Establishing premises

Similar documents
There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Now you know what a hypothesis is, and you also know that daddy-long-legs are not poisonous.

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Let s explore a controversial topic DHMO. (aka Dihydrogen monoxide)

From the Greek Oikos = House Ology = study of

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Physics 496 Introduction to Research. Lecture 2.0: Tools for the Scientific Skeptic (Based on a talk by Lance Cooper)

If I were to give an award for the single best idea anyone has ever had, I d give it to... Darwin

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Logical (formal) fallacies

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

1. What is Philosophy?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

Forum on Public Policy

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to Critical Thinking M. Neil Browne and Stuart Keeley

Argumentation. 2. What should we consider when making (or testing) an argument?

Scientific Arguments

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

CHAPTER 13: UNDERSTANDING PERSUASIVE. What is persuasion: process of influencing people s belief, attitude, values or behavior.

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

IIE-2015 Workshop December 12 20, K P Mohanan. Types of Reasoning

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

Naturalism vs. Conceptual Analysis. Marcin Miłkowski

Experimental Design. Introduction

Arguments. 1. using good premises (ones you have good reason to believe are both true and relevant to the issue at hand),

Chapter Notes (Final Exam) On April, 26, 2012

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Basic Concepts and Skills!

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Discussion Notes for Bayesian Reasoning

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Ch01. Knowledge. What does it mean to know something? and how can science help us know things? version 1.5

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

Chapter 5: Ways of knowing Reason (p. 111)

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

II Plenary discussion of Expertise and the Global Warming debate.

PHIL / PSYC 351. Thinking and Reasoning

BIO 221 Invertebrate Zoology I Spring Course Information. Course Website. Lecture 1. Stephen M. Shuster Professor of Invertebrate Zoology

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Richard Carrier, Ph.D.

This fallacy gets its name from the Latin phrase "post hoc, ergo propter hoc," which translates as "after this, therefore because of this.

Philosophical Arguments

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy. Hume on Causation. I. Recap of Hume on impressions/ideas

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Correcting the Creationist

Practice Test Three Spring True or False True = A, False = B

PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS

"Easy Yokes for Sagging Shoulders" + 8 Pentecost A + Zechariah 9:9-12; Romans 7:15-25; Matthew 11:16-19, July 6, 2008

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

What is Pseudoscience?

Science and Faith: Discussing Astronomy Research with Religious Audiences

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Karl Popper & The Philosophy of Science. What Makes a Theory Scientific?

Why Creation Science must be taught in schools

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

I. Claim: a concise summary, stated or implied, of an argument s main idea, or point. Many arguments will present multiple claims.

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Evidence for evolution

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

What is rationality? (Paper presented by Tim Harding at Mordi Skeptics meetup, 1 February 2011)

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Theory of knowledge prescribed titles

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Chapter 2 Science as a Way of Knowing: Critical Thinking about the Environment

Debate Vocabulary 203 terms by mdhamilton25

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Intelligent Design. Kevin delaplante Dept. of Philosophy & Religious Studies

YFIA205 Basics of Research Methodology in Social Sciences Lecture 1. Science, Knowledge and Theory. Jyväskylä 3.11.

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

1/18/2009. Signatories include:

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Why We Should Trust Scientists (transcript)

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

The Nature of Science: Methods for Seeking Natural Patterns in the Universe Using Rationalism and Empiricism Mike Viney

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Transcription:

Establishing premises This is hard, subtle, and crucial to good arguments. Various kinds of considerations are used to establish the truth (high justification) of premises Deduction Done Analogy Induction Inference to the best explanation

Explanation What is an explanation? An answer to a why questions Beliefs are often justified because they help explain our experience. What kinds of explanation are there? saying how something is the consequence of more general facts (deductive) stating the causes of an event (causal) stating the purpose of an event (teleological)

Causal explanation Generally, we're interested in stating some necessary (not sufficient) conditions of an event Definitions: sufficient conditions together always guarantee a result (although they might not have to obtain for the result). A->B necessary conditions must obtain to get the explained result (but don't guarantee the result on their own) A->B E.g., The vase broke because I hit it with a hammer, it s glass, I hit it hard, (suff: given these it had to break, but can break other ways)) The vase broke because I knocked off the table (necess: if i didn t knock it off it wouldn t have broken)

Structure of causal explanation Usually, causal explanation is about constructing an 'abductive' argument (aka Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE)) These are of the (non-deductive/invalid) form: One observes O E is part of the best explanation for O Therefore, E. O E->O Therefore, E E.g.: I see a broken vase and small, muddy feline-like foot prints nearby. My cat breaking the vase is part of the best explanation for it being broken. Therefore, my cat broke the vase.

