If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

Similar documents
Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Multilateral Retributivism: Justifying Change Richard R. Eva

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

The Philosophy of Ethics as It Relates to Capital Punishment. Nicole Warkoski, Lynchburg College

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Justification Defenses in Situations of Unavoidable Uncertainty: A Reply to Professor Ferzan

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

MORAL RELATIVISM. By: George Bassilios St Antonius Coptic Orthodox Church, San Francisco Bay Area

CEDAR PARK CHRISTIAN SCHOOLS

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Pojman: What is Moral Philosophy?

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

Scanlon on Double Effect

v Pierre Lewis, Isaac Boateng, Jemmikai Orlebar Forbes & Rachel Kenehan the Crown Court Winchester March 2014 Sentencing remarks Justice Keith

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

TOPIC 27: MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

LAW04. Law and Morals. The Concepts of Law

The Role of Inconsistency in the Death of Socrates 1

AMERICAN LAW REGISTER.

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Pilate's Extended Dialogues in the Gospel of John: Did the Evangelist alter a written source?

A Non-Attribution- Dilemma and its Impact on Legal Regulation of Cyberwar

Doctrine of God. Immanuel Kant s Moral Argument

INNOCENCE LOST: A PROBLEM FOR PUNISHMENT AS DUTY

Jesus is Better My Goal is to Simplify a possibly very confusing passage in the Bible

SUBSTITUTE APPLICATION

Heritage Academy, 606 Ridgeway Avenue, Columbia, MO Phone: (573) Fax: (573)

Imprint. Excusing Mistakes of Law. Gideon Yaffe. Philosophers. University of Southern California

U.S. Bishops Revise Part Six of the Ethical and Religious Directives An Initial Analysis by CHA Ethicists 1

Introduction Paragraph 7 th /8 th grade expectation: 150+ words (includes the thesis)

Both Hollingsworth and Schroeder testified that as Branch Davidians, they thought that God's true believers were

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

EXECUTIVE SUMMARY: A Survey Highlighting Christian Perceptions on Criminal Justice

Excusing Mistakes of Law

PHIL 202: IV:

2014 Errata to 2013 Punishment Chart for North Carolina Crimes and Motor Vehicle Offenses

It is commonplace feature of our interpersonal lives that the beliefs we hold can,

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

AN ECCLESIASTICAL POLICY AND A PROCESS FOR REVIEW OF MINISTERIAL STANDING of the AMERICAN BAPTIST CHURCHES OF NEBRASKA PREAMBLE:

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Introduction. R.A. Duff *

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Argument Writing. Whooohoo!! Argument instruction is necessary * Argument comprehension is required in school assignments, standardized testing, job

Resolved: Connecticut should eliminate the death penalty.

When the New Yorker sent me... to report on the trial of Adolf Eichmann, I assumed... that a courtroom had only one interestto fulfill the demands of

Before the Court House

SOCCER COACH APPLICATION PLEASE WORD PROCESS OR HAND WRITE AND SEND THE COMPLETED APPLICATION. YOUR

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Option one: Catchment area Option two: The nearest school rule

Veritas Classical Christian Academy Faculty Application

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Center on Wrongful Convictions

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

UNIVERSAL PERIODIC REVIEW JOINT SUBMISSION 2018

Lesson Plans 12: Argument and Piety in the Euthyphro e Civic Knowledge Project: Winning Words

Reflections on Xunzi. Han-Han Yang, Emory University

Session 26 Applbaum, Professional Detachment: The Executioner of Paris

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Guidelines for Handling Abuse Allegations against a Church Leader. A. Why a Procedure for Handling Abuse Allegations Is Necessary

15.2 SAFE MINISTRY WITH PERSONS WHO HAVE BEEN CONVICTED OF A SEXUAL OFFENCE OR ARE THE SUBJECT OF A NEGATIVE FINDING

Salvation: The Cross. Excerpts from Why the Cross by Jerry Bridges

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

The Scarlet Letter: What happens when a private sin becomes a public crime?

