The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Similar documents
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Philosophical Review.


The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

History of Education Society

Philosophical Review.

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld


From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

What is a counterexample?

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 17. Naturalism and Norms

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1


Varieties of Apriority

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

M.A. PROSEMINAR, PHIL 5850 PHILOSOPHICAL NATURALISM Fall 2018 Tuesdays 2:35-5:25 p.m. Paterson Hall 3A36

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

The Social Atom and Death. J. L. Moreno. Sociometry, Vol. 10, No. 1. (Feb., 1947), pp

Naturalism and is Opponents

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis


Epistemology Naturalized

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

Skepticism and Internalism

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Equality of Resources and Equality of Welfare: A Forced Marriage?

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Oxford University Press and The Analysis Committee are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Analysis.

Horwich and the Liar

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Machine Consciousness, Mind & Consciousness

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

Constructing the World

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Contemporary Epistemology

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Royal Institute of Philosophy

Realism and instrumentalism

Philosophy Courses-1

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).


INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

Philosophy Courses-1

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

Stout s teleological theory of action

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Probability: A Philosophical Introduction Mind, Vol July 2006 Mind Association 2006

What Should We Believe?

Transcription:

Review: [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Judgment and Justification by William G. Lycan Lynne Rudder Baker The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp. 481-484. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108%28199107%29100%3a3%3c481%3ajaj%3e2.0.co%3b2-n The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Mon Jul 30 18:39:19 2007

cludes many sentences linked to stimulation only very indirectly. So it seems that translation manuals must be sensitive to the connections-to the internal structure of theories. This is not to gay that translation must take account of physiological facts as such. As Quine has said, "translators do not supplement their behavioral criteria with neurological criteria." The point is rather that translation manuals must take account not only of dispositions to assent to and dissent from queried sentences, but of higher-order dispositions, including those to revise, acquire, or lose such dispositions. For example, they must take account of the kinds of dispositions which come into play when discussion induces people to reflect, revise their views, and arrive at new conclusions. Unlike the thesis which Hookway ascribes to Quine, the thesis that translation is underdetermined even by the totality of such dispositions is neither obviously true nor obviously false, and seems to have the interesting implications which Quine claims for his indeterminacy thesis. Hookway himself seems to lean towards a Davidsonian approach to interpretation. His account of the contrasts between this approach and Quine's is illuminating. The philosophical vision of Hookway's Quine is "rather narrow," focused on the search for the ultimate laws governing the universe (p. 220). His chief importance is that "he has worked through what is involved in a physicalist empiricism more thoroughly and rigorously than any other post-positivist philosopher" (p. 219). I would argue for a more generous reading of Quine's work. The last but one paragraph suggests that such a reading may be available for the particular case of the indeterminacy doctrine. I think it is also available for other key ideas, notably those of physicalism, realism and factuality. However, Hookway makes a strong case on the opposite side. His sophisticated discussions in this area are among the most valuable features of his book. University of Nottingham ROBERTKIRK The Philosophical Review, Vol. C, NO.3 (July 1991) JUDGEMENT AND JUSTIFICATION. By WILLIAM G. LYCAN.New York, N.Y., Cambridge University Press, 1988. Pp. xiv, 236. Judgement and Justfication completes Lycan's presentation of his views on cognition. With nine of the eleven chapters reworked from previously published articles, the book is not as cohesive or as deep as Lycan's Logical Form in Natural Language (MITIBradford, 1984) or Knowing Who (with Stephen Boer; MITIBradford, 1986). Nevertheless, it is a useful addition

BOOK REVZE WS to the literature aiming to "naturalize" the mind by showing how cognitive phenomena fit into the (nonintentional, nonsemantic) "closed causal order." Lycan is sensitive to the difficulties of this project, and he tackles them with vigor. The book has two parts. Part I, on philosophy of psychology, has chapters on the ontology of belief, the semantics of belief ascription, tacit belief, and psychological laws. Part 11, on epistemic justification, has chapters on reliabilism, inference to the best explanation, the realism/ antirealism debate, and moral knowledge. I have space here for only a brief comment on each part. A belief, on Lycan's representational view, is a sentence-in-the-head with a truth condition and a computational/causal role. Lycan argues forcefully that a narrow psychology that eschews semantic properties misses important generalizations, and that in psychological explanations of certain phenomena (for example, learning from authority), we need to ascribe beliefs individuated by truth condition (pp. 79ff.). But on Lycan's model, a psychological ("homunctionalist") law would take the form: "If an organism of type X receives an input of type Y while its @-er is in state A and its JI-er is in state B (etc.), then (it is probable to degree n that) the organism will spit out an output of type Z" (p. 50). This raises, but does not answer, a crucial question: If psychological laws take this form, just how do they accommodate belief indiuiduated by truth condition? One may suspect that in order to accommodate such belief, the inputs and outputs must be specified intentionally or semantically, in which case the law loses its "naturalistic" credentials. Perhaps Lycan will reply that the laws are causal, but not all explanations are causal; hence, explanations in terms of belief individuated by truth condition-call these "semantic explanations'-may not require causal laws as backing. But this suggests a dilemma: Either there are behavior-explaining psychological laws that are noncausal, or semantic explanations are not backed by psychological laws of any sort. The former, I think, would be unpalatable to one with a "naturalistic" account of scientific psychology; the latter would undercut the motivation for introducing semantic explanations into psychology in the first place. These worries also suggest at least a limitation on Lycan's "two-schemes" approach to belief ascription. Lycan is ecumenical: When we are interested in explaining and predicting behavior, we individuate beliefs in terms of computational/causal properties; but when we are interested in truth and reliability, we individuate in terms of semantic properties. Sometimes, however, when we want to explain some behavior based on

