Beyond Virtue Epistemology 1

Similar documents
Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology

Epistemic Virtues and their Limits

Replies 1. Ernest Sosa Rutgers University

Book Reviews 309 science, in the broadest sense of the word is a complex achievement, which depends on a number of different activities: devising theo

Character Virtues, Epistemic Agency, and Reflective Knowledge

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

What Should We Believe?

Skepticism and Internalism

Reliabilism and the Value Problem. Christoph Jäger, Innsbruck. Draft May forthcoming in Theoria (2010)

THE DEBATE ON EPISTEMIC AND ETHICAL NORMATIVITY

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Prof Paul O Grady 16 th January, What is Wisdom?

PL 399: Knowledge, Truth, and Skepticism Spring, 2011, Juniata College

Dr. Evan Butts. Academic Building 419 College Drive Barnesville, GA United States (Home) (Mobile)

On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE

Contemporary epistemologists often borrow from act

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

1 Sosa 1991, pg. 9 2 Ibid, pg Ibid, pg Ibid, pg. 179

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Virtue Epistemologies and Epistemic Vice

General Philosophy. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Michaelmas Overview 2. 2 Course Website 2. 3 Readings 2. 4 Study Questions 3

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Sosa on Epistemic Value

The Value of Knowledge. Olsson, Erik J. Published in: Philosophy Compass. Link to publication

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

SAFETY-BASED EPISTEMOLOGY: WHITHER NOW?

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

EPISTEMIC EVALUATION AND THE AIM OF BELIEF. Kate Nolfi. Chapel Hill 2010

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Four Varieties of Character-Based Virtue Epistemology

PHIL-210: Knowledge and Certainty

Virtue reliabilism is a theory of justification: it purports to give the

INFERENTIALIST RELIABILISM AND PROPER FUNCTIONALISM: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS AS DEFENSES OF EXTERNALISM AMY THERESA VIVIANO

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Life Science Journal 2014;11(9) Virtue Epistemology and Psychology of Education. Karimov, Artur Ravilevich

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION

Character, Reliability, and Virtue Epistemology

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Skill in Epistemology I: Skill and Knowledge

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Tiago Alfredo S. Ferreira, Charbel N. El- Hani & Waldomiro José da Silva-Filho

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

WARRANT AND EPISTEMIC VIRTUES: TOWARD AN AGENT-RELIABILIST ACCOUNT OF PLANTINGA S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE STEWART DOUGLAS CLEM

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Unifying the intellectual virtues (formerly known as Virtues, truth-conduciveness, and robustness ) Draft, March 2009

STEPHANIE LEARY CURRICULUM VITAE

Epistemic Value and the New Evil Demon. B.J.C. Madison. (Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly) Draft Version Do Not Cite Without Approval

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Veritas Revista de Filosofia da PUCRS

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

Anti-Luck Epistemologies and Necessary Truths

Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge (Rough Draft-notes incomplete not for quotation) Stewart Cohen

RECOVERING PLATO: A PLATONIC VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY

Knowledge, so it seems to many, involves

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Which Groups Have Scientific Knowledge? A Reply to Chris Dragos

Heather D. Battaly. 800 N. State College Blvd. Office phone: California State University Fullerton Fullerton, CA

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Competent Perspectives and the New Evil Demon Problem

Realism and anti-realism. University of London Philosophy B.A. Intercollegiate Lectures Logic and Metaphysics José Zalabardo Autumn 2009

Seminary Mission Statement. Course Description. Course Purpose. Core Values Addressed

Safety, Virtue, Scepticism: Remarks on Sosa

Introduction Naturalized virtue epistemology

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

Three Independent Factors in Epistemology. Guy Axtell and Phil Olson

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Some Iterations on The Subject s Perspective Objection to Externalism By Hunter Gentry

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Københavns Universitet. Naturalistic Epistemology Kappel, Klemens. Published in: Routledge Companion to Epistemology. Publication date: 2010

Reliabilism, Stability, and the Value of Knowledge. Erik J. Olsson

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Epistemic Circularity and Common Sense: A Reply to Reed

UNIT 3: Social Epistemology

Epistemology. PH654 Bethel Seminary Winter To be able to better understand and evaluate the sources, methods, and limits of human knowing,

Epistemic Value Dennis Whitcomb 6111 words. Draft For The Continuum Companion to Epistemology.