It s not valid Homer: Well, there's not a bear in sight. The Bear Patrol is sure doing its job. Lisa: That's specious reasoning, Dad. Homer: Thank you, sweetie. Lisa: Dad, what if I were to tell you that this rock keeps away tigers. Homer: Uh-huh, and how does it work? Lisa: It doesn't work. It's just a stupid rock. Homer: I see. Lisa: But you don't see any tigers around, do you? Homer: Lisa, I'd like to buy your rock.

Induction Also very common in science Of the form: All observed A are B Therefore all A are B. E.g., All observed crows are black Therefore all crows are black

Example: Inductive failure All observed philosophy professors are at UW Therefore all philosophy professors are at UW U of Waterloo

Induction (cont.) How do we know the argument form isn't deductively valid? Determining when it is justified can be done by considering it as we have considered cases of abduction. Suppose we identify the implicit premise: E is part of the best explanation for the first premise [where E=All A are B] What do we have? abduction (i.e., IBE!)

Induction (cont.) The main determinant of the goodness of E will be how the statistics are collected (a later topic) In particular, E should reflect a good sampling of the relevant target population (e.g., florks are white vs. florks have livers ) Given this characterization of induction, we know that we can evaluate such arguments in the same way we evaluate abductions (IBE). Much of the latter part of the course is about how to evaluate IBE, because it is about how to evaluate theories.

Three kinds of argument Deduction All balls from this bag are red These balls are from this bag. Therefore, these balls are red. Abduction All balls from this bag are red These balls are red. Therefore, these balls are from this bag. Induction These balls are from this bag. (& these balls, ) O These balls are red Therefore, all balls from this bag are red. E E O

Induction and Abduction Abduction Generates hypotheses Becomes induction if we continue to test the conclusion Induction Summarizes past observations Becomes abduction if our best explanation of the observations is the conclusion Both Are invalid forms Are used in most of our reasoning

Causal reasoning Can provide reasons to believe A->B (all else being equal) We can characterize causal arguments as 'double' abduction (IBE). These arguments are of the form: P1: Observed A and B are correlated P2: C1 is part of the best explanation for P1 C1: Therefore, A and B are generally correlated P3: C2 is part of the best explanation for C1 C2: Therefore, events of kind A cause events of kind B P1, P2, and C1 form the first abduction and C1, P3, and C2 form the second abduction.

Causal conclusions (cont.) P1: In most cases when I turn my key (A) my car starts (B). P2: Turning my key being generally correlated with my car starting is part of the best explanation for those observations C1: Therefore, turning my key is generally correlated with my car starting P3: That turning my key causes my car to start is the best explanation for that correlation C2: Therefore turning my key causes my car to start

Causal explanation (cont.) However, Correlation Causation: P1: In most cases when I have lunch (A) the peace tower bells ring (B). P2: My having lunch being generally correlated with the ringing bells is part of the BE C1: Therefore, my having lunch is generally correlated with ringing bells P3: That my having lunch causes ringing bells is the BE C2: Therefore my having lunch causes ringing bells

Causal conclusions (cont.) Why use correlation? Because: Claiming that A is a cause is not the claim that A is sufficient for B, but rather that it is a necessary part of the sufficient conditions for B. The other conditions that make the sufficient set may vary from case to case (and we may not know what they are), we must rely on imperfect correlations to suggest when events are causally related.

Causal conclusions (cont.) E.g., Helicobacter pylori hypothesis (Nobel Prize) Bacterium causes ulcers (but not in everyone all the time) Supported by an imperfect correlation (i.e. not everyone exposed to helicobacter gets an ulcer) The reason is that the remaining background or structuring conditions must be met as well They are only met in some individuals, so exposure to the bacterium only works in those cases. However, even in those individuals who do meet these conditions, ulcers won't appear unless they are exposed to the bacterium.

Causal conclusions (cont.) How can you help rule out other causes? in the lab, i.e., perform controlled experiments (we will talk about these in detail a few classes from now). Criticizing such causal arguments is much like criticizing abduction (or IBE). Except we can apply the criteria twice. To criticize the first premise, in particular, it is useful to understand the pitfalls of statistical data... which is a later topic

Observation What counts as an observation is relative to context. The context is generally determined by what we permit ourselves to take for granted (which can easily vary). So, we must agree on what the observations are before trying to compare explanations of the phenomena.

Finding the best explanation Determining which explanation is the best can be quite difficult. Generally we should prefer: explanations that rely on already widely established theories explanations that are specific (hence more evaluable) Often the best explanation will come from/be part of the best established theory (we will return to this shortly).

Science Pragmatically, science is a trusted source of factual knowledge Scientists often enjoy prestige and authority Scientific denotes reliability, honesty, accuracy, care in production, generally positive associations. The claim that a statement is scientific isn t especially helpful (compare reasonable ) What makes a statement (argument, method) scientific?

