives come in two types: categorical imperatives are those which govern our action at all times, no matter what interests or desires we have. Categorical here means unconditional, without exception, absolutely binding Ø Kant thinks all moral maxims are categorical imperatives, to which all human beings are strictly bound because our reason compels us to follow these rules. For Kant, to behave immorally is to act irrationally. hypothetical imperatives govern our behavior only under the condition that we have a particular interest/desire at a particular time. Hypothetical refers to the fact that these maxim apply only if one is in the relevant circumstances. The reading next class by Philippa Foot will examine these in depth. 6

Kant believes that he has derived three maxims which our actions absolutely must follow at all times. Ø He regards them as logically equivalent (as if they are three facets of a single rule), Ø and collectively calls them the Categorical Imperative : This is Kant s Supreme Principle of Morality. Each of its three formulas expresses one of the maxims we must obey. Formula of Universal Law:» Act as if the maxim of your action were to secure through your will a universal law of nature Formula of Kingdom of Ends» Act as if you were through your maxims a law-making member of a kingdom of ends Formula of the End in Itself Ø Following O Neill s lead, we will focus on this formula. But to get an idea of the others, video: bit.ly/1r6y1tx 7

O Neill explains, Kant states the Formula of the End in Itself as follows: Ø Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end. (1)» So, in order to figure out whether an action we are considering is morally acceptable, Ø We just have to check that the act we have in mind will not use anyone as a mere means, and, if possible, that it will treat other persons as ends in themselves. (2)» But to understand this we need to know what it is to treat a person as a means or as an end. (1) 8

To use someone as a mere means is to involve them in a scheme of action to which they could not in principle consent. (2) Using someone as a mere means is like treating them like a tool, pawn, or instrument, disregarding their freedom to a) rationally set their own goals, & b) choose their own course of actions to achieve those goals. Ø Another word for this is instrumentalization. O Neill explains that we often use people as means to ends: we have to do so in any cooperative scheme of action E.g. if I ask a friend to proofread my paper, I plan to use him/her as a means to eliminate typos & other mistakes. But in this case, each party consents to her or his part in the transaction, so this way of using of a person as a means is acceptable. Each person assumes that the other has maxims of his or her own and is not just a thing or a prop to be manipulated. (2)» What is unacceptable is using a person as a mere means which denies them a chance to opt in/out of acting. 9

So using someone as a means is not wrong in itself, as long as the person in question knows what action they are participating in & consents to participating. Ø What is wrong, Kant believes, is forcing someone to carry out an action 1. without giving them all the information necessary for them to decide whether or not they want to participate, 2. and/or without confirming that they agree to participate. For example, one person may make a promise to another with every intention of breaking it.» Successful false promising depends on deceiving the person to whom the promise is made about what one's real maxim is. And since the person who is deceived doesn't know that real maxim, he or she can't in principle consent to his or her part in the proposed scheme of action. The person who is deceived is, as it were, a prop or a tool a mere means in the false promisor's scheme. Hence, A person who promises falsely treats the acceptor of the promise as a prop or a thing [a mere means] and not as a person.» In Kant's view, it is this that makes false promising wrong. (2) 10

One standard way of using others as mere means is by deceiving them. By getting someone involved in a business scheme or a criminal activity on false pretenses, or by giving a misleading account of what one is about, or by making a false promise or a fraudulent contract, one involves another in something to which he or she in principle cannot consent, since the scheme requires that he or she doesn't know what is going on. (2)» E.g., the fast-food restaurant managers who were tricked by the strip-search phone scammer into violating an employee s rights were used as a mere means by the scammer, because they were deceived into believing that they were carrying out a police officer s orders to help catch a criminal Another standard way of using others as mere means by coercing them. (2) is Anytime you force someone to do something against their will even if it would lead to good consequences for them you use them as a mere means. 11

To summarize, in Kant's view, acts that are done on maxims that require deception or coercion of others, and so cannot have the consent of those others are wrong. When we act on such maxims, we treat others as mere means, as things rather than as ends in themselves. If we act on such maxims, our acts are not only wrong but unjust. (3) Ø This means that it is always wrong to lie (video: bit.ly/1tpdxcs) In contrast,» Aristotle agreed that honesty is a virtue, but would allow that there are surely some situations in which it is ok to lie.» Mill would say that it s ok to lie when it has good consequences, and only wrong to lie when it increases total harm. 12