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

OTHER-REGARDING EPISTEMIC VIRTUES. Jason Kawall

A Two-Factor Theory of Perceptual Justification. Abstract: By examining the role perceptual experience plays in the justification of our

Achieving epistemic descent

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

REVISED PROOF. 3 Reliabilism and the extra value of knowledge. 4 Wayne A. Davis Christoph Jäger. 5 6 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

MSc / PGDip / PGCert Epistemology (online) (PHIL11131) Course Guide

REFLECTIVE KNOWLEDGE: CONFUCIUS AND VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY

THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION: AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL AND METHODOLOGICAL RESPONSE. Alan Robert Rhoda. BA, University of Nevada, Las Vegas, 1993

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Transcription:

Beyond Virtue Epistemology 1 Waldomiro Silva Filho UFBA, CNPq 1. The works of Ernest Sosa claims to provide original and thought-provoking contributions to contemporary epistemology in setting a new direction for old dilemmas about the nature and value of knowledge. Judgment and Agency () presents some new developments in his ideas. This book, described by Ram Neta () as both monumentally important and largely successful, brings together eleven essays, mostly based on articles previously published in journals and collected works. These texts address the principal themes of Sosa s philosophy, such as the nature and value of epistemic achievements, the different degrees of belief, the interaction between animal justification and reflective justification, the point of ancient and modern skepticism, and the moral, social and pragmatic aspects of knowledge. As we know, virtue epistemology (Sosa, 1991, 2007, 2009) provides a solution to the disputes that monopolized the epistemological debates of the 1960s and 1980s, between, on the one hand, foundational and coherentist theories about epistemic justification and, on the other hand, externalist and internalist conceptions about the nature of knowledge. These foundational and coherentist, externalist and internalist positions address aspects relevant to our cognitive 1 This text was written during my time as a Visiting Scholar at the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT), Mass., USA, under a Senior Fellowship Grant from CAPES (proc. BEX 2706/15-6). I would like to thank Felipe Rocha for his comments and suggestions on the first version of this text. ANALYTICA, Rio de Janeiro, vol 19 nº 1,, p. 123-128 123

Beyond Virtue Epistemology lives, however, their defenders are inclined to refute other positions, even when they contain intuitively relevant ideas: can we set aside the idea that we are natural beings and that the way in which we are embedded in the natural world plays a constitutive role in our mental lives? Can we also reject the idea that reflection and a broad understanding of our cognitive achievements play a central role in our lives? Sosa argues that knowledge requires true belief produced by something that is related to the, natural or learnt, skills and competence that allow someone to pursue and reach the truth. The idea of apt performance is crucial for both knowledge and action because it involves the idea of an achievement based on the deliberate endeavor of the person in the capacity of agent. In this sense, Sosa (2007, pp. 22-43) uses the example of an archer shooting an arrow at a target in order to illustrate the fact that one of the demands which may be required for knowledge is the fact that the cognitive agent must undertake a specific type of performance based on certain skills. Once this archer is truly competent, we expect that he will hit the target because of his skill and not because of some other factor: Performance whose success manifests the relevant competence of the performer avoids thereby a kind of luck. According to competence virtue epistemology, knowledge is a special case of that. Knowledge of a sort is belief whose correctness is attained sufficiently through the believer s epistemic competence, belief that is thus apt. (Sosa,, p. 9) The cognitive agent is someone who forms a true belief in virtue of their competence to form true beliefs. 124 2. Sosa makes a distinction between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge (Sosa, 2007; 2009): when a belief is correctly attributed to a competence exercised under the appropriate conditions, this counts as apt and as knowledge of a certain type, i.e. animal knowledge (Sosa, 2007a, p. 93). The adjective animal does not have negative connotations, but merely serves to emphasize the natural sense of the process of acquiring beliefs; its paradigm is perceptual knowledge. Animal knowledge requires apt belief without, however, requiring defensible apt belief, in other words an apt belief that the subject aptly believes is apt, and the subject can defend its aptness against skeptical doubts (Sosa, 2007, p. 24).

Waldomiro Silva Filho Reliabilism (Goldman, 2012) as a form of epistemic externalism declares that the fact that the cognitive agent does not know how he forms true beliefs and does not have any idea that the procedure is reliable does not prevent him from having knowledge, because knowledge does not require reasons. Virtue epistemology inclines towards externalism and reliabilism and accepts that an agent has animal knowledge only if his belief is apt, in other words: a) the belief is true, b) it is produced by intellectual virtue, c) the subject obtains the truth from his intellectual virtues. On the other hand, virtue epistemology also accepts the relevance of something as an intentional awareness, an epistemic perspective: the agent who is conscious of the ways and means in which he forms beliefs (in other words, he is careful to avoid mistakes and takes account of the available evidence) will be more virtuous and, as such, more reliable than someone who does not have this attitude. We can therefore admit that the epistemically virtuous person exercises both externalist excellence (is involved in reliable processes proved by nature, by their perceptual virtues, by society) and internalist excellence (an agent is virtuous if he has good motives for supporting what he believes). For Sosa, reflective knowledge requires not only apt belief but apt belief that is defensible as apt (Sosa, 2007, p. 24; 2009, pp. 135-153; 2011, pp. 67-95). Reflective knowledge is actively acquired as the result of an intentional investigation; it requires the agent to undertake voluntary intellectual activities: thinking about evidence, formulating hypotheses, evaluating objections, considering alternatives, and formulating conjectures, as is the case with science and philosophy. 3. Judgment and Agency goes one step further, since Sosa intends to develop his theory of human knowledge (as seen in Sosa, 2007 and 2009) further than before, by taking up issues of metaphysics and ethics (broadly conceived) that arise for it (Sosa,, p.1). We would like to highlight two points here. A large number of commentators and philosophers divide virtue epistemology into two branches, reliabilist virtue epistemology (associated with Sosa and John Greco) and responsibilist virtue epistemology (associated with Linda Zagzebski, Jonathan Kvanvig and Jason Baehr) (Axtell, 2000). The latter is based on a direct criticism of reliabilism and is specifically located in the axiological, evaluative and moral aspects of knowledge. Intellectual virtues are strictly the agent s characteristic traits related to their personal qualities. For this reason, when we assign a virtue to a person, we are, in fact, saying 125

