Qualia: A Defense. Brendan James Moore, MA, & Dr. Syed Adeel Ahmed

Similar documents
Corporate Activity, Social Responsibility, and Quining Moral Blameworthiness

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Realism and instrumentalism

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Metaphysics & Consciousness. A talk by Larry Muhlstein

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Chalmers says Too Hard ; Dennett says Too Easy

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation


Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Consciousness Without Awareness

Kant and his Successors

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

The Empirical Skepticism of David Hume. Dustin M. Sigsbee

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Machine Consciousness, Mind & Consciousness

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Experiences Don t Sum

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Common sense dictates that we can know external reality exists and that it is generally correctly perceived via our five senses

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Précis: Perplexities of Consciousness. for Philosophical Studies

Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment

Varieties of Apriority

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Man Has No Identical Self

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

PRIVILEGED ACCESS AND QUALIA

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Formative Assessment: 2 x 1,500 word essays First essay due 16:00 on Friday 30 October 2015 Second essay due: 16:00 on Friday 11 December 2015

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Stout s teleological theory of action

Skepticism and Internalism

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

DOES SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING SOLVE THE BOOTSTRAPPING PROBLEM?

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Cartesian Rationalism

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Thinking About Consciousness

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

GROUP A WESTERN PHILOSOPHY (40 marks)

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Transcription:

(IJAHSS) Volume 1 Issue 4 ǁ November 2016. www.ijahss.com Brendan James Moore, MA, & Dr. Syed Adeel Ahmed College of Continuing Studies, 800 E Commerce Rd., Tulane University, Elmwood, 70123, Louisiana, United States Xavier University of Louisiana, 1 Drexel Drive, New Orleans, 70125, Louisiana, United States Abstract In Daniel Dennett s Quining Qualia, 15 intuitional pumps are used to argue that qualia cannot be founded on four commonly assumed features. Dennett s aim is to eventually make anyone uncomfortable when trying to sensibly talk of qualia. We will go over Dennett s stance as well as several of the intuitional pumps he uses. We will reject that the considerations he raises does not give us reason to doubt that qualia is ineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible in consciousness. Moreover, by rejecting that Dennett s stance and intuition pumps gives us reason to doubt qualia in the pre-theoretical sense, we argue that we should not abandon sensible talk of qualia. Keywords: Philosophy of Mind, Dennett, Intuition Pump, Introspective Knowledge, Infallibilism, Epistemology I. Introduction In Daniel Dennett s Quining Qualia, 15 intuitional pumps are used to argue that qualia cannot be founded on four commonly assumed features. Qualia is simply the way things seem to us, and as a folk psychological, pre-theoretical, concept has the following four properties: being ineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible in consciousness [1; pp. 228-229]. Dennett s aim is to eventually make anyone uncomfortable when trying to sensibly talk of qualia. He states, I want to make it just as uncomfortable for anyone to talk of qualia-or "raw feels" or "phenomenal properties" or "subjective and intrinsic properties" or "the qualitative character" of experience [1; p. 227]. We will go over Dennett s stance as well as several of the intuitional pumps he uses. We will reject that the considerations he raises does not give us reason to doubt that qualia is ineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible in consciousness. Moreover, by rejecting that Dennett s stance and intuition pumps gives us reason to doubt qualia in the pre-theoretical sense, we argue that we should not abandon sensible talk of qualia. Afterwards, we address possible objections. Before describing Dennett s position in detail, we will first formalize Dennett s stance and how it differs from our own. Jonathan Simon accurately characterizes a formalized version of Dennett s argument in Quining Qualia the following way. Dennett is arguing as follows: 1) qualia (by definition) are: ineffable, intrinsic, private, and accessible to introspection 2) but no states have all of these features 3) therefore there are no qualia [4; p. 1]. In this paper, we will reject premise #2 and assume that we can intelligibly understand qualia as having the four features listed in premise #1. In doing so, we are then left with being unable to accept Dennett s conclusion (proposition #3). First, we will address Dennett s interpretation of intrinsic and how qualia can be understood as intrinsic in a differing sense. II. Intrinsic First, we will address Dennett s position that qualia are not intrinsic. He argues that properties that "seem intrinsic" at first often tum out on more careful analysis to be relational [1; p. 237]. One example he 15

