Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology

Similar documents
Beyond Virtue Epistemology 1

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE

Contemporary epistemologists often borrow from act

Attacking Character: Ad Hominem Argument and Virtue Epistemology

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

1 Sosa 1991, pg. 9 2 Ibid, pg Ibid, pg Ibid, pg. 179

Book Reviews 309 science, in the broadest sense of the word is a complex achievement, which depends on a number of different activities: devising theo

THE DEBATE ON EPISTEMIC AND ETHICAL NORMATIVITY

Virtue reliabilism is a theory of justification: it purports to give the

What Should We Believe?

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Virtue Epistemologies and Epistemic Vice

Prof Paul O Grady 16 th January, What is Wisdom?

PHIL-210: Knowledge and Certainty

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

INFERENCE AND VIRTUE

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

Four Varieties of Character-Based Virtue Epistemology

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Epistemic Virtues and their Limits

Skepticism and Internalism

Unifying the intellectual virtues (formerly known as Virtues, truth-conduciveness, and robustness ) Draft, March 2009

Character, Reliability, and Virtue Epistemology

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Competent Perspectives and the New Evil Demon Problem

Three Independent Factors in Epistemology. Guy Axtell and Phil Olson

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

EPISTEMIC EVALUATION AND THE AIM OF BELIEF. Kate Nolfi. Chapel Hill 2010

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Character Virtues, Epistemic Agency, and Reflective Knowledge

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

INTRODUCTION. Chapter 1

MSc / PGDip / PGCert Epistemology (online) (PHIL11131) Course Guide

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Safety, Virtue, Scepticism: Remarks on Sosa

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Reliabilism, Stability, and the Value of Knowledge. Erik J. Olsson

Reliabilism and intellectual virtue

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Life Science Journal 2014;11(9) Virtue Epistemology and Psychology of Education. Karimov, Artur Ravilevich

Edinburgh Research Explorer

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility. Allan Hazlett. Forthcoming in Episteme

The Theory of Epistemic Justification and the Theory of Knowledge: A Divorce

EPISTEMIC VIRTUE AND ACCEPTANCE IN LEGAL FACT-FINDING

Prejudice and closed-mindedness are two examples of what Linda Zagzebski calls intellectual vices. Here is her list of such vices:

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Introduction Naturalized virtue epistemology

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Some Iterations on The Subject s Perspective Objection to Externalism By Hunter Gentry

Epistemic Virtue from the Viewpoints of Mulla Sadra and Zagzebski

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Virtues, Evidence, and Ad Hominem Arguments

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

Sosa on Human and Animal Knowledge

RECOVERING PLATO: A PLATONIC VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY

WARRANT AND EPISTEMIC VIRTUES: TOWARD AN AGENT-RELIABILIST ACCOUNT OF PLANTINGA S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE STEWART DOUGLAS CLEM

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION

Truth as the Epistemic Goal Marian David. From Steup, M Knowledge, Truth, and Duty.

Sosa on Epistemic Value

The Value of Knowledge. Olsson, Erik J. Published in: Philosophy Compass. Link to publication

Ernest Sosa and virtuously begging the question

Responsibilism and the Analytic-Sociological Debate in Social Epistemology

OTHER-REGARDING EPISTEMIC VIRTUES. Jason Kawall

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Evidentialist Reliabilism

KNOWLEDGE AND INTELLECTUAL SKILL JOSHUE OROZCO. A Dissertation submitted to the. Graduate School-New Brunswick

Internalism and Et Externalism

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

JASON BAEHR. Department of Philosophy Loyola Marymount University One LMU Drive Los Angeles CA,

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Edinburgh Research Explorer

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Routledge Handbook of Virtue Epistemology, ed. Heather Battaly. Epistemic Virtues in Understanding. Catherine Z. Elgin

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Forthcoming in Epistemology, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Internalism without Luminosity 1

EVERYBODY NEEDS TO KNOW?

Dr. Evan Butts. Academic Building 419 College Drive Barnesville, GA United States (Home) (Mobile)

Published version in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64, January 2002

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Knowledge First Virtue Epistemology

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

V.F. Hendricks. Mainstream and Formal Epistemology. Cambridge University Press, 2006, xii pp.

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Transcription:

IB Metaphysics & Epistemology S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology 1. Beliefs and Agents We began with various attempts to analyse knowledge into its component parts. Given the intuition that knowledge is something, in some sense, more valuable than merely true belief, we searched for properties that, when added to true belief, would be necessary and sufficient for knowledge. In discussing accounts of justification, we encountered the intuition that epistemic agents should act in ways that are epistemically responsible. It is this intuition that motivates the class of theories that come under the heading virtue epistemology. In virtue epistemology, agents rather than beliefs are the primary objects of epistemic evaluation, and intellectual virtues and vices, which are evaluations of the agents, are the fundamental concepts and properties (Heather Battaly 2008: 640). 2. Varieties of Virtue Epistemology There are different kinds of virtue epistemology. Accounts are often divided into two main categories: virtue reliabilists and virtue responsibilists. These two kinds of virtue epistemology disagree about what intellectual virtues consist in. Virtue Reliabilists This version of virtue epistemologist draws heavily on the processreliabilist s position, but uses to the notion of an intellectual virtue to solve problems faced by the latter s theory. Ernest Sosa is a prominent example of virtue-reliabilist. On Sosa s account, for a belief to be justified is for it to manifest a truth-conducive faculty or intellectual virtue (2010: 273, my emphasis). And, knowledge is true belief out of intellectual virtue, belief that turns out right by reason of the virtue and not just by coincidence (277, my emphasis).

