Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Similar documents
Human rights theory as solidarity

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Kant and his Successors

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Richard Rorty (1931 )

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Rorty and human rights Contingency, emotions and how to defend human rights telling stories

The British Empiricism

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Kant s Copernican Revolution

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

A Japanese Ethics of Double Negation: Watsuji Tetsurô s Contribution to the Liberal- Communitarian Debate

Metaphysical Pluralism: James and the Neo-Pragmatists

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Modern Philosophy II

Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism. Introduction

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

PHILOSOPHY OF LIFELONG EDUCATION Kenneth Wain London: Croom Helm.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Plato s Concept of Soul

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

The Explanation of Free Will in Kant and Mulla Sadra s Metaphysics

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Assertion and Inference

After Sen what about objectivity in economics?

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Contingency, Meliorism and Fate. Henrik Rydenfelt University of Helsinki

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

Carlin ROMANO, America the Philosophical

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

The Grounding for Moral Obligation

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Philosophy Courses-1

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Practical Wisdom and Politics

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Philosophy Courses-1

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

COURSE SYLLABUS. Course Description

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Cameron Boult. Employment. Education. Research Areas. Publications. Book Reviews

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

THEISM, EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY, AND TWO THEORIES OF TRUTH

J.M. COETZEE AND ANIMAL RIGHTS: ELIZABETH COSTELLO S CHALLENGE TO PHILOSOPHY

Bioethics and Epistemology: A Response to Professor Arras t

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Solidarity or Objectivity: Rorty s Neo-Pragmatic View of Science and Its Ethical Implication

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Transcription:

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya Abstract This article considers how the human rights theory established by US pragmatist Richard Rorty, which denies the transcendental grounding of human rights, gave birth to different interpretations of human rights theory and practice. Anti-foundationalism is one of the main tenets of Rorty s critique on epistemic and metaphysical foundations of human rights. In the concern for human rights, epistemic foundationalism runs through the conception of truth as representation, and human rights also derives from an unhistorical vision of truth. By the denial of epistemic foundationalism, Rorty asserts that no knowledge is born out of the historical circumstances in which the world occurs, and that in the field of human rights there is no natural law and rights are always historical and cultural. Rorty s metaphysical anti-foundationalism is a strong critique of the principle of the inherent and unalienable character of human rights. Rorty maintains that it is not possible to speak about a human condition because, as there are no phenomena outside the domain of history, there are only historical and cultural configurations. Introduction Human rights discourse is perhaps one of the most important discourses of our times. The contemporary discourse on human rights is both passionate and puzzling when considered from a philosophical point of view. Richard Rorty s neo-pragmatism constitutes one of the most powerful reappraisals of metaphysics, the political and philosophical legacy of modernity and the rational understanding of human rights. Rorty s notion of human rights is grounded on the notion of sentimentality. He contended that throughout history humans have devised various means of construing certain groups of individuals as inhuman or subhuman. Thinking in rationalist or foundationalist terms will not solve this problem, he claimed. Rorty advocated the creation of a culture of global human rights in order to stop violations from happening through a sentimental education. Sentimental education works only on people who can relax long enough to listen. Rorty s re-contextualization of rights offers a possibility for a radical transformation of the theory and practice of human rights. Rorty defends the epistemological and metaphysical presupposition of the contingency of human rights, understands rights and morality in terms of human suffering, and elaborates the idea of 1

advancing human sensibility to consolidate the rights culture. Rorty focuses on a specific, cultural fact, the fact of what he calls Human Rights Culture. The emergence of human rights culture seems to owe nothing to increased moral knowledge, and everything to hearing sad and sentimental stories. He schematizes the concept of a global moral sentiment and finds in sympathy and solidarity the appropriate feelings and values for a human rights culture. He argued that we should create a sense of empathy or teach empathy to others so as to understand others suffering. Human rights as natural rights Human rights are natural in the sense that they exist independently of human agreements, conventions, treaties and the like. Many of those who believe in natural rights would say that natural rights fit into a larger realm, one that includes not only natural rights but also the rights that accrue to the parties to agreement and the like which course do not exist independently of those agreements. It also includes natural duties or obligations as well as those duties or obligations accrued by the parties to agreements and so on. Human rights adhere to the human being by virtue of being human, and for no other reason. This suggests that there is something special about being human. It is more than simply being the member of one species rather than another. Rather, it is being the member of a species that by virtue of its nature has rights, indeed a particular specific set of rights. Rorty thinks that the only way to expand people s perception of humanity and human rights to include all human beings is to improve the quality of life for everyone in order that they will be a mindset that will permit them to look past superficial differences and see the common bond that all humans share. Rorty s approach Before entering into Rorty s approach to human rights, it is necessary to look briefly at his intellectual trajectory and background. As an exponent of US pragmatism, Rorty s thought was developed amidst the reaction to the hegemony of analytical philosophy in the Anglo-North American philosophical debate. In other words, Rorty established a fruitful dialogue between Anglo-American and Continental philosophy and opened the door to a realm where both traditions converge. At the same time, paradoxically Rorty was heir to the political project of modernity. In this regard he made a distinction between the philosophical and the political legacy of the enlightenment and, while dropping the 2