gives is the experienced beer drinker intuitional pump #9. When someone first tastes beer, the experience of first tasting is unique and acquiring a taste for beer, Dennett argues, demonstrates that the way things seem to us is not intrinsic but is rather relational since it relies on how we interact with other, external, things. As Dennett puts, no one comes to enjoy the way the first sip tasted [1;p. 237]. Rather, when we notice that our reactions to other, external, things change over time, this gives us reason to assume qualia holds more of a relational, rather than intrinsic, property. Dennett s point is concisely stated as the following: For if it is admitted that one's attitudes towards, or reactions to, experiences are in any way and in any degree constitutive of their experiential qualities, so that a change in reactivity amounts to or guarantees a change in the property, then those properties, those "qualitative or phenomenal features," cease to be "intrinsic" properties, and in fact become paradigmatically extrinsic, relational properties [1; p. 237]. However, there are several reasons to reject the claim that changes in reactivity demonstrate that qualia are not intrinsic. First, one could simply divorce the notion of the way things seem to us from the external objects that may give rise to our phenomenological states. The fact that our different experiences change and vary over time, even when consuming the same chemical compounds that form a substance (in this case beer), indicate that how we view the world is intimately tied to internal processes. A second reason to reject the claim that changes in reactivity demonstrate that qualia are not intrinsic would be to adopt an alternative-interpretation of a Humean approach to personal identity. Concerning personal identity, David Hume would ask us to consider the following: For from what impression could this idea [of the self] be derived? This question it is impossible to answer without a manifest contradiction and absurdity [3;Treatise, Book I, Part IV, Sec. 6, p. 320]. For Hume, one interpretation of personal identity is that there is no personal identity, since we are always changing what we will call an error theory interpretation. Another alternate interpretation of Hume could be simply that we never have one single perception, since the eye always changes perceptions. Similarly, our identity is constantly changing, and it is simply wrong to ascribe an identity similar to numerical identity. These two interpretations of Humean personal identity drastically affect how meaningful we view the claim that qualia have intrinsic properties. The first interpretation of Hume as an error theorist would leave us with a pessimistic outlook on qualia having an intrinsic property. Hume may be pointing out that we make two mistakes in our talk of personal identity. Our first perceptional mistake is that our being is unchangeable through time. Then, we make a second mistake in creating a soul or something that is unchangeable or unknown, and that cannot possibly be known in order to justify our first mistake in perception. Basically, we invent something to cover up our philosophical mistake. The reason this is a mistake is that we are not able fully to satisfy ourselves in that particular [a self that is reducible to an impression] nor find anything invariable and uninterrupted to justify our notion of identity [3;Treatise, Book I, Part IV, Sec. 6, p. 321]. Adopting an alternative, non-error theorist, approach concerning Hume s stance on personal identity will leave qualia in a position where it can still be described as intrinsic. Even though we have multiple perceptions, what necessarily binds them to our identity? What Hume suggests is that Whatever changes he endures, his several parts are still connected by the relation of causation [3;Treatise, Book I, Part IV, Sec. 6.]. One idea will give rise to another where memory alone acquaints us to our own continuity. We have mental events and connectedness, and we may talk about this mental connectedness without referencing identity. Hume eventually finds talk of identity unintelligible in the absence of this connectedness that has been described above. All disputes concerning the identity of connected objects are 16