One practical application of the Formula of the End in Itself is the issue of objectification,» i.e., treating a human being like an object or thing, instead of as a subject with thoughts & feelings. Ø Kant thinks that sexual desire is a very powerful force that conduces to the thinglike treatment of persons[:] the treatment of persons not as ends in themselves, He says: but as [mere] means or tool for the satisfaction of one s own desires. (Martha Nussbaum, Objectification) as soon as anyone becomes an object of the other s sexual] appetite, all motives of moral relationship fall away; as an object of the other s appetite, that person is in fact a thing, whereby the other s appetite is sated, and can be misused as such a thing by anybody. As soon as the person is possessed, and the appetite sated, they are thrown away, as one throws away a lemon after sucking the juice from it. (Lectures on Ethics, 156). 13

Why is objectification wrong, on a Kantian view of ethics? Ø It instrumentalizes people as things to be enjoyed, instead of respecting that they are rational human beings, who are imbued with reason and autonomy,» i.e., the power to rationally determine one s own ends & choose the means to those ends. As philosopher Catherine MacKinnon explained,» objectification cuts women off from full self-expression & self-determination from, in effect, their humanity Kant thinks marriage is the only solution to the problem of objectification. Objectification can be rendered harmless only if sexual relations are restricted to a relationship that is structured institutionally in ways that promote and, at least legally if not morally, guarantee mutual respect and regard. (Nussbaum 268-9) Ø Is this an acceptable solution? Ø What else could be done to remedy the problem? 14

O Neill elaborates on what it means to treat someone as an end in themself: To treat someone as an end in him or herself requires in the first place that one not use him or her as mere means, that one respect each as a rational person with his or her own maxims. Ø But beyond that, one may also seek to foster others' plans and maxims by sharing some of their ends : to be beneficent. To act beneficently is to seek others' happiness, therefore to intend to achieve some of the things that those others aim at with their maxims. If I want to make others happy, I will adopt maxims that not merely do not manipulate them but that foster some of their plans and activities. Beneficent acts aim to satisfy other people s desires.» However, we cannot seek everything that others want; their wants are too numerous and diverse, and, of course, sometimes incompatible.» It follows that beneficence has to be selective. (3) 15

According to O Neill, There is then quite a sharp distinction between the requirements of justice and [the requirements] of beneficence in Kantian ethics. Justice requires that we act on no maxims that use others as mere means. The Formula of the End in Itself says we are absolutely obligated to never instrumentalize other people. Beneficence requires that we act on some maxims that foster others' ends, though it is a matter for judgment & discretion which of their ends we foster. (4) The Formula says we ought to sometimes help other people but doesn t specify when or how often. Ø If we have to be selective about which of others ends to foster, how do we know whose ends to prioritize? At least Mill supplied a method of determining which pleasures are superior & more worth promoting. 16

Ø Let s do a comparative analysis of Kantian ethics & utilitarianism. Unlike utilitarians, Kantians are not committed to working interminably through a list of happiness-producing & misery-reducing acts. Kantians don t have to weigh every option for their actions, in terms of total happiness caused / total misery reduced.» Nor do they try to compare all available acts and see which has the best effects. They consider only the proposals for action that occur to them and check that these proposals use no other as mere means.» If they do not, the act is permissible;» if omitting [i.e., not performing] the act would use another as a mere means, the act is obligatory. (4) Ø So, as O Neill sees it, Kantian ethic requires less deliberation, and hence is simpler to follow. Kant s ethics does leave a lot of grey area when it comes to acting beneficently, though. 17

Ø Kantian ethics makes some actions obligatory are merely recommended by utilitarians. A Kantian would have to tell the axe murderer where his friend was, even though it would probably lead to the greatest total happiness to lie to the murderer and protect his friend. In contrast, a utilitarian allows that there are situations where lying to someone or tricking them are morally acceptable. 18

