NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

Similar documents
THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Are There Philosophical Conflicts Between Science & Religion? (Participant's Guide)

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

is knowledge normative?

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Assertion and Inference

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

PURE THEORY OF LAW - Legal Validity - Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Kant and his Successors

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The unity of the normative

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Dennett's Reduction of Brentano's Intentionality

MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Scanlon on Double Effect

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Philosophical Review.

Epistemology Naturalized

The text below preserves the pagination of the published version, but typos and minor errors have been corrected. Preferred citation form:

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Four Asymmetries Between Moral and Epistemic Trustworthiness Susann Wagenknecht, Aarhus University

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Ethics is subjective.

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Pragmatism and Inferentialism

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Realism and instrumentalism

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

The Ontological Argument. An A Priori Route to God s Existence?

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Citation Philosophy and Psychology (2009): 1.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Reply to Robert Koons

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

Transcription:

FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 195 NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 Jesús Zamora-Bonilla jpzb@fsof.uned.es UNED, Madrid. Spain. Stephen Turner s book Explaining the Normative (Polity, Oxford, 2010) constitutes a powerful onslaught against one of the main intellectual havens where the thesis of something like a transcendental foundation for rationality is still alive and flourishing. During the two last centuries, naturalism has been conquering one territory after another, but there was a portion of philosophical land where it seemed that ordinary scientific research would necessarily be insufficient to offer us an account of what happened there. This thesis has often been expressed as the irreducibility of normativity (see Parfit 2011 for a recent exposition), and Turner s book aims at showing that the arguments supporting this thesis are not defensible. I am absolutely sympathetic to the claim that the normative is just an ordinary citizen of the natural world, though probably more complex than other vulgar things like neutron stars, hurricanes or lizards, but my own impression reading the book has been that Turner tries perhaps to go a little bit farther than where I would be happy to take company with him, and I shall try here to explain the slight differences I see in our ways of understanding the question, albeit running the risk of misinterpreting some of his claims of course. I have to make a confession to begin with. A large part of my own work in analytical philosophy of science has been inspired by the idea that, besides analysing the internal structure and dynamics of purely epistemic states (i.e., what makes of something a theory, or a case of empirical confirmation, or a case of approximation to the truth, etc.), it was convenient to look at scientific objects as the result of the decisions of human agents (i.e., scientists), and those decisions would not only be guided by epistemic interest, but also by social ones. Most of the work done in the sociology of scientific knowledge in the last quarter of the past century tended to interpret the epistemic and the social as not only different, but usually conflicting aspects and forces within the possible motivations of scientists, with an increasingly smaller space left to the former as we approached the more radical, relativistic brands within the discipline. Looking for some approach in which the epistemic and the social could be conceived as coherent, complementary, and even interdependent elements of the process of scientific research, I came across Robert Brandom s breathtaking theoretical fabric as disclosed in his book Making it Explicit, and found in his notions of commitment, entitlement and scorekeeping a particularly apt methodological tool to represent the dynamics of scientific research in terms of a conversation governed by a system of inferential rules. These are rules that 1 Financial support from Spanish Government s research project FFI2011-23267 is acknowledged.