merely verbal, except so far as the relation of parts gives rise to some fiction or imaginary principle of union as we have already observed [3;Treatise, Book I, Part IV, Sec. 6., p. 325]. Under this interpretation, a kind of identity claim could be made, but only relating the connectedness of mental events. If intrinsic is understood as merely being essential and belonging to us naturally, then it seems reasonable to assume that qualia is intrinsic, since there would be nothing against holding an interactionist view of what gives rise to qualia, yet still holding that it both belongs and is essential to ourselves. Also, if our identity is merely an amalgam of time-sliced mental events, the claim that changes in our reactivity demonstrates the relational character of qualia becomes untenable. While Dennett might rightly show that objects internal to human bodies (the taste buds) and external objects (the beer) are both involved in creating qualia, he has not demonstrated that qualia (the way things seem to us) is not an intrinsic property. Dennett argues against qualia understood as being privately knowable. III. Privately Knowable A commonplace assumption is that our experience is private, and an infallibilist position would state that we could not be wrong or misdiscover qualia. Dennett characterizes the popular claim as stating, I know how it is with me right now [1; p. 233]. Dennett holds the stance that qualia are public (insofar as redness can be construed as a public property), and only private in a superficial sense. To the claim that qualia is private he states, But if absolutely nothing follows from this presumed knowledge what is the point of asserting that one has it? [1; p. 233]. He then supposes they must be fictions, since they fail to have empirical testability. There are many truths that humans cannot test due to limitations on our ability. For example, before the Hubble telescope, humans were unable to see extremely far distant planets. However, human limitations do not affect the truth of the matter of whether or not there were distant planets before Hubble telescopy 1. Just because nothing useful can come from knowing a particular fact does not mean that the particular fact cannot be understood in a way that constitute knowledge. Also, there might exist other methods than empirical that are worthwhile and might be used as a process to develop reasonable claims that are knowable. Descartes method of systematic doubt is a classic example of how he derived Cogito Ergo Sum in Meditations on First Philosophy. Descartes four laws, that he adhered to in Meditations on First Philosophy, were elaborated on in the beginning of Discourse on the Method, which we now call the Method of Systematic Doubt: 1. Never accept anything as true 2. Divide each of the difficulties into as many parts as possible. 3. Direct my thoughts in an orderly manner 4. Make enumerations so complete, review so comprehensive, that I could be sure of leaving nothing out [2; AT, VI, 19]. By following these steps, Descartes found that he could exhaust the ability to doubt something so thoroughly, as to render it necessarily or undoubtedly true. Dennett should not assume that empirical models are the only models that allow us to meaningfully claim knowledge. To address Dennett s point on what is the point of asserting that one has it? we would respond that the point of asserting something might be tied to an individual s motivational set. If someone cares about accurately representing reality, he or she will not be perturbed when particular facts seem irrelevant to everyday 1 Telescopy is the art of making telescopes. 17

survival (such as the privateness of the way things seem to us - qualia). Dennett argues against the direct and immediately knowableness of qualia. IV. Direct and Immediately Knowable Third, we will address Dennett s rejection of qualia as directly or immediately apprehensible in consciousness. Intuition pump #7 (the case of Chase and Sanborn) is an example where Dennett illustrates that a subject's "introspective" convictions about his or her own taste may generally be worse evidence than what outside observers can gather. Intuition pump #7: Chase and Sanborn Mr. Chase and Mr. Sanborn are coffee tasters, and after a long history of coffee tasting (for Maxwell House) they each grow to dislike the taste. However, their claims as to why they currently dislike the taste vary. Mr. Chase Says to Mr. Sanborn: I hate to admit it, but I'm not enjoying this work anymore. When I came to Maxwell House six years ago, I thought Maxwell House coffee was the best-tasting coffee in the world. I was proud to have a share in the responsibility for preserving that flavor over the years. And we've done our job well; the coffee tastes just the same today as it tasted when I arrived. But, you know, I no longer like it! My tastes have changed. I've become a more sophisticated coffee drinker. I no longer like that taste at all [1;p. 232]. However, Sanborn says to Chase: When I arrived here, shortly before you did, I, like you, thought Maxwell House coffee was tops in flavor. And now I, like you, really don't care for the coffee we're making. But my tastes haven't changed; my... tasters have changed. That is, I think something has gone wrong with my taste buds or some other part of my taste-analyzing perceptual machinery. Maxwell House coffee doesn't taste to me the way it used to taste; if only it did, I'd still love it, for I still think that taste is the best taste in coffee. Now I'm not saying we haven't done our job well. You other tasters all agree that the taste is the same, and I must admit that on a day-to- day basis I can detect no change either. So it must be my problem alone. I guess I'm no longer cut out for this work [1; p. 232]. All Dennett has shown is that a subject's "introspective" convictions lend no insight into the causal history that answers the question why the subject currently has the way it seems to him or her. However, nothing Dennett has said attacks the notion that each coffee taster knows his own qualia the way it seems to him. Indeed, Mr. Sanborn and Mr. Chase might be epistemically in the dark when it comes to questions about whether their taste buds have developed or the coffee blend has changed over time, or both. Dennett, in order to attack our commonsense notion of qualia, needs to show that either Chase or Sanborn cannot know their own immediate experience, not merely that they lack the details of its realization. He says, Chase's intuitive judgments about his qualia constancy are no better off, epistemically, than his intuitive judgments about, say, lighting intensity constancy or room temperature constancy- or his own body temperature constancy. Moving to a condition inside his body does not change the intimacy of the epistemic relation in any special way [1; p 236]. Room temperature does not have a strict, scientific, definition, since it relies on what humans are normally accustomed to, which may vary over time. In assuming that there is a set, definable, number of degrees Celsius to define room temperature in the same way defining a taste such as bitterness would have a corresponding taste bud activation Dennett is missing the defining, vague, element of a human s raw feeling on the subject. What a human is accustomed to depends on the way it seems to him or her, which is why we cannot assume a strict number with regard to room temperature and why we cannot assume a corresponding 18