first, he embraced the second including human rights. Rorty mainly developed his view on human rights in the essay Human Rights Rationality and Sentimentality. This text has been a precursor in establishing a link between human rights and sensibility, between the tradition of the ethics of emotions in Western philosophy and the theory of human rights, and between sentimental education and long-term human rights activism. Human history is full of stories in every civilization in every part of the world; violations of human rights are in every imaginable way. What is it that brings some human beings to violate and justify the violation of the rights of other human beings? What is it that brings some human beings to denounce atrocities and to honor the rights of others who are different? Richard Rorty in his essay, Human Rights, Rationality and Sentimentality, claims that what makes people respect or deny human rights is their life circumstances. Rorty believes that violators of human rights, specifically those violators who are not sociopaths, are deprived of life s necessities in both security and sympathy. These, Rorty s claims are what are needed in order for people to be able to look past the differences that allow one person to dehumanize another or one group to dehumanize another. Through sympathy we achieve awareness of the experience of another as if were happening inside our own realm of existence; it necessarily brings others, who are different from us, into our definition of humanity. Rorty s reflection begins with the idea that developing theories about the transcendental foundations of rights is outdated. Thus, while there are those who are involved in the exploration of the philosophical grounding of human rights as a way of strengthening them against skeptics and critics, Rorty is their counterpart. He assumes himself to be a participant in the effort to achieving the political project of modernity, including the task of furthering contemporary human rights culture as a way of avoiding or alleviating the suffering of victims of the abuse of power. Rorty s distrust of a priori groundings or unhistorical justifications of rights, or what he calls foundationalism, leads to a different interpretation of human rights theory and practice. Anti-foundationalism is one of the crucial tenets of Rorty s critique of metaphysics as it encompasses a transformation of the image of philosophy and of the concept of truth. Rorty distinguishes between two different types of foundationalism, which are usually found together in modern theory. In the Platonic tradition, philosophy has configured itself not only as epistemology, as a transcendental theory of knowledge but also as grounding, as a reflection about things in relation to their metaphysical foundations. Thus it is possible to speak about epistemic foundations or foundations of knowledge on the one hand, and of metaphysical foundations on the other. The first pursued in the theory of knowledge, which look for the transcendental conditions of the possibility of truth. The later belongs to the ambit of ontology. 3

Epistemic and metaphysical anti-foundationalism and human rights For Rorty the theory of natural law is foundationalist and rights are deduced from a human nature. Such a notion is based on a conception of truth as representation, a metaphor that has dominated western philosophy since the times of Plato. With this theory of knowledge, truth is the result of an effort aimed at obtaining an accurate description of what stands in front of the subject, and consciousness and mind become mirrors of nature. The notion of human rights also derives from a universalistic and unhistorical vision of truth. Rorty asserts the historical, contingent, and perspective character of knowledge. There cannot be knowledge that is not born out of the historical circumstances in which the world occurs. Rorty maintains that he is not elaborating a theory about the nature of truth, but a theory about the culture of truth. In the field of human rights, this point of view translates into the idea according to which there is no natural law and rights are always historical and cultural. Rorty points out foundationalism as a way of thinking that has been present throughout the history of Western philosophy. In the concern for human rights, metaphysical foundationalism runs through the principle of the inherent and inalienable character of human rights. Rorty s metaphysical anti-foundationalism is the critique of the way of thinking that proceeds by looking for grounds. Rorty thinks that a well functioning human rights culture results from two conditions, security and sympathy. By security I mean conditions of life sufficiently risk-free as to make one s difference from others inessential to one s self respect, one s sense of worth By sympathy I mean the sort of reactions. It is not possible to speak about a human condition because, as there are no phenomena outside the domain of history, there are only historical and cultural configurations. The human condition is cultural because the human is the result of historical dynamics in which human beings and societies act on themselves. To the philosophical grounding of human rights Rorty also opposes the ethics of pragmatism and a particular conception of cultural practice. As a consequence, dealing with human rights cannot be a question of looking for transcendental grounds but of directly engaging with suffering of facing the situation of those in pain. Conclusion Human rights are often thought to be natural in the sense that human beings possess them independently of any human agreements or social conventions and humanity itself is supposed to ground such rights. Rorty believes that this assumption cannot be justified. In his view there are no morally relevant trans-cultural facts. Thus the trans-cultural fact of one s humanity cannot ground human rights. Rorty focuses on a specific, cultural fact he 4

calls human rights culture. Rorty is keen to rescue emotions for the theory of culture, and to take them from the place of the banned troublemaker that disturbs the pursuing of truth and morality to fulfill the role of moral progress. As the ethos and the culture in which human rights can advance as a sphere of sensibility, the moral subject does not need to be a cold and rational individual, but a warm and sympathetic human being. In this scenario sympathy becomes a key moral virtue and a central feature of a culture of rights. Rorty does not oppose human rights, neither their cultural nor historical justification, but only the transcendental grounding of human rights. Through the establishment of antifoundationalism Rorty labeled foundationalism as outdated and our task should be making our culture the human rights culture more self-conscious, more powerful rather than of demonstrating its superiority to other cultures by an appeal to something transcultural. BIBLIOGRAPHY Brandom Robert. ed; Rorty and His Critics. Oxford and Cambridge, Mass: Blackwell, 2000. Geras, Norman. Solidarity in the Conversation of Humanity. London: Verso, 1995. Hall, David L. Richard Rorty: Prophet and Poet of the New Pragmatism. Albany: State University New York Press, 1994. Malachowsky, Alan R. ed; Reading Rorty. Oxford and Cambridge, Mass: Blackwell, 1991. Peters, Michael and Ghiraldelli, Paulo.eds; Richard Rorty: Education, Philosophy, Politics. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc; 2002. Rorty, Richard. 1998.Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Vol.3, Camebridge: Camebridge University Press,1998. Saatkamp, Herman J. ed; Rorty and Pragmatism. Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press, 1995. Dr. P.S. Sreevidya 2018 Email: neelambarineela@gmail.com 5