Science is... Just the facts No science proceeds theory free A method Mostly fit retrospectively or partially Naturalism How to distinguish supernatural from natural Verifiability & falsifiability Both are a matter of degree which don t demarcate

An attitude No need to appeal to unwarranted objects (phlogiston) Always allow the possibility of error (ID pledges) Domain specific application of many critical thinking ideas In short, a rejection of dubious statistics, biases (psychological & otherwise), fallacious reasoning, sloppy methods, irreproducibility, dogmatism Does not provide a sharp science/pseudo-science divide!

Evaluating theories So how do we determine which theories are good to have and which aren't? Generally, a good theory has: 1. Content: The theory should be testable. 2. Scope: The theory should be truly general. 3. Unity: The theory should integrate with other theories. 4. Accuracy: The theory should have many confirming cases (i.e. consistent with the data). 5. Uniqueness: The theory should rule out competing theories.

Content A theory has content just in case it has consequences that could be false The more non-accidental the consequences, the more content it has (e.g. precision = content). The content of a theory is diminished if: It lacks clarity It is imprecise, meaning that although quantitative predictions are made, they have large ranges It relies on ad hoc (literally 'to this') elements. It is vacuous.

Scope It s truly general A theory that reduces the number of beliefs we need to have while explaining the same phenomena will be a strong candidate. Ockham's razor - simpler theories are to be preferred over more complex ones. Sir William

Unity A theory is generally better if it meshes with our previous beliefs, especially if we can derive it from those beliefs. We should generally be skeptical of theories that posit bizarre, unproven forces.

Accuracy A theory should have many confirming cases. Or, in contrast, we could say that theories should not be falsified (i.e., have disconfirming cases). However, falsification in science (and elsewhere) is seldom straight forward. We must consider the theory as a whole when determining if it is best or not.

Uniqueness A theory that predicts an outcome that no other theory predicts, or, better yet, contradicts previous theories will be very convincing. This essentially gives that theory a lot of content. The more such predictions, the more content the theory will have.

ID vs. evolution Question: How do evolution and creationism compare given these criteria? Content: The theory should be testable. Scope: The theory should be truly general. Unity: The theory should integrate with other theories. Accuracy: The theory should have many confirming cases (i.e. consistent with the data). Uniqueness: The theory should rule out competing theories.

Kansas On October 18, 2004, the Defendant Dover Area School Board of Directors passed by a 6-3 vote the following resolution: Students will be made aware of gaps/problems in Darwin s theory and of other theories of evolution including, but not limited to, intelligent design. Note: Origins of Life is not taught. On November 19, 2004, the Defendant Dover Area School District announced by press release that, commencing in January 2005, teachers would be required to read the following statement to students in the ninth grade biology class at Dover High School: The Pennsylvania Academic Standards require students to learn about Darwin s Theory of Evolution and eventually to take a standardized test of which evolution is a part. Because Darwin s Theory is a theory, it continues to be tested as new evidence is discovered. The Theory is not a fact. Gaps in the Theory exist for which there is no evidence. A theory is defined as a well-tested explanation that unifies a broad range of observations. Intelligent Design is an explanation of the origin of life that differs from Darwin s view. The reference book, Of Pandas and People, is available for students who might be interested in gaining an understanding of what Intelligent Design actually involves. With respect to any theory, students are encouraged to keep an open mind. The school leaves the discussion of the Origins of Life to individual students and their families. As a Standards-driven district, class instruction focuses upon preparing students to achieve proficiency on Standards-based assessments.

ID vs. evolution Essentially these criteria were used to successfully challenge this attempt to introduce intelligent design into Kansas classrooms http://files.findlaw.com/news.findlaw.com/hdocs/docs/ educate/ktzmllrdvr122005opn.pdf

Criticisms of IBE We can criticize IBE (abduction) by attacking either of the premises or the conclusion. In attacking the first premise, we can either show that it is false (i.e. O wasn't observed); or show that there is a further observation that doesn't fit with E In attacking the second premise we can apply the previously discussed criteria for evaluating explanations in the context of a theory

Criticizing abduction (cont.) In attacking the conclusion we can Give a counter example to E; or Derive consequences of E and show that they don't obtain (through experiment perhaps)

Example E.g.: Last night when I was out walking my dog, I looked up at the perfectly clear sky and saw a stationary light that hovered for a moment and then zoomed off. It must have been an alien space ship. You didn't see a light in the sky, it was a firefly. The UW meteorological society published a notice saying that they'd launch a weather balloon at exactly that time, and it burst shortly after takeoff. Many lights with those properties aren't alien space ships. If it was an alien space ship, we'd know about such things by now. If 'they' didn't want us to know, why was it lit?

Summary A general belief or theory is justified if it is part of the best explanation of what is observed. A particular belief is justified if it follows from some justified general belief. It should be clear that this incorporates a kind of circularity. The reason the circle is not vicious is because of the observations (and secondarily some of the criteria of what determines a 'best' explanation).

Question Question: Provide a causal argument for a simple, everyday causal connection (e.g. hitting glass causes it to break, striking a match causes it to light, flicking the light switch causes the light to go on, etc.).