Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Similar documents
Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Logical (formal) fallacies

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Positions 1 and 2 are rarely useful in academic discourse Issues, evidence, underpinning assumptions, context etc. make arguments complex and nuanced

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

LOGIC. Inductive Reasoning. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

HSC EXAMINATION REPORT. Studies of Religion

Introducing Our New Faculty

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

Chapter 5: Ways of knowing Reason (p. 111)

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Section 4. Attainment Targets. About the attainment targets

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

OTTAWA ONLINE PHL Basic Issues in Philosophy

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

The Art of Critical Thinking

Our Guide to Better Grades

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

EXAMINERS REPORT AM PHILOSOPHY

14.6 Speaking Ethically and Avoiding Fallacies L E A R N I N G O B JE C T I V E S

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

IIE-2015 Workshop December 12 20, K P Mohanan. Types of Reasoning

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Logical Fallacies RHETORICAL APPEALS

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

Questions for Critically Reading an Argument

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Cambridge International Advanced Level 9013 Islamic Studies November 2014 Principal Examiner Report for Teachers

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

With prompting and support, identify the reasons an author gives to support points in a text.

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Persuasive Argument Relies heavily on appeals to emotion, to the subconscious, even to bias and prejudice. Characterized by figurative language,

the negative reason existential fallacy

Honours Programme in Philosophy

GCE Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Unit G571: Philosophy of Religion. Advanced Subsidiary GCE. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

Objections, Rebuttals and Refutations

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

AS RELIGIOUS STUDIES 7061/2A

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Basic Concepts and Skills!

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Inductive Reasoning.

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Higher National Unit Specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Philosophy C: An Introduction to Analytic Philosophy

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

A s a contracts professional, from

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

A Note on Straight-Thinking

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)

Cambridge International Advanced Level 9013 Islamic Studies November 2014 Principal Examiner Report for Teachers

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals

Purdue OWL Logic in Argumentative Writing

Chapter 2: Two Types of Reasoning

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Argument. What is it? How do I make a good one?

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Ethos, Logos, Pathos: Three Ways to Persuade

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

Introduction Symbolic Logic

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Transcription:

ACADEMIC SKILLS THINKING CRITICALLY In the everyday sense of the word, critical has negative connotations. But at University, Critical Thinking is a positive process of understanding different points of view to your own, and evaluating their strengths and weaknesses so you can respond appropriately. The ability to think critically is something you learn, and it helps if you can develop specific attitudes and skills. (See the Handout Critical thinking - Attitudes and Skills ). In learning to think critically, it is helpful to understand some principles of recognising and evaluating the arguments you read and listen to. You should also try to be aware of your own reasoning processes, and recognise the values and assumptions you hold when interpreting the arguments of others, and when formulating your own arguments. Argument Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion. A line of reasoning is the logical progression of these reasons towards the conclusion made, e.g.: Traditionally, Australian identity has been mythologised in images of the outback landscape and the figure of the bushman. However, the majority of the population has always lived on or near the coast, and enjoyed the beach as a pastime. These Australians have used the beach as an egalitarian public space which brings together a diverse range of mostly suburban people, and these aspects of beach culture have been represented in painting, film and literature since the 1930s. Therefore, twentieth century Australian cultural identity is more accurately described in terms of the suburban coast dweller, rather than the nineteenth century bushman. The structure of this argument might be understood as: Background statement (or target to pit the argument against): + Reason 1: Traditionally, Australian identity has been mythologised in images of the outback landscape and the figure of the bushman. However, the majority of the population has always lived on or near the 1