Beyond Virtue Epistemology that they have a motive or inspiration to act in a certain way in order to carry out an intellectual good, principally to attain truth. In a frank debate with Jason Baehr (2011) and in the light of an interesting reinterpretation of the skeptical tradition in Descartes and Sextus Empiricus Sosa (, pp. 2-3; 34-61; 215-254) considers that a true epistemology will indeed assign to such responsibilist-cum-reliabilist intellectual virtue the main role in addressing concerns at the center of the tradition. The second point refers to the two notions that figure in the book title, agency and judgment. For Sosa, someone is an agent if they have the capacity to perform actions freely and deliberately endeavor to perform them. Epistemic agency is present if this person has the capacity to undertake an epistemic performance by choice. Judgment, for its part, is the exercise of epistemic agency, when the person establishes a goal to reach higher levels of epistemic performance ( full aptness, knowing full well ), as found in the philosophical traditions started by Pyrrhonism and in Descartes concept of scientia. As the first part of the book suggests, Judgment and Agency proposes an extended and unified virtue epistemology, which goes beyond virtue epistemology, deepening and extending its previous positions, principally that of reflective aptness. Judgment is identified as a fully alethic assertion which aims for both aptness and accuracy. From this point of view, an apt judgment is a fully apt assertion because, as well as seeking truth, it surpasses that which is only reflectively apt (for reflective aptness the condition of aptness and the condition of aptly representing it as apt are autonomous). Judgment as an exercise of epistemic agency is a fully apt performance because it is the kind of performance which necessarily expresses the competence that an agent exercises when he freely decides to undertake an investigation. From the point of view of tradition, crucial epistemic competence and agential performance are originally at the center of any philosophical investigation about knowledge, while, in the meantime, many current epistemologists, be these associated with reliabilism or responsibilist virtue epistemology, have neglected this aspect 126 4. In June, under the auspices of the Postgraduate Program in Philosophy at the Federal University of Bahia (UFBA) and the Teaching, Philosophy and History of Science Program at UFBA/State University of Feira de Santana (UEFS), with financial support from the Coordi-

Waldomiro Silva Filho nation for the Improvement of Higher Education Personnel (CAPES PAEP 2012, process number 342229) and coordinated by both the Grupo de Investigações Filosóficas (CNPq) and the Skepticism Working Group (GT-Ceticismo) of the National Association of Postgraduate Studies in Philosophy (ANPOF), a group of Brazilian philosophers met in the city of Salvador, Bahia, Brazil in order to converse with Professor Ernest Sosa about his book Judgment and Agency. This book symposium brings together contributions from the participants at this meeting. Only Professor João Carlos Salles, as a result of his pressing commitments as Rector of Universidade Federal da Bahia was unable to contribute his text to this publication. We would, however, like to extend our sincere thanks to him for his valuable participation. The meeting that took place in Bahia was a truly unique opportunity for the participants. As well as being one of the most important philosophers of our time, Professor Ernest Sosa is also highly educated and polite, open to dialogue, attentive to criticisms, and respectful of his interlocutors. We were able not only to discuss and clarify points in Sosa s arguments, but also to establish a frank dialogue. For the postgraduate programs involved in promoting the event, this signified an important step in terms of their international involvement, since they then began to address the agenda of current, significant debates in the philosophical community. We would like to thank two specific supporters of this project. This publication would not have been possible without the encouragement of Juan Comesaña and Edgar Marques. Juan provided initial contact with Ernest Sosa, while Edgar, the Editor of Analytica, enthusiastically accepted our proposal to publish this book symposium. Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA, January 6, 2016. 127

Beyond Virtue Epistemology References Axtell, Guy (2000). Introduction. In: Axtell, Guy (ed.) Knowledge, Belief, and Character: Readings in Virtue Epistemology. Lanham, Boulder, New York, Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. xi-xxix. Baehr, Jason (2011). The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues & Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford Neta, Ram (). Ernest Sosa - Judgment and Agency. In: Notre Dame Philosophical Review (Nov.). Accessed in http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/62571-judgment-and-agency/. Goldman, Alvin (2012). Reliabilism and Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford Sosa, Ernest (1991). Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge Sosa, Ernest (2007). A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Vol. I. Oxford: Oxford Sosa, Ernest (2009). Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford Sosa, Ernest (2011). Knowing Full Well. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton Sosa, Ernest (). Judgment and Agency. Oxford: Oxford 128 Recebido em janeiro de 2016 Aprovado em março de 2016