Figure 1: Laika. Definite Descriptions Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University. Definite Descriptions: Pick out an entity in the world (Figure 1)

Similar documents
Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Class 8 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Russell: On Denoting

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Russell on Descriptions

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Chapter Two Russell's theory of Proper Names

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Analyticity and reference determiners

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Beyond Symbolic Logic

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Complex demonstratives as quantifiers: objections and replies

russell s theory of propositions

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Coordination Problems

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

CONTENT, THOUGHTS, AND DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS

Great Philosophers Bertrand Russell Evening lecture series, Department of Philosophy. Dr. Keith Begley 28/11/2017

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Russell on Plurality

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Frege and Russell on Names and Descriptions Naïve theories

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Brainstorming exercise

Some observations on identity, sameness and comparison

THE GREAT DETOUR. John Perry. June 22, 2016 Institut Jean Nicod Paris

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Philosophy 370: Problems in Analytic Philosophy

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Class #7 - Russell s Description Theory

FREGE S AND RUSSELL S SOLUTIONS TO THE PROBLEMS OF NON-EXISTENT SUBJECT TERMS, IDENTITY STATEMENTS AND OPAQUE CONTEXTS ELIZABETH KITIS

Foundations of Logic, Language, and Mathematics

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Knowledge, Language, and Nonexistent Entities

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Generalizing Soames Argument Against Rigidified Descriptivism

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Postmodal Metaphysics

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Frode Bjørdal ON BELIEFS. 1. Introduction

A presupposition is a precondition of a sentence such that the sentences cannot be

ON DENOTING BERTRAND RUSSELL ORIGINALLY PUBLISHED IN MIND 14.4 (1905): THIS COPY FROM PHILOSOPHY-INDEX.COM.

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

ABOUT ABOUTNESS * University of California, Santa Barbara. Abstract

ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI Scope of Semantic Innocence

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. declarative sentence, or the content of a representational mental state,

Logic & Metaphysics Allan Gibbard Contingent Identity Notes

Opacity and the attitudes

2 in which a; is a constituent, where x, the variable, is. 1 I have discussed this subject in Principles of Mathematics, chapter

Theories of propositions

PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

DISCUSSION - McGINN ON NON-EXISTENT OBJECTS AND REDUCING MODALITY

Opacity and the double life of singular propositions

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Hintikka on Demonstratives

S T A TE THE REFERENTIAL AND THE ATTRIBUTIVE : TWO DISTINCTIONS FOR THE PRICE OF ONE 1

10.3 Universal and Existential Quantifiers

Varieties of Apriority

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Reflexivity NATHAN SALMON*

The Referential and the Attributive : Two Distinctions for the Price of One İlhan İnan

Singular Thought Tim Crane and Jody Azzouni

Definite Descriptions: From Symbolic Logic to Metaphysics. The previous president of the United States is left handed.

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Definite Descriptions, Naming, and Problems for Identity. 1. Russel s Definite Descriptions: Here are three things we ve been assuming all along:

HORWICH S MINIMALIST CONCEPTION OF TRUTH: Some Logical Difficulties

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

An argument against descriptive Millianism

Transcription:

Figure 1: Laika Definite Descriptions Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University 1 Russell, Strawson, Donnellan Definite Descriptions: Pick out an entity in the world (Figure 1) (1) a. the first dog in space: Laika b. the tallest student in the class: Big Bird c. the 42nd president of the United States: Bill Clinton d. the director of Eraserhead : David Lynch e. the present governor of California: Arnold Schwarzenegger Rusell (1905) On Denoting. The King of France (2) The present King of France is bald. 1

Russell (and Frege s) Question: What kind of a claim is this? Claim about an individual? [Like John is bald.] Quantificational Claim? [Like Every man is bald.] The Problem of Negation: (3) a. The present King of France isn t bald. b. John isn t bald. c. These appear to be semantically parallel, a claim of hairpresence for an individual. d. But then what does (a) mean (given that there is no present king of France)? Quantified NPs don t suffer from the problem of negation (4) a. Not every king is bald. b. (a) does not appear to be a claim about individuals. And therefore it is clear what (a) means: The set of kings is not a subset of the set of bald people. Russell s analysis: Sometimes quantification allows denoting By a denoting phrase I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the presenting King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish three cases: (1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., the present King of France. (2) A phrase may denote one definite object; e.g., the present King of England denotes a certain man. (3) A phrase may denote ambiguously; e.g. a man denotes not many men, but an ambiguous man. The interpretation of such phrases is a matter of considerably difficulty; indeed, it is very hard to frame any theory not susceptible of formal refutation. All the difficulties with which I am acquainted are met, so far as I can discover, by the theory which I am about to explain. Bertrand Russell On Denoting (Beginning) 2