coast, and enjoyed the beach as a pastime. + Reason 2: These Australians have used the beach as an egalitarian public space which brings together a diverse range of mostly suburban people, + Reason 3: and these aspects of beach culture have been represented in painting, film and literature since the 1930s. = Conclusion: Therefore, twentieth century Australian cultural identity is more accurately described in terms of the suburban coast dweller, rather than the nineteenth century bushman. The three reasons together support the conclusion made. In order to evaluate the strength, or quality, of this argument you need to examine the truth of each reason given, and decide if all the pieces really do fit together logically. Underlying Values and Assumptions (a worldview ) Most arguments are presented within a paradigm, or world-view. A paradigm is the pattern, or framework through which you make sense of the world. A paradigm, or world-view, is based on certain values and assumptions. For example, a feminist world-view is based on the value that women should have equity with men, and this translates into a range of assumptions about the social, political and cultural rights of women. When acknowledging the arguments put forward by others, try to evaluate the evidence and argument by recognising the paradigm through which it is presented. More importantly, try to be aware of your own world-view and the paradigms through which you interpret the argument/evidence presented. In this way, you not only challenge the arguments of others, but also test the validity of your own. NB: A particular paradigm or world-view may be articulated in a theoretical framework, which is a body of formally developed theory (such as feminist theory). The previous argument about Australian cultural identity has been made by someone whose worldview may value the contemporary over the historical, or reality over myth. It may also be worldview shaped by where that person grew up. The validity of a worldview can be assessed by exploring the extent and the quality of evidence justifying such a view.

Reasoning Processes This section describes various reasoning processes and some common flaws in arguments. Soundness An argument is sound if: the reasons given are true or acceptable these reasons support the conclusion made A sound argument may also be referred to as a valid argument. A well-known example of valid reasoning is this: All men are mortal. (reason A) Socrates is a man. (reason B) Therefore, Socrates is mortal. (conclusion) What makes this argument valid is that, logically, reason A and reason B add up to ensure the validity of the conclusion. The use of logical thought here is bound up in language. Reason A suggests that mortal is a broad category that includes men. Reason B suggests that an even smaller element of the category of men is Socrates. If he belongs to the category of men, and men belong to the category of mortal, then the conclusion must be true. In other words, the structure is sound. An invalid argument is one in which the conclusion does not follow from the reasons, even though each reason may be true in itself, e.g.: All men are mortal. (reason A) Socrates is mortal. (reason B) Therefore, Socrates is a man. (conclusion) In this case, each reason and the conclusion are true statements in themselves, but structurally this argument is unsound. Reason A and reason B are not connected. Each reason suggests that men and Socrates are mortal, but they could be different types of mortal. There is no connection established between men and Socrates. Although each reason is a true statement in itself, they do not work together to guarantee the truth of the conclusion. This conclusion may also be true, but its truth in this argument is not a logical result of the reasons adding up. Therefore, the argument is structurally unsound. Sometimes we can be persuaded by an argument that appears to have a sound structure, e.g: All men are tall. (reason A - untrue) Socrates is a man. (reason B - true) Therefore, Socrates is tall. (invalid conclusion) Structurally, this argument adds up, like the first example above. Logically, the reasons ensure the conclusion, as above. It suggests that all men belong to the category of tall, and Socrates belongs to the category of all men, so he must also belong to that broader category of tall. The problem, however, is that the content of reason A is untrue; all men are not tall, so, reason A cannot contribute to the truth of conclusion. If Socrates was, in fact, a tall man, that would be a coincidental truth; it would not be a truth derived from the argument. So, despite the possible truth of

this conclusion, the argument is structurally invalid. This demonstrates how important it is to verify the truth of each part of an argument. Some arguments are unsound because, although each statement is true in itself, there is no connection at all between them, or between them and the conclusion, e.g.: All men are mortal. (reason A - true) Socrates is a Greek man. (reason B - true) Therefore, Socrates is a philosopher. (conclusion - true) This argument is structurally unsound because the reasons are not connected to each other and do not lead to the conclusion. In all of these examples, it has been assumed that you know the meanings of all the content referred to: man, mortal, tall, Greek, Socrates, philosopher. If you were not familiar with all these concepts, you might be tempted to accept all the arguments as valid. A critical thinker, however, will examine the content of each argument. (And the more you read and learn, the more you will know about the content in your field.) The writer often provides examples and evidence to explain or justify the content they use, and this can help you, as a critical reader, to judge the validity of the content, and, thus, the argument as a whole. Deductive and inductive reasoning These reasoning processes are concerned with the method of thinking, and should not be confused with the way you present thinking in various forms of writing for different disciplines. The basic distinction is that deductive reasoning, or deduction, begins with a general statement, or hypothesis, ( All men are mortal ) and examines more specific possibilities of that generalisation ( Socrates is a man ) to reach a specific conclusion (Therefore Socrates is mortal). The purpose of deductive arguments is to confirm the certainty of a proposition, or hypothesis. Inductive reasoning, on the other hand, considers specific observations to arrive at broad generalizations. The researcher explores and measures specific situations in order to detect patterns or trends, and thereby develops a general conclusion or theory. This conclusion or theory is not necessarily certain; it remains open to the possibility of challenge. You may recognise this as the generally accepted process of academic argument. Both deductive and inductive reasoning are used across various disciplines. For further information try websites such as: http://www.livescience.com/21569-deduction-vs-induction.html http://sociology.about.com/od/research/a/deductive-reasoning-versus-inductive-reasoning.htm In an inductive argument, the evidence builds a case for the conclusion, e.g.: Research shows that not all smokers get lung cancer, and, that some non-smokers also get lung cancer. Therefore, smoking may not be the cause of lung cancer. Inductive arguments may be evaluated as being either strong or weak. The argument above is weak; the evidence is vague, and the conclusion, while logical, is a broad generalisation.

