Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Similar documents
1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

Definitions of Gods of Descartes and Locke

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel)

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Cartesian Rationalism

Cartesian Rationalism

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 88, No. 2. (Apr., 1979), pp

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Baruch Spinoza. Demonstrated in Geometric Order AND. III. Of the Origin and Nature of the Affects. IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Power of the Affects.

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

Spinoza on God, Affects, and the Nature of Sorrow

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

On The Existence of God

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

5 A Modal Version of the

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Introduction to Philosophy

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Spinoza as a Philosopher of Education. Cetin Balanuye, Akdeniz University, Turkey

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Summer Preparation Work

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Kant and his Successors

The Solution to Skepticism by René Descartes (1641) from Meditations translated by John Cottingham (1984)

The Principle of Sufficient Reason in Spinoza

Descartes Meditations

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3


The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Aristotle and Aquinas

Dualism: What s at stake?

Kant s Theory of the Sublime in Nature and His Concept of Nature

15 Does God have a Nature?

Of the Nature of the Human Mind

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Descartes and Foundationalism

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Clear and Distinct Perception in Descartes's Philosophy. Shoshana Rose Smith. B.A. University of California Los Angeles, 1995

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

1/9. The First Analogy

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Rene Descartes August 1, 2005 The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy b. Religion, Science and Scepticism

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

1/8. Leibniz on Force

The Kalam Cosmological Argument

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs.

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

An Examination of the Traits of Philosophical Discourse by John Locke 1

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Transcription:

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza Ryan Steed PHIL 2112 Professor Rebecca Car October 15, 2018

Steed 2 While both Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes espouse geometric truth and fastidious deduction to establish truth, I argue that Spinoza s proof of God and substance is closer to the rational ideal on the grounds that he is more consistent in his definition and application of causal relations between things. To do so, I frame each philosophers set of axioms as a variant of the Principal of Sufficient Reason (PSR), a foundational principle of relations. First, I will briefly review the PSR and its variable components. Next, I will examine Descartes treatment of causality in light of the PSR, finding that his definition of sufficient reason fluctuates in the course of his argument and that he stops short of the full consequences of his postulates. With Descartes inconsistencies as a guide, I will then examine Spinoza s reflexive axioms with respect to the PSR and conclude that his resolution of infinite regress is more thorough and rational, notwithstanding the restrictions it places on his conception of God. The epistemological and ontological differences examined here may be conveniently categorized as one of two kinds of variations on the basic PSR. The Principal of Sufficient Reason states quite simply that for any given tautology p, there must be a sufficient reason why p is true. Stated in discrete terms, where the relation R is defined such that y R x indicates that y is the sufficient reason for x: Principal of Sufficient Reason: ( x)( y)(y R x) I argue that both authors attempt to establish the intelligibility of all or many things by relating them through the PSR; all that remains to be examined is the criterion of the sufficient reason relation R and the set of elements to which it applies. In his trademark proof of God, Descartes adheres closely to the PSR with respect to the reality of things: 1 1 Meditations, 49.

Steed 3 Now it is indeed evident by the light of nature that there must be at least as much [reality] in the efficient and total cause as there is in the effect of that same cause. For whence, I ask, could an effect get its reality, if not from its cause? Hence it follows that something cannot come into being out of nothing All effects that is, all things must have sufficient, or adequate, cause. Mathematically, y R x if y has as much reality as x. This relation not only holds between formal things, but also between ideas: this is manifestly true not merely for those effects whose reality is actual or formal, but also for ideas in which only objective reality is considered. 2 Descartes equates the formal reality of a cause to the objective reality of an idea in the same proportion. He dubs this amount of reality (formal or objective) the relative perfection of a thing. 3 I discern two major discrepancies with this version of the PSR. The first lies in Descartes manipulation of the definition of perfection, and thereby the very definition of the causal relationship R. Descartes clarifies his ambiguous reference to the degrees of reality in third objections: 4 if there is an infinite and independent substance, it is a thing to a greater degree than is a finite and dependent substance. Descartes supposes that perfection has a maximum, an infinite and independent substance. This point is crucial to his trademark argument for God. 5 Yet while dispelling the notion of an evil genius and removing all doubt in the intelligibility of external bodies in Meditation Four, Descartes abandons the question of finitude entirely. The term perfection comes to refer to qualities that are not defects; perfection connotes an ethical 2 Ibid. 3 Ibid. 4 Objections and Replies, 81. 5 In short, that if all ideas must have sufficient cause with as much formal reality as the idea has objective reality, and I have the idea of a most perfect being, then there must exist formally a most perfect being. The only thing with a sufficient degree of reality is an infinite and independent substance which formally exists.

Steed 4 scale, rather than the ontological one Descartes describes in Meditation Three. This passage ostensibly associates the term perfection with moral goodness or strength: To begin with, I acknowledge that it is impossible for God ever to deceive me, for trickery or deception are always indicative of some imperfection the will to deceive undoubtedly attest to maliciousness or weakness. Accordingly, deception is incompatible with God. 6 Descartes may claim that this sort of ethical perfection is a separate attribute of God, but the trademark proof in Meditation Three necessitates no such attribute. The original PSR requires only sufficient reason that is, a sufficient degree of reality. It follows that Descartes proof of external bodies, which relies on the benevolence of God insofar as he does not manipulate judgment or mathematical truth, relies on a definition of God that is unnecessary to his existence. Descartes therefore cannot claim on these grounds that the existence of God implies the existence of all bodies. The second discrepancy also regards Descartes reliance on God to ensure mathematical truths. It is clear from Descartes language in Meditation Four that God is a being with a free and independent will which is incomparably greater in God than it is in [Descartes himself]. 7 For instance, God always wills what is best and does not wish to deceive. 8 But even if God s will is the cause of all intelligible things, including mathematical truths and the faculty to judge, the unrestricted PSR requires that God s will must also have a sufficient cause. In Descartes own words, something cannot come into being out of nothing. 9 By assuming the freedom and 6 Meditations, 54. 7 Meditations, 56. 8 Meditations, 64. 9 Meditations, 49.