The King of France is bald. x[kof(x) y[kof(y) x = y] bald(x)] x[ KoF(x) y[kof(y) x = y] bald(x) ] Existence Uniqueness Asserted Property Existence: An entity x having the property of being a present King of France exists. Uniqueness: Any entity y having the property of being a present King of France is x (x is the ONLY present king of france, pretenders beware!) Asserted Property x is bald. Russell s analysis naturally deals with the problem of negation Internal Negation The present King of France isn t bald. x[ KoF(x) y[kof(y) x = y] bald(x) ] Existence Uniqueness Negated Property So now we know what it means. It just happens that the claim it makes is false, because there is no present king of France (the first conjunct is false and therefore the entire conjunction is). Russell actually claims (3a) also has the following reading: External Negation The present King of France isn t bald. x[ KoF(x) y[kof(y) x = y] bald(x) ] Existence Uniqueness Asserted Property Note that this reading is true! Does (3a) have an external negation reading? (5) a. No, brothers and sisters, the present king of France is NOT bald. In fact, brothers and sisters, there is no present king of france. b. # There is a present king of France, brothers and sisters. In fact, brothers and sisters, the present king of France does not exist. Context and definiteness I 3

(6) The dog got locked out last night. x[dog(x) y[dog(y) x = y] locked-out(x)] Entails there is just one dog in the world A contextually determined unspoken property P (the P dog; i.e., ours) x[dog(x) P(x) y[ [dog(y) P(x)] x = y] locked-out(x)] Entails there is just one dog that is also P (ours) in the world The text calls such a definite description, where part of the description is unexpressed but implicit in context, an incomplete description Is Russell right? Is the internal negation reading of (3a) false? Strawson, in particular, disagrees (P.F. Strawson. (1950). On Referring ): Referring to an entity is not the same as making an assertion of its existence [the contrast between (5a) and (5b)] Statements are utterances of sentences on an occasion of use. Statements are true or false, not sentences. When a referring expression in an utterance fails to refer, then the utterance fails to make a statement. Thus, the utterance is NEITHER true NOR false. Rather it fails to make a statement because a presupposition of making a statement has failed. Donnellan (1966) Reference and Definite Descriptions They re both right (Russell and Strawson). Context matters. (7) a. Smith s murderer is insane. b. Referential Use: Reporter sees defendant outside courtroom talking to himself. Meaning: The man I see talking to himself (whom I believe to be Smith s murderer) is insane. Donnellan s claim: We don t say the reporter s claim is false if the defendant turns out to be innocent (but insane). c. Attributive Use: Investigator looking at horribly mutilated body of Smith. Meaning: Whoever murdered Smith must be insane. Donnellan s claim: The investigator s claim actually is false if it turns out that Smith s death is due to an unlikely accident. 4

References: For referential uses Strawson s analysis is closer to right, but failure to refer is at least a lot rarer than Strawson thinks. For attributive uses Russell s analysis is closer to right. Russell, Bertrand, On Denoting, in Mind 14 (1905): 479-493. Strawson, P. F., On Referring, in Mind 59 (1950): 320-344. Donnellan, Keith, Reference and Definite Descriptions, in Philosophical Review 75 (1966): 281-304. 2 The as a Generalized Quantifier Our analysis: The is a generalized quantifier. This is like Russell s analysis. But consider plurals, which Russell didn t (he had enough on his plate) (8) a. Bob bought some sheep and cows at the sale. b. Sally vaccinated the sheep c. Entailment: Sally vaccinated ALL the sheep bought at the sale. Sally vaccinated the sheep. (9) {x sheep(x)} {y vaccinate(sally, y)} {x sheep(x)} 2 (10) a. Bob bought a sheep and a cow at the sale. b. Sally vaccinated the sheep c. Entailment: Sally vaccinated the unique sheep bought at the sale. Sally vaccinated the sheep. (11) {x sheep(x)} {y vaccinate(sally, y)} {x sheep(x)} 1 Note: For singular definites our analysis has the same truth conditions as Russell s analysis. So for singular indefinites, it IS Russell s analysis, despite the changed notation. 5