A stronger version of this inductive argument would be: 60% of all smokers in Australia get lung cancer. 10% of all people in Australia who get lung cancer are non-smokers. Therefore we can conclude that: A. smoking causes lung cancer for a high proportion of smokers. B. most, but not all, lung cancer victims are smokers. This argument presents specific evidence and draws more cautious conclusions, which makes it a stronger argument, and more difficult to challenge. Fact and opinion A fact is something that is accepted as objective knowledge. Its truth can be objectively verified, e.g. James Cook sailed up the east coast of Australia in 1770. We know this for a fact from diaries, governmental records and other public documents of the time. The objective truth of some facts can be potentially, rather than actually, known, e.g. Anthropologists currently believe that the first Aboriginal people arrived in Australia 60,000 years ago. This potentially objective fact is based on estimates from excavations and carbon dating. An opinion is subjective knowledge. Its validity is based on value judgements, e.g.: Government funding for Indigenous health is inadequate. It is not wrong to be subjective; academic arguments vary and can be challenged precisely because they evolve from different subjective worldviews. The worth of a subjective argument is determined by the strength of the evidence provided to support it. This kind of judgement creates intelligent debate, and is the process by which we develop knowledge. When evaluating or challenging arguments, be clear of the distinction between an objective fact, and a subjective opinion (argument). NB: by opinion here, we mean view or argument. An academic opinion is informed by rational research and evidence. Personal opinions expressed in everyday conversation may well be intelligent, but cannot be used in academic work unless substantiated by research and evidence.

Flaws in Reasoning Jumping to conclusions: being too quick to draw a conclusion without really examining what is shown in the evidence. This can happen if you allow your emotions, gut response or uninformed opinions about the issue shape pre-conceived ideas. Read an argument with an open mind. Bias: a biased argument is one-sided. It seems to point, either negatively or positively, all one way. In other words, it omits or ignores relevant evidence which doesn t suit the author s purpose. A good academic argument respects points of view that might be different, or opposing, and includes them in the discussion by answering the challenge they pose. A biased argument shies away from doing this. Fallacy: a misleading or false idea, and leads to flawed arguments. Ad hominem: evaluating an argument on the basis of who is saying it, not on the basis of what is said. Appeal to authority: accepting that a person with expert knowledge in one field must therefore have expert knowledge of all other fields. Argument from ignorance: believing a proposition to be true simply because it can t be proved false. Begging the question: an argument in which the conclusion is merely a restatement of the premise. False cause: assuming that one thing caused another because they happened in sequence, or that simultaneous events are connected. False dilemma: presenting two arguments, of which only one can possibly be true, and ignoring all other options. Generalisation: drawing a conclusion that is broader than the evidence can support. Irrelevance: the premise/reason/evidence in an argument may be related to the topic generally, but does not contribute to the conclusion. Further explanations and exercises for these concepts can be found in the following sources Butterworth, J. & Thwaites, G. (2005). Thinking skills. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cottrell, S. (2003). The study skills handbook. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan Ltd