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

1 Ted Kirnbauer Galatians 2: /25/14

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

There Are No Little Sins No. 196

LUTHER S SMALL CATECHISM

God s Boundary Stones Part 2 Glenn Smith, April 2013, Ahava B Shem Yeshua

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE

Who is in Authority? Scripture Text: Romans 13:1-7

GOD S JUSTICE IN JESUS CHRIST Romans 3:19-28; Reformation; October 27-28, 2018

BIBLICAL SOTERIOLOGY An Overview and Defense of the Reformed Doctrines of Salvation Limited Atonement, part 18. by Ra McLaughlin

Building Your Framework everydaydebate.blogspot.com by James M. Kellams

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Calvary Chapel Costa Mesa Children s Ministry. Leading a Child to Christ

CAPITAL PUNISHMENT Text: Exodus 20:13; Numbers 35:30-31

Argument Mapping. Table of Contents. By James Wallace Gray 2/13/2012

First of all, the question implies the word loving to mean only giving pleasant things to those who are loved.

Lancaster County Christian School Application for Teaching Positions

The question before us this morning is the greatest of all questions. It s the Philippian Jailer question. What must I do to be saved?

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

The Expository Study of Romans

NON-TEACHING EMPLOYMENT APPLICATION. Position Desired: Schedule Desired: Full-Time Part-Time Substitute Secondary Position Desired:

FALL2010: PHI7550 FINAL EXAM PART III

Transcription:

27 If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman Abstract: I argue that the But Everyone Does That (BEDT) defense can have significant exculpatory force in a legal sense, but not a moral sense. I consider whether legal realism is a better theory of the law than the more orthodox view of respecting the law as it is written. I next examine what the purpose of the law is, especially attending to how widespread disobedience is treated. Finally, I attempt to fit BEDT within Paul Robinson s framework for categorizing defenses. I conclude that, first, BEDT can have significant exculpatory force; second, a BEDT plea does not comport with either Robinson s definition of an excuse or other commonly held conceptions and so needs its own classification; and finally, BEDT does not exonerate the offender in a moral sense only in a legal context. Two competing views about the nature of the law underlie the debate about whether the BEDT plea has any exculpatory significance at all. On the orthodox view, the law is what is written in the official statutes of a particular society or community. If one wants to know how fast one can go on a particular road, whether one is allowed to steal from one s neighbor, or what the legal drinking age is, one need only consult one s corpus of laws. Violating any of these rules constitutes a breach of the law, for which one is culpable and liable to be punished by the criminal justice system. Even if a person P joins most members of her community in breaking the written law, she is just as liable to be punished and is just as blameworthy as she would be were she the only person who transgressed. This would remain true even if those in charge of enforcing the law in question broke that law as well. A legal realist conception of the law is entirely different. On this view, the written law is meaningless vis-à-vis determining what the law actually is. Instead, P should consult judges decisions and the actions of law enforcement officials to figure out what she actually can and cannot do. If the statute on the books sets the speed limit on a particular road at thirty-five miles per hour, but people are only forced to pay speeding tickets when they exceed forty-five miles per hour, then the speed limit is really forty-five miles per hour. The