3 Context and Definiteness II; Familiarity, A Generalized version of anaphora (12) a. An old man i came down the road leading a donkey j. It j carried a large brown sack k on its j back and every now and then he i adjusted it k more securely. b. An old man i came down the road leading a donkey j. The donkey j carried a large brown sack k on its j back and every now and then the old man i adjusted the sack k more securely. Is this a problem for our neo-russellian analysis? Not directly. We treat these all just be treated as incomplete descriptions Restored complete descriptions (13) An old man i came down the road leading a donkey j. The donkey [the old man was leading] j carried a large brown sack k on its j back and every now and then the old man [leading the donkey] i adjusted the sack [the donkey was carrying on its back] k more securely. But does this work completely? Note our restored definite descriptions still have incomplete descriptions inside them (in angle brackets) (14) An old man i came down the road leading a donkey j. The donkey [ the old man was leading] j carried a large brown sack k on its j back and every now and then the old man [leading the donkey ] i adjusted the sack [ the donkey was carrying on its back] k more securely. Point: In practice it s quite tricky to define precisely what the complete description is in context. Another pronoun-like property: Bound Definites Bound Pronouns: (15) a. Every man x thinks he x s a genius. b. x[man(x) think(x, genius(x))] Bound Definites: 6

(16) Every little leaguer x s father thinks the boy x s a genius. 4 Scope and Opaque Contexts Leibniz s Law (from Lecture I : Substitutivity of Identicals)[ the (c) sentences follow from the (a) and (b) sentences]) (17) a. Mohammed Ali = Cassius Clay b. Mohammed Ali was a boxer. c. Cassius Clay was a boxer (18) a. the director of Eraserhead = the director of Blue Velvet b. The director of Eraserhead is tall. c. The director of Blue Velvet is tall. Failures of Leibniz s Law in Modal Contexts [the (c) sentences do not follow from the (a) and (b) sentences] (19) a. Yuri Gagarin = the first man in space b. Yuri Gegarin might not have been the first man in space. [Alan Shephard might have beaten him up there.] c. Yuri Gegarin might not have been Yuri Gegarin. [?] (20) a. the number of the planets = nine b. Necessarily nine is nine. c. Necessarily the number of the planets is nine. Contexts in which Leibniz s Law can fail are called Opaque Contexts Failures of Leibniz s Law with propositional attitudes Quine s case (Quine 1976) and Russell s case (Russell 1905) There is a certain man in a brown hat whom Rallp has glimpsed several times under questionable circumstances on which we need not enter here; suffice it to say that Ralph suspects he is a spy. Also, there is a gray-haired man, vaguely known to Ralph as a pillar of the community, whom Ralph is not aware of having seen except once at the beach [but whose 7

name Ralph knows to Bernard J. Ortcutt]. Now Ralph does not know it, but the men are one and the same. (21) a. Bernard J. Ortcutt = the man sen at the beach = the man in the brown hat b. Ralph believes that Ortcutt is a spy. [false] c. Ralph believes that the man in the brown hat is a spy.[true] d. Ralph believes that the man seen at the beach is a spy.[false] Russell s example: (22) a. the author of Waverley is Sir Walter Scott. b. King George IV wondered whether the author of Waverley was Sir Walter Scott. c. King George IV wondered whether Sir Walter Scott was Sir Walter Scott. (23) Oedipus wanted to marry his mother. [true or false given Sophocles s plot?] These examples are all arguments for a quantificational analysis of definite descriptions Gegarin: Natural reading Yuri Gegarin might not have been the first man in space The x [first man in space(x)] g = x Another, silly reading Yuri Gegarin might not have been the first man in space The x [first man in space(x)] g = x de dicto reading with a propositional attitude: Description falls under the scope of the attitude predicate. (24) a. Ralph believes the man in the brown hat is a spy. b. believe(r, The x [man in brown hat(x)]spy(x)) c. Ralph believes the man on the beach is a spy. d. believe(r, The x [man on beach(x)]spy(x)) 8

(25) a. Oedipus wanted to marry his mother. [de dicto reading is false in play; Oedipus wants to marry Jocasta, who is his mother, but he doesn t know it!] b. want(o, The x [mother-of(x, o)] marry(o, x)) de re reading: description takes wide scope with respect to the attitude predicate (26) a. Oedipus wanted to marry his mother. [true in play] b. The x [mother-of(x, o)] want(o, marry(o, x)) But since similar examples occur with proper names, these examples are also arguments for a quantificational analysis of proper names Ancient names for the evening star and the morning star (=Venus): Hesperus and Phosporus respectively. (Frege s examples) (27) a. Hesperus = Phosphorus b. The ancients knew that Hesperus was Hesperus. [True] c. The ancients knew that Hesperus was Phosphorus. [False] References Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 53. Reprinted in Quine, W.V. O. (1956). The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays Cambridge, MA. Harvard University Press. 185-96. Frege, G. (1970). On Sense and Reference In P. Geach and M. Black, editors, Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. pp 56-78. Blackwell, Oxford, 1970. Originally published in 1892. 9