196 FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM help scientist to keep score of the contributions and burdens of each participant, and such that the explanation of why a scientific community adopts the rules it adopts might be given in terms of a combination of epistemic and social goals (i.e., only norms that are efficient enough in helping scientists to satisfy both types of goals would be accepted). The idea, then, of rational behaviour (in this case, the behaviour of scientists, but I am sure the idea can be made much more general so as to cover most of social action) as explainable by the agents submission to the validity of some norms governing the dynamics of their (i.e., the agents) obligations and permissions was a framework I found considerably apt to explain both why science is just a social battlefield and an efficient institution in the production of something like objective knowledge. Of course, this approach needed to assume the existence of norms and norm-guided behaviour, though in no moment did I doubt the possibility of giving an account of both things within a plainly naturalistic framework. In fact, I found it surprising that the reluctance of Brandom and other philosophers in the inferentialist school was taken as naturalist, since it was more or less obvious that, after all, what Brandom was doing could be phrased precisely as an attempt to describe and analyse what type of behaviour (empirically determinable by means of just good-old-fashioned descriptive, non-normative concepts) should an empirically given being display in order to be classified as engaging in a Sellarsian game-forgiving-and-asking-for-reasons ; a kind of analysis that is still more obvious in Brandom s later book, Between Saying and Doing. So, I confess I wanted to have my cake and eat it too: to have both a description and explanation of social behaviour (and even rational behaviour in general) in terms of norms, commitments, reasons, proprieties, and the like, and also staying within a safe naturalistic worldview which accepts that all that there is is what the best confirmed theories of our empirical sciences tell us there is. I celebrate, hence, Stephen Turner s book as a deep and clever attempt to deconstruct the anti-naturalist transcendentalism (what he calls normativism ) that transpires in much of the literature on norms and norm-guided behaviour, and in particular in many philosophical theories about the nature of rationality. However, I think that Turner s argument is also dangerously close to throwing the baby of normativity away with the bathwater of normativism. Normativism, i.e., the thesis that every form of rational thinking presupposes the existence of non-naturalisable normative facts and has to assume the validity some kind of Grundnorm self-evident to all rational agents, can be rightly critized, as Turner does, for necessarily resting on circular arguments, for accepting the existence of some type of queer facts not connectable to the natural causal order, for resting in the end on confusing metaphors, and for many other sins that make it suspicious of too closely resembling the old-fashioned supernatural entities of traditional theology, like God s and our rational, immortal soul s ghastly capabilities. But is it really necessary to dispense with normativity, i.e., the fact that there are such things in the world as norms and norm-guided behaviour in order to erase transcendental normativism from our intellectual zoo? The problem here is the usual one within the discussions about reductionism: should the reductionist attempt to explain the emergence of the reduced things, events and properties?, or

FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 197 should he (for the reductionist is typically a male in our philosophical imaginary) explain those things away? Perhaps I am not being fair to the aim of Turner s book, but my reading of it leads me to think that his argument is more of the second, eliminativist type. Consider, for example, the following quotation: Is there a fact that there are meanings and oughts? Or is merely a fact that people understand one another and that they have beliefs about obligations, or that (given that obligation is a local notion of our culture and time) that we can interpret as being about obligations? (op. cit., 188) When molecular biologists explain chromosomes on the basis of their chemical properties, they are not trying to deny that there is a fact that there are chromosomes ; they want, rather, to explain why chromosomes are the way they are. Even when (to cite what is perhaps the most famous example of reductionism) physicists explain the appearance of the rainbow, they do not deny that there are rainbows: these are simply a concrete species of optical phenomena. Cannot we take the same scientific attitude towards meanings and oughts? Of course, meanings and obligations only emerge when some very specific type of cognitive systems allow them to emerge, which includes the fact that some conscious agents understand, undertake and attribute those meanings and obligations, as rainbows only appear when some image producing device exists and is focused towards the right direction in the right circumstances. The critical point is that an acceptable naturalistic explanation of normative facts like meanings and commitments could not merely consist in directly identifying them with the beliefs of agents about them; i.e., my obligation of paying, say, 25,000 in income tax this year does not consist in my believing that I must do it, nor in the belief that such is the case by someone in the tax office, nor is of course something like a collective belief. It can indeed happen that I actually have the obligation of paying 25,000 this year, whereas my own belief about it is a different one (for example, I may have unconsciously miscalculated my tax return, and think that what I have to pay is 25,009), and that nobody else actually has any belief at all about this issue (for my tax return may be checked automatically by a computer that has been programmed so as not to inform about differences of less than 10). Of course, from a naturalist point of view my obligation, as a normative fact, cannot be but somehow constituted by some psychological attitudes of some flesh-and-bone people (viz., their beliefs and decisions about the creation of the norms regarding income tax, and about the legitimacy of the institutions and processes establishing the tax), but it does not consist in anyone s beliefs that I have such and such specific obligation, for the latter beliefs can, as any other kind of beliefs, be right or wrong. We can say something similar regarding Turner s attempt to dispense with transcendental explanations of rationality (i.e., those assuming that the existence of irreducibly normative facts is a prerequisite of any kind of rational thought) by resource to Donald Davidson s well known but probably not often well interpreted ideas about rationality and the charity principle. Turner is right in pointing out an important shortcoming of the trans-