Ø O Neill notes that Kant's theory has less scope than utilitarianism it cannot weigh in on as many issues. Kantians may be reluctant to judge others' acts or policies that cannot be regarded as the maxim of any person or institution. Since it assesses actions by looking at the maxims of agents, it can only assess intentional acts, and not unintentional consequences of actions.» E.g., if a corporation adopts a policy which leads them to perform actions harmful to the environment, utilitarians can deem the corporation s action unethical because of its bad consequences, but Kantians can only judge the policy, and might determine the actions totally acceptable despite the harm they produce. Kantian ethics can do nothing to assess patterns of action that reflect no intention or policy, hence it cannot assess the acts of groups lacking decision-making procedures, such as the student movement, the women's movement, or the consumer movement. (4) 19

A common objection to utilitarianism is that Ø it is impossible for anyone to know in advance exactly what the consequences of their actions will be, so they can t use knowledge of the outcomes of an action to determine whether it is right or wrong. O Neill believes that Ø [Kant s] theory offers more precision than utilitarianism when data are scarce. One can usually tell whether one's act would use others mere means, even when its impact on human happiness is thoroughly obscure. (4) She highlights that it is usually possible for people to test their proposals by Kantian arguments even when they lack the comprehensive causal knowledge that utilitarianism requires. Conscientious Kantians can work out whether they will be doing wrong by some act even though they know that their foresight is limited and that they may cause some harm or fail to cause some benefit. But they will not cause harms that they can foresee without this being reflected in their intentions. (5) 20

But perhaps the greatest point of contrast between Kantian ethics & utilitarianism are their sharply contrasting views of the value of human life. Ø O Neill explains, In utilitarian thought persons are not ends in themselves. Their special moral status derives from their being means to the production of happiness. (6) O Neill thinks a utilitarian doesn t do good for others on the grounds that their lives are inherently valuable, but only because their happiness matters. Ø Moreover, utilitarianism sees nothing inherently wrong with instrumentalizing other people:» it is only wrong if it leads to bad consequences. There is nothing wrong with using another as a mere means, provided that the end for which the person is so used is a happier result than could have been achieved any other way, taking into account the misery the means have caused. (6) Ø A utilitarian might deem it acceptable to exploit workers in order to produce something that improves many people s lives (like The Panama Canal). 21

According to O Neill, the trouble with utilitarianism is that: sometimes human happiness demands the sacrifice of lives, including the sacrifice of unwilling lives. Further, for most utilitarians, it makes no difference if the unwilling sacrifices involve acts of injustice to those whose lives are to be lost. (6) She believes that Utilitarian moral theory has then a rather paradoxical view of the value of human life. Living, conscious humans are (along with other sentient beings) necessary for the existence of everything utilitarians value. But it is not their being alive but the state of their consciousness [i.e., their happiness] that is of value. Hence, the best results may require certain lives to be lost --by whatever means--for the sake of the total happiness and absence of misery that can be produced. (6) Ø However, some utilitarians (like Peter Singer) argue that that approach makes us obligated to save lives. (video: bit.ly/1mzjv7b) 22

O Neill says: Kantians reach different conclusions about human life. Human life is valuable because humans (and conceivably other beings, e.g., angels or apes) are the bearers of rational life. This capacity & its exercise are of such value that they ought not to be sacrificed for anything of lesser value. Therefore, no one rational or autonomous creature should be treated as mere means for the enjoyment or even the happiness of another. (6) Ø Note, though Kant does not believe that we have any moral obligations to promote the well-being of animals, the environment, or anything else that doesn t qualify as a rational agent (which might include some humans). We may in Kant's view justifiably--even nobly--risk or sacrifice our lives for others, for in doing so we follow our own maxim & nobody uses us as mere means. But no others may use either our lives or our bodies for a scheme that they have either coerced or deceived us into joining. For in doing so they would fail to treat us as rational beings; they would use us as mere means and not as ends in ourselves. (6) 23

O Neill concludes: It is conceivable that a society of Kantians, all of whom took pains to use no other as mere means, would end up with less happiness or with fewer persons alive than would some societies of complying utilitarians. For since the Kantians would be strictly bound only to justice, they might without wrongdoing be quite selective in their beneficence & fail to maximize either survival rates or happiness (7) On the other hand, nobody will have been made an instrument of others' survival or happiness in the society of complying Kantians. (7) Ø Would you rather have:» Greater total happiness, but at the expense of potentially sacrificing/instrumentalizing some people?» OR less total happiness, but absolutely no sacrifice of lives or instrumentalization for the greater good? 24