Steed 5 agency of God s will, Descartes violates the PSR used to prove his existence. Instead, divine will must be taken as an inexplicable truth, as Descartes himself admits: It is not without rashness that I think myself capable of inquiring into the ends of God. 10 Thus Descartes allows an arbitrary, brute truth into his epistemology. Spinoza, on the other hand, successfully avoids contingent truths and maintains a much more consistent definition of the sufficient reason relation. I will describe Spinoza s improvements on the PSR in terms of three variations: first, the basic definition of the relation R and its improved consistency and applicability; second, the reflexivity of R; third, an infinite regress which separates the relation R between finite things and with regards to God. Spinoza s PSR is clearly stated in 1a3 and clarified in 1a4: The knowledge of an effect depends on, and involves, the knowledge of a cause. 11 Thus the relation R is some epistemological dependence which Spinoza also expresses as understanding through, conception through, and stipulates some sort of commonality between x and y. 12 While Descartes uses an inconsistent scale of perfection to determine sufficient reason, Spinoza deliberately avoids the ethical or aesthetic attributions Descartes embraces, saying, I do not attribute to Nature [God] beauty, ugliness, order, or confusion. 13 Additionally, Spinoza s broader definition of sufficient reason allows him the freedom to apply the PSR to the non-existence of things. Spinoza leverages this freedom to provide an alternate a priori proof of God: if there can be no reason or cause which prevents God from existing or which annuls his existence, we are bound to conclude that he necessarily exists. 14 10 Meditations, 55. 11 Ethics 1a4. 12 Ethics 1a5, 1a2, 1p3. 13 Letter to Henry Oldenburg (November 20, 1665), p. 142. 14 Ethics, 1p11, second proof.

Steed 6 To solve the problem of contingent truths, Spinoza s second variation establishes reflexive causation in his very first definition. 15 1a2 states it in terms of the PSR: That which cannot be conceived through another thing must be conceived through itself. 16 By allowing selfcausal relations for substances, Spinoza ensures that no cause is needed for God or God s will. Rather, God may be understood through himself. 1p17 clearly states that God acts solely from the laws of his own nature, constrained by none. 17 Further, Spinoza explicitly proves in 1p29 that nothing in nature is contingent, especially God. 18 Spinoza s proof for God s selfsufficiency relies on his earlier proofs describing God s infinite nature, which in turn relies on the definition of God. Not only does Spinoza deny that God is contingent on an arbitrary will, he readily denies absolute, or free, will or the faculty of willing and non-willing to the mind in general. 19 Thus Spinoza maintains the legitimacy of the PSR for all elements in his ontology, including the first efficient cause, and avoids contingent truth. The last fundamental difference I observe from Descartes causal relation is Spinoza s insistence on the immanence of God as first cause. Descartes prohibits the infinite regress of caused ideas, favoring a transitive approach to the first cause which relates any given thing to God in linear fashion: 20 Although one idea can perhaps issue from another, nevertheless no infinite regress is permitted here; eventually some first idea must be reached whose cause is a sort of archetype that contains formally all the reality that is in the idea merely objectively. 15 Ethics, 1d1. 16 Ethics, 1a2. 1717 Ethics, 1p17. 18 Ethics, 1p29. 19 Ethics, 1p48-49. 20 Meditations, 50.

Steed 7 Spinoza, on the other hand, repeatedly stresses the direct relation between God and all things: God is the immanent, not the transitive, cause of all things. 21 Moreover, every idea of any body or particular thing existing in actuality necessarily involves the eternal and infinite essence of God. 22 But because Spinoza ontologically distinguishes the existence of finite and determinate things from the infinite and eternal, it is simultaneously true that all finite things must have finite causes in the modes of God s infinite attributes. 23 As such, a finite thing simultaneously belongs to an infinite regress of finite causes with no hypothesis or contingent resolution and to a proximate causal relation with God. There exists an endless chain of finite causes and effects with no beginning or end, but because this chain is composed of finite things it is contingent on God for its existence. This quirk of Spinoza s ontology finds a resolution in his epistemological PSR only through the permission of the infinite regress of finite things. In summary, Spinoza manages to explain the infinite regress of finite causes with God, and grounds the infinite regress of infinite causes by allowing R to be reflexive with respect to substances. He avoids the complications of degrees of perfection with a clearly defined epistemological R, applies that relation to more reliably prove the existence of God a priori, and dances around ontological conflicts by permitting infinite regress of finite causes only. Descartes falls further short of the rational ideal, consigning God s will to the unintelligible and muddling the trademark proof with an ambiguous R. Thus Spinoza s variant of the PSR, the causal proof of God, and epistemology as a whole is a much better effort to arrive at an intelligible world by reason. 21 Ethics, 1p18. 22 Ethics, 2p45. 23 Ethics, 1p28

Steed 8 Bibliography Descartes, Meditations. Spinoza, From the Letters to Oldenburg and to Meyer. Spinoza, The Ethics.