what one has learned from authority, we seem to need individuation in terms of both semantic and causal properties. Now consider epistemic value. Lycan's view is "explanationism," that is, "crudely put, the doctrine that all justified reasoning is fundamentally explanatory reasoning that aims at maximizing the 'explanatory coherence' of one's total belief system" (p. 128). We begin with our spontaneous beliefs, which we accept as true at the outset. (Lycan emphasizes conservatism.) Then there are three further(?) kinds of explanatory coherence; the first two are consistency and incorporability into the system of one's previously justified beliefs. Beliefs that pass these tests are "tenable." The third grade of coherence, needed for a belief to be fully justified, is characterized in nonequivalent ways. Tenable beliefs achieve coherence of the third kind if and only if: (a) The believer has explanations of the production of the beliefs as outputs of reliable mechanisms (p. 168) (b) The believer has explanations of the production of the beliefs, and each explanation "involves the truth of the belief" (p. 209) (c) The "beliefs achieve their coherence of the third kind purely through the roles they play in a maximally coherent explanatory system and not because of anything in particular to do with the mechanisms that produced them" (pp. 172-173). The differences among (a)-(c) are important. (Clearly, the book would have benefited from a more careful reworking of the original papers.) Characterization (c) has earned Lycan the epithet "Hegelian fellow traveler." On characterization (b), Descartes's proof of the existence of God in Meditation I11 would seem to achieve coherence of the third kind, thereby rendering his belief in God "fully justified, perhaps to the point of counting as an item of knowledge" (p. 209). At best, (a) alone conforms to "naturalism." Lycan makes a striking attempt to accommodate morality in his "naturalistic" picture. However, the differences in the characterizations (a)-(c) of coherence of the third kind prevent clear discussion of the justification

of moral beliefs. Also, much more needs to be said about the supervenient status of moral facts. Simply to suggest that moral properties may be identical to properties "of a more or less nonevaluative sort" (p. 204) like "utility, harm and degradation" (p. 207), which, in turn, supervene on physical properties, is just a promissory note-all the more so in light of the ostensible value-ladenness of properties like degradation. The last word is not in on these perplexing issues, but Lycan allows them to be raised in explicit and perspicuous ways. Whether or not Lycan's framework finally proves successful, I would recommend this work to philosophers interested in philosophy of psychology or in epistemology. People unfamiliar with recent work in these areas, however, will find the book too schematic to stand on its own; frequently, instead of laying out arguments, Lycan relies on simply citing sources in lists. Judgement and Justification features Lycan's usual energetic style of writing. It is engaging and well informed, and readers who appreciate the enormity of Lycan's task will find that it illuminates various aspects of cognition. Middlebury College Uniuersity of Massachusetts at Amherst The Philosophical Review, Vol. C, No. 3 (July 1991) ENLIGHTENED EMPIRICISM: AN EXAMINATION OF W. V. QUINE'S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. By ROGER F. GIBSON, JR. Gainesville, Fla., University Presses of Florida, 1988. Pp. xix, 191. Enlightened Empiricism is Gibson's second book on the work of W. V. Quine. Its purpose is to develop the interpretation of Quine's views offered in the earlier book, The Philosophy of W. V. Quine: An Expository Essay,' and to defend Quine's position against some critics. While no one doubts that Quine is a systematic philosopher, there is not a consensus on how to understand his arguments and doctrines. Gibson is addressing questions that have exercised Quine scholars for at least twenty years. He argues that Quine's views on many topics, ranging from ontology to ethics, stem from a "central axiom," which he calls "the naturalistic-behaviorist (NB) thesis." The NB thesis is the view that language is 'Gainesville, Fla.: University Presses of Florida, 1982.