28 Stance Volume 9 April 2016 written law thus has no intrinsic meaning; it is merely ink on paper. What matters is what people are actually allowed to do, not what an official text says they are allowed to do. Which of these views is correct depends largely upon what the purpose of law is. If it is true that law is meant to set absolute and objective standards for permitted and prohibited actions, then these standards cannot lose their force over time. If the people who make law are accepted as infallible, then the orthodox view is probably correct. But this is not, in fact, how people and the legal system actually operate. Law fundamentally exists to ensure and promote standards of conduct that society wants. A community could formalize its desire to prohibit driving at any speed over ten miles per hour by establishing it as a law and using this statute as a tool to prosecute people who drive faster than this speed. If the community later decided that it wanted to keep people from going faster than thirty miles per hour, it could either change the written law or simply stop prosecuting people who did not obey this threshold. Writing an amendment to the law and prosecuting people in accordance with this amendment would be much more effective, since it would both clearly inform community members what is expected of them, and apply punishment in a manner consistent with these expectations. But both the realist and orthodox methods of changing the law intend to enforce the community s will through legal means, and both, properly enforced, have the same effect. Thus, the fact that a law is written in a certain way does not preclude people from rejecting it through disobedience. A law cannot have any force if it bans conduct for which the actor is not deemed worthy of blame by a significant portion of the community. Jaywalking, to use a common example, is illegal in New York City. But any native New Yorker knows that it is perfectly acceptable to jaywalk in the city, and it is even common for pedestrians to do so directly in front of police officers without being punished. If person P gets prosecuted for jaywalking in New York City, she would likely feel aggrieved and claim that she was wronged because everyone does that. This is a perfectly valid plea. While P did technically break the law, she did not effectively break the law. In other words, she acted wrongly according to the criminal statute on the books, but not according to the majority of people in her community. What intrinsic or instrumental value is there, then, in prosecuting P? If the other members of her community have plainly demonstrated that they do not want to prohibit the sort of conduct for which she is being prosecuted, then her prosecution is

Charlie Melman, If Everyone Does It 29 instrumentally unjustifiable. The law, as written, has ceased to serve its purpose. Since its purpose is to reflect and promote the standards of conduct that the community wants, it only has instrumental value. 1 P will rightly feel that she is being discriminated against, for her conduct alone does not provide a good enough reason for the state to prosecute her. In the context in which she acted, she is not blameworthy. 2 One may wonder exactly when P ceases to be liable for prosecution. What proportion of the population needs to disobey the written law for the BEDT plea to have significant exculpatory force? Douglas Husak notes that when P asserts BEDT, P does not claim that literally everyone in her community would do what she did if put in the same circumstances. 3 Rather, she asserts that the average person and most people would do the same thing in the same situation. 4 While this is the strongest and most easily defended formulation of BEDT, it is not the only one that works. It is difficult to draw a bright line that defines what proportion of people have to consider a written law invalid for the BEDT plea to have exculpatory significance. But there does not seem to be anything inherently special about the fifty percent threshold. Surely no one would consider a law very effective or forceful if, say, fortyfive percent of community members routinely violated it and did not believe themselves worthy of punishment. It is thus better to say that the exculpatory force of the BEDT plea admits of degrees. If, for example, P violated a written law that was commonly disobeyed by twenty percent of people in her community, a judge should still convict her if BEDT was her only defense but consider it as a mitigating factor in determining her quantum of punishment. Fifty percent is a useful threshold for determining whether BEDT should totally exculpate because past this point we can say that most people would do the thing in question. However, it seems difficult to justify punishing P for an action that is technically illegal but slightly less than half the people in her community commit anyway. It is 1 The only law that can have intrinsic value is a moral law, or a law given by God, if either of these exists. Thus, the sort of law with which we are concerned here can only reflect these intrinsically valuable laws. Even if they did, they would only be instrumentally valuable insofar as they enforced these moral laws. 2 As Husak notes, the force of the BEDT plea depends significantly on the community in which the action in question was done. If P jaywalked in a community that made jaywalking illegal through written law and adhered to this law, P would be blameworthy and liable for prosecution. Douglas Husak, The But-Everyone-Does-That! Defense, Public Affairs Quarterly 10, no. 4 (October 1996): 309. 3 Ibid. 4 Ibid.