IB Metaphysics & Epistemology S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 2 Faculty = a virtue or competence such that an epistemic agent S has said virtue only if there is a field of propositions F and a set of circumstances C (that are accessible within S s epistemic perspective) in which S would likely distinguish the true from the false in F in C. E.g. Vision. The field would include propositions about the appearance of things; the circumstances would include standard conditions of observation. From here, S can be said to have a given intellectual virtue V(C, F) relative to some environment E just in case S has an inner nature I such that if (i)-(iv) obtain, S is very likely right with respect to P. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) S is in E and has I P is a proposition in field F S is in conditions C with respect to P S believes or disbelieves P And from this, S can be said to believe some proposition P, at time t, out of intellectual virtue just in case, (1) S is in an environment E such that S has intellectual virtue V(C, F) relative to E (2) P is a proposition in F (3) S is in C with respect to P (4) S believes that P Notice that the reliability of the virtue is indexed to a particular epistemic agent. This is part of what distinguishes virtue-reliabilism from process-reliabilism. Sosa s virtue perspectivism, as he calls it, makes several distinctions that allow it to accommodate both internalist and externalist intuitions about our beliefs. Justification/Aptness Justification of a belief that P requires the (implicit or explicit) use of reasons in favour of P (290). This is an internalist notion.

IB Metaphysics & Epistemology S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 3 Aptness of a belief concerns the truth-conduciveness of the method used to form the belief. A belief can be apt without being justified. This is an externalist notion. Animal Knowledge/Reflective Knowledge Animal knowledge consists in true beliefs that are apt but (often) not justified. They arise out of (an) intellectual virtue, but the agent often is not aware of this (though they may be so). The agent must conform to this virtue not by accident but because they possess that virtue. E.g. a child knows that the ball is on the grass because their belief is a result of using the virtue of vision. Their belief is apt but, they couldn t give you an explanation of their belief in terms of the reliability of vision. Reflective knowledge consists in true beliefs that are justified. Again, they must arise out of intellectual virtue, where the agent must conform to the virtue because they possess that virtue (and not merely by accident). Virtue Responsibilist This version of virtue epistemologist draws heavily on its ethical counterpart. It begins with the intuition that what makes an agent an excellent thinker are active features of her agency: actions, motivations, and habits over which she has some control and for which she is (to some degree) responsible (Battaly 2010: 648). There is some disagreement between responsibilists over whether virtues must be reliable or not. Montmarquet (1987) argues that they need not be; on his position virtues need only be desirable to those agents who want truth. On the other hand, Zagzebski (1996) argues that they do have to be reliable, in some sense; she takes virtues to be traits a virtuous agent would possess involving a motivation to achieve a particular epistemic end, and reliability in leading to that end (where the end must always include attaining truth). Some intellectual virtues countenanced by Monmarquet and Zagzebski include: Intellectual courage willingness to investigate non-orthodox ideas; willingness to challenge orthodox ideas

IB Metaphysics & Epistemology S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 4 Impartiality openness to other s ideas; lack of personal bias Intellectual humility sensitivity to one s own fallibility Thoroughness willingness to research and investigate On these views, a virtuously formed belief is justified, and a virtuously formed true belief is knowledge (modulo each s conception of what it takes to be an intellectual virtue). There is some debate over whether the reliabilist/responsibilist distinction is a useful one in carving up the virtue epistemological landscape. Indeed, notice that the idea of reliability seems to appear on either side of the divide. So far, we have seen a distinction between those theories that require virtues to be reliable and those that do not (Zagzebski/Sosa vs. Montmarquet). And we have seen a distinction between those theories that allow faculties to be virtues, or only traits (Sosa vs. Montmarquet/Zagzebski). There is yet a further distinction to be made between those virtue epistemological accounts that seek to participate in the defining of knowledge and justification, and those that eschew this practice altogether. Call these theorists and anti-theorists respectively. Those we ve talked about so far can broadly be classed as theorists. 3. Anti-Theorists Virtue anti-theorists agree with other virtue epistemologists that the epistemology debate so far needs to change, and should do so by shifting focus in some way to the notion of intellectual virtues. So far, we have discussed those that are interested in offering definitions of justification and knowledge in terms of intellectual virtues. But some virtue epistemologists disagree with this approach. For instance, Lorraine Code (1987) argues that we should adopt virtue epistemology, but that doing so will not provide a decision-making scale against which specific knowledge claims can be measured for validity (63). While some argue that, given this, we should give up on the project of defining knowledge and justification altogether (Kvanvig 1992). Other argue for a more inclusive view of epistemology; one that includes the

IB Metaphysics & Epistemology S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 5 traditional enterprise, but adds other hitherto ignored questions about knowledge. For instance, Miranda Fricker (2007) argues that the traditional enterprise is not conducive to revealing the ethical and political aspects of our epistemic conduct (2). She argues that intellectual virtues are invaluable to understanding these aspects of our epistemic lives; however, she takes this view to be consistent with allowing the traditional analytic enterprise to continue. 4. Problems for Virtue Epistemology As with any position in philosophy, virtue epistemologies of all sorts face objections. Some argue (e.g. Lockie 2006) that the virtue epistemologist s claim to provide an irenic solution to the internalist/externalist debate is illfounded. Lockie in particular argues that as soon as one asks about the nature of the epistemic agent (information-processor or free self with choice over cognitive conduct?), the debate reemerges. Similarly when one asks what the value of the virtues are (as merely means to truth or as part of practical wisdom?). Second, there is a question as to whether the character-first picture is correct. What is it for an agent to have a particular character? If character reduces to actions, then we have to be able to describe the formation of particular beliefs as epistemically good independently of the agent s character. NEXT WEEK: Knowledge First