measure to how coffee tastes to Chase or Sanborn. Dennett is right that Chase and Sanborn may be in the dark about certain epistemic features in how their qualitative experience arises, but he has failed to show that they are in the dark with regard to knowing the way things seem to them. Dennett argues against the ineffability of qualia. V. Qualia s Ineffability Finally, we should address Dennett s attack on the ineffability of qualia. Dennett states, But it would be a mistake to transform the fact that inevitably there is a limit to our capacity to describe things we experience into the supposition that there are absolutely indescribable properties in our experience [1; p. 244]. There are two ways to approach the assertion that there is an indescribable nature to the way things seem to us. The first, and harder to defend, is that the some properties that are currently indescribable will always be indescribable, regardless of whether our species capacities change over time. The second, more hopeful, characterization of the sentiment that some properties in our experience are indescribable is that the indescribability is merely an ephemeral, contextual problem, and perhaps what may limit our capacity to describe certain features will change with either a newly developed capacity or future physics. Dennett is right that we ought not to accept the position that current ineffability implies indefinite ineffability; however, he has not shown that we are warranted in abandoning talk of qualia nor shown that ineffability fails as a feature of qualia. VI. Objections and Responses Objection #1 We cannot rely on future physics as an adequate answer to qualia s ineffability. Concerning the ineffable quality of qualia, it is not enough to withhold our theoretical allegiances until the sunny day when the philosophers complete the tricky task of purifying the everyday concept of qualia [1; p. 238]. In other words, to simply settle for a concept as unknowable is unacceptable. Response to Objection #1 We do not mean to suggest that we should not pursue empirical routes to better understanding conscious experience; however, to assume that we should abandon talk of the intimate position we stand with respect to qualia seems unwarranted. Compared to the total duration of our human species existence, only recently have we made scientific advances in understanding the mental. We have also done so in ways that would be unfathomable to previous generations, such as fmri scans. In defending the commonplace concept of qualia, our aim is not to close off a particular way of understanding a phenomenon, especially a way of understanding a phenomenon that has served our species survival over an extremely long amount of time. Objection #2 The commonplace assumptions about qualia simply arose out of evolution by natural selection and random mutation, and there is no reason that beliefs that are selected for survivability are truth-tracking. Therefore, even if our pre-theoretic intuitions about qualia served a useful function in the past, we should still not cling onto talk of useful fictions and claim that they are true. 19

Response to Objection #2 While this is a good point, our claim in this paper is that Dennett has not shown us to have good reason in rejecting the four commonplace, assumed, features of qualia. If it were the case that there were evidence that qualia does not exist, then objection #2 would stand. However, Dennett s stance did not present sufficient justification to abandon talk of qualia, and because of this, we are not clinging to a useful fiction when qualia s fiction-hood is still in doubt. VII. Conclusion Overall, although Dennett uses a plethora of intuition pumps, he does not show that we have conclusive reasons to reject the concept of qualia as a pre-theoretical, folk psychological, concept. Understanding qualia as having the features of being ineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible in consciousness is still defensible. In rejecting that Dennett s stance and intuition pumps, we have reason to doubt qualia in the pre-theoretical sense. We have argued that we should not abandon sensible talk of qualia. REFERENCES [1] Dennett, Daniel, Quining Qualia, p. 226 from Chalmers, David, Philosophy of Mind, 2003. [2] Descartes, Discourse on the Method, 1637 from Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings, translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). [3] Hume, David, Treatise on Human Nature, 1739-1740 from Ariew, Roger; Watkins, Eric, Readings in Modern Philosophy: Volume II Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Associated Texts. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis/Cambridge, 2000. [4] Simon, Jon, personal communication: Further Comments on Dennett and Churchlands Philosophy of Mind course, Tulane University,November 12 th, 2013. Acknowledgements Thank you to Dr. Syed Adeel Ahmed, as well as Tulane University, for guidance and mentoring through the Business of Information Technology and Managing the IT Department courses in the Masters of Professional Studies program for Computing Technology. Also, thank you to the Tulane Philosophy Department and Ohio University Philosophy Department for helping cultivate a rich philosophic atmosphere. 20