198 FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM cendental approaches: there being committed to the assumption that one that violated some principle of rationality (e.g., consistency) would be irrational, and hence unintelligible. The fact, Turner insists, is that in general we can pretty well understand the people that, according to our own views, have some self-contradictory beliefs or support claims that lead to contradictions; we simply consider that they are wrong. Davidson s point that understanding someone implies being in agreement with most of what he or she thinks allows, on the one hand, that two people are in disagreement about some things, but on the other hand, and more importantly, it does not commit us to the claim that they must share something like a kernel of a priori, universal rationality principles. Instead, following Turner s interpretation, it only commits us to the idea that rational conversation and interaction is guided by empathy : my capability of seeing what you are behind, i.e., of tracking your own chains of arguments; a capability that can be given a plainly naturalistic explanation through our knowledge of neural systems (e.g., mirror neurons, and the like), and does not need any kind of transcendental foundation. The problem is that when I discover that some of your ideas are wrong, I am not simply following your chain of arguments. In a way, I am following your arguments while simultaneously following my own arguments, and seeing that both chains lead to contradictory results; but often it is the case that what I find is that it is you who is not correctly following your own chains of reasons. So, in order to assess your beliefs, I have to make a distinction between the process of reasoning you are actually carrying out, and the process of reasoning you should be carrying out (of course, each of us can, and even must, apply this very same distinction to our own selves). Does this entail that we have to presuppose something like irreducible normative facts? I don t think so. What is necessary is that when we attribute a belief to somebody (or to ourselves), we not only identify that belief with a mental state, but with a particular kind of mental state, namely the state of treating the content of that state as something that is subject to reasons, i.e., to say it in Brandomian jargon, the state of undertaking the commitment to revise that belief if compulsory arguments show it must be revised. But, what a kind of psychological state is this? The idea behind Turner s strategy of naturalisation-through-empathy was, as far as I understand it, to consider only the causal dispositions within the working of the other s brain (and all the relevant things), and follow these dispositions as far as possible. Stated differently, to empathise with someone s reasoning would consist in something like being capable of predicting what he or she will or would affirm under relevant circumstances. This includes our capacity to make counterfactual, subjunctive judgments about the linguistic behaviour of others, but nothing in this assumption goes against the hypotheses that all the relevant process is grounded on physical, natural capabilities, for counterfactual judgments are, after all, common in any area of natural science or its application. But what we are now trying to predict is not what the agent will do or say, but what she should do or say, i.e., what she would do or say were she appropriately honouring her commitments. Normativists would argue that this is not anything like an empirical prediction, but I think, with Turner, that we don t need to follow them in this point: the only thing we need to transform this

FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 199 prediction into an empirical one is an empirical description of what lines of behaviour or reasoning are appropriate to the commitments of the agent. Of course, this can only be done in a tentative, incomplete and perspective fashion: each agent will have her own (and probably mistaken at some point) ideas about what lines of action are appropriate to such and such commitments; ideas that she can apply rightly or wrongly, but it is according to these ideas that she will make her predictions about what others should do. Note that the fact that the term appropriately occurs within my phrase were she appropriately honouring her commitments does not presuppose any irreducible notion of appropriateness (i.e., one which is not ultimately accountable in terms of the actual attitudes of some subjects), for it has to be understood in the sense of appropriately from my own point of view, i.e., from the point of view of the person assessing the linguistic or cognitive behaviour of the other agent. What I (counterfactually) predict in saying what it is that the other person should do, is what she would do if her behaviour corresponded to what would be an appropriate compliance with her commitments according to my own interpretation of those commitments. In conclusion, I am optimistic about the possibility of reducing normativity to either biological or social natural processes, but this reduction would certainly not consist in explaining away normative facts. Instead it would involve showing how the particular kinds of psychological attitudes we are capable of constitute such a complex game of mutual interactions in which being obliged or being entitled consist in. And I am sure that Stephen Turner s book on Explaining the Normative would be a remarkable milestone in the collective argument leading to that conclusion. References Brandom, R. 1994. Making it Explicit. Cambridge, Mas.: Harvard University Press. Brandom, R. 2009. Between Saying and Doing: Towards an Analytic Pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Turner, S. P. 2010. Explaining the Normative, Cambridge: Polity Press. Zamora-Bonilla, J. P. 2006. Science as a Persuasion Game. Episteme, 2:189-201.