30 Stance Volume 9 April 2016 impossible to avoid disputes about the importance of various levels of disobedience, and when there is enough of it for the BEDT plea to work by itself, but that does not mean that we should dismiss the importance of BEDT altogether. A most or nothing approach seems too analytically facile. When might someone reasonably be able to claim BEDT? Husak mentions several instances in which people are punished for behaving, or not behaving, as others would have if put in the same situation: negligence (how do we determine what constitutes a significant deviation from a standard of care that a reasonable person would observe? ) and duress ( but everyone would have aided the robber s escape if a gun was put to their head! ) are two particularly persuasive examples. 5 However, we should also consider laws that draw clear distinctions between what is legal and what is illegal. Salient examples include speeding, underage drinking, jaywalking, drunk driving, and trespassing. It is very easy to determine if a person is guilty of one of these crimes by consulting the written law. The legal drinking age is twenty-one, the speed limit is thirty-five miles per hour, the boundaries of the crosswalk are painted on the street, one cannot have a blood alcohol content of over 0.08, etc. These cases are particularly useful for illustrating how one can violate the written law and still be exculpated. Husak does not consider these offenses as a category, but they seem to elicit the BEDT plea most often in the real world. BEDT tends to be more applicable when it is relatively easy to determine whether a crime has been committed than in cases where the exact conditions of an individual incident are more difficult to specify. Determining whether the average community member would also have violated the written law in the same situation is necessary for evaluating BEDT s exculpatory significance, and this is possible only when we know what the accused is supposed to have done. If BEDT is a valid defense, what type of defense is it? Among others, Paul Robinson enumerates justification and excuse defenses. 6 BEDT can only be a Justification if the written law is flawed, such that P s following the law in the given circumstance does not prevent a greater harm than would be realized by not following the law. This is usually not the case in many of the situations in which BEDT is applied. The world is not better for P having jaywalked or exceeded the speed limit; in fact, it is usually better, ceteris paribus, for people to drive slower and walk within the crosswalk at designated 5 Ibid., 311. 6 Robinson, Criminal Law Defenses, Columbia Law Review 82 (1982): 221.

Charlie Melman, If Everyone Does It 31 times. In short, these two laws generally serve a clear purpose. But the value of the law in question does not matter vis-à-vis P s guilt or innocence based on the BEDT plea. What matters is whether P s act comported with her community s accepted standard of action in her particular circumstance. Thus, in pleading BEDT, P makes no claim about the instrumental benefit of her action. If BEDT is an excuse, then P acknowledges that her action was wrong and, in making the BEDT plea, asserts that she has a condition that absolves her of responsibility for her action. While BEDT seems to fit this definition more closely than it fits the definition of a justification, it does not work if we assume that P acts with full agency and knowledge of the law. I propose a special exception to Robinson s definition of an excuse for the BEDT plea. If P pleads BEDT, she asserts not that there is a quality about her that makes her not responsible for her action, but that there is a feature of the community in which she acted that absolves her of legal culpability for her action. That quality is the disobedience of a substantial portion of her fellow community members in the same circumstances, viz., the fact that everyone does that. Assuming that P s claim is true, she can justifiably claim that she would be discriminated against if convicted and the law, as written, has no force. The BEDT plea will not satisfy moral philosophers who rightly worry about groupthink determining what is permissible and impermissible in a society. It could, in theory, enable a majority to discriminate against a minority. For example, many, if not most Hutus, would have killed their Tutsi neighbors during the Rwandan genocide regardless of Rwanda s laws regarding murder or hate crimes. The BEDT plea says nothing about what we ought to do; rather, it endorses a particular method of determining whether disobeying the written law makes one liable to criminal prosecution, and if so, what quantum of punishment one deserves. Thus, it is entirely possible for a community to let flagrantly immoral actions go unpunished. That does not, however, reduce the BEDT plea s exculpatory significance in a legal context. Judges should take it seriously, and consider it as a mitigating factor during sentencing if it does not have enough force to fully exonerate the alleged wrongdoer. 7 7 I owe thanks to Professor Douglas Husak for helping me hone my understanding of many of the ideas discussed in this paper.