A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen

Similar documents
Informalizing Formal Logic

Circularity in ethotic structures

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

1/9. The First Analogy

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

I. In the ongoing debate on the meaning of logical connectives 1, two families of

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

The Dialectical Tier of Mathematical Proof

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Writing Your Doctoral Thesis with Word This document is an example of what you can do with the POLITO Template

3. Knowledge and Justification

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

What is a counterexample?

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Introduction. September 30, 2011

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

A normative account of defeasible and probabilistic inference

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Proof as a cluster concept in mathematical practice. Keith Weber Rutgers University

Kant and his Successors

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

SPRING 2014 UNDERGRADUATE COURSE OFFERINGS

Symbolic Logic Prof. Chhanda Chakraborti Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

ELA CCSS Grade Five. Fifth Grade Reading Standards for Literature (RL)

Combining Pricean and Peircean Pragmatism. Henrik Rydenfelt

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

5 A Modal Version of the

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Philosophy Pathways Issue nd October

Objections, Rebuttals and Refutations

The British Empiricism

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

A Priori Bootstrapping

The Problem of the External World

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

On Freeman s Argument Structure Approach

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

The Problem of Logical Omniscience, the Preface Paradox, and Doxastic Commitments

Judging Coherence in the Argumentative Situation. Things are coherent if they stick together, are connected in a specific way, and are consistent in

Introduction to Philosophy

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

1/8. The Third Analogy

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective

Some Pragmatic Themes in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

Introduction to Philosophy

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Argumentation without arguments. Henry Prakken

Descartes Method of Doubt

Presuppositional Apologetics

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

ELA CCSS Grade Three. Third Grade Reading Standards for Literature (RL)

Transcription:

A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen 1

Introduction In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? But does logic really have a normative import at all? If yes, is thought specifically within the remit of logic s normative grip? Or perhaps something else? Proposal: logic is originally a normative theory of specific dialogical practices, but with applications for scientific inquiry in mono-agent situations. 2

Introduction In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? But does logic really have a normative import at all? If yes, is thought specifically within the remit of logic s normative grip? Or perhaps something else? Proposal: logic is originally a normative theory of specific dialogical practices, but with applications for scientific inquiry in mono-agent situations. 3

Introduction In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? But does logic really have a normative import at all? If yes, is thought specifically within the remit of logic s normative grip? Or perhaps something else? Proposal: logic is originally a normative theory of specific dialogical practices, but with applications for scientific inquiry in mono-agent situations. 4

Introduction In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? But does logic really have a normative import at all? If yes, is thought specifically within the remit of logic s normative grip? Or perhaps something else? Proposal: logic is originally a normative theory of specific dialogical practices, but with applications for scientific inquiry in mono-agent situations. 5

Plan of the talk 1- Brief recap of the debate 2- The forgotten dialogical origins of logic 3- The built-in component conception of deduction 4- Back to the normativity of logic 6

Brief recap of the debate 7

The contenders Traditional view: logic is the science of correct reasoning => correct thinking Kant, Frege, dictionaries, textbooks. - Laws of logic as laws of truth. Harman (1986): logic has no more of a connection to rationality than any other important discipline. - Logic is the science of truth-preserving forms of arguments. Newcomers : MacFarlane, Field, Milne. 8

The contenders Traditional view: logic is the science of correct reasoning => correct thinking Kant, Frege, dictionaries, textbooks. - Laws of logic as laws of truth. Harman (1986): logic has no more of a connection to rationality than any other important discipline. - Logic is the science of truth-preserving forms of arguments. Newcomers : MacFarlane, Field, Milne. 9

The contenders Traditional view: logic is the science of correct reasoning => correct thinking Kant, Frege, dictionaries, textbooks. - Laws of logic as laws of truth. Harman (1986): logic has no more of a connection to rationality than any other important discipline. - Logic is the science of truth-preserving forms of arguments. Newcomers : MacFarlane, Field, Milne. 10

The contenders Traditional view: logic is the science of correct reasoning => correct thinking Kant, Frege, dictionaries, textbooks. - Laws of logic as laws of truth. Harman (1986): logic has no more of a connection to rationality than any other important discipline. - Logic is the science of truth-preserving forms of arguments. Newcomers : MacFarlane, Field, Milne. 11

The contenders Traditional view: logic is the science of correct reasoning => correct thinking Kant, Frege, dictionaries, textbooks. - Laws of logic as laws of truth. Harman (1986): logic has no more of a connection to rationality than any other important discipline. - Logic is the science of truth-preserving forms of arguments. Newcomers : MacFarlane, Field, Milne. 12

But what do we mean by logic? There are many logics available in the market: classical, relevant, defeasible etc. A weakness in the debate: logic is used as if it was a sufficiently homogeneous generic term. What is under discussion is the property of necessary truth-preservation, which underpins some but not all logical systems. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary and sufficient for validity => classical logic. 13

But what do we mean by logic? There are many logics available in the market: classical, relevant, defeasible etc. A weakness in the debate: logic is used as if it was a sufficiently homogeneous generic term. What is under discussion is the property of necessary truth-preservation, which underpins some but not all logical systems. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary and sufficient for validity => classical logic. 14

But what do we mean by logic? There are many logics available in the market: classical, relevant, defeasible etc. A weakness in the debate: logic is used as if it was a sufficiently homogeneous generic term. What is under discussion is the property of necessary truth-preservation, which underpins some but not all logical systems. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary and sufficient for validity => classical logic. 15

But what do we mean by logic? There are many logics available in the market: classical, relevant, defeasible etc. A weakness in the debate: logic is used as if it was a sufficiently homogeneous generic term. What is under discussion is the property of necessary truth-preservation, which underpins some but not all logical systems. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary and sufficient for validity => classical logic. 16

Bridge principles (MacFarlane 2004) If A, B => C, then (normative claim about believing A, B, and C). Variations: type of deontic operator, polarity, scope. Wr+ you have reason to see to it that if you believe A and you believe B, you believe C. Seemingly, an uncontroversial bridge principle has yet to be formulated. Should we go probabilistic? But would it really change the terms of the debate? 17

Bridge principles (MacFarlane 2004) If A, B => C, then (normative claim about believing A, B, and C). Variations: type of deontic operator, polarity, scope. Wr+ you have reason to see to it that if you believe A and you believe B, you believe C. Seemingly, an uncontroversial bridge principle has yet to be formulated. Should we go probabilistic? But would it really change the terms of the debate? 18

Bridge principles (MacFarlane 2004) If A, B => C, then (normative claim about believing A, B, and C). Variations: type of deontic operator, polarity, scope. Wr+ you have reason to see to it that if you believe A and you believe B, you believe C. Seemingly, an uncontroversial bridge principle has yet to be formulated. Should we go probabilistic? But would it really change the terms of the debate? 19

Bridge principles (MacFarlane 2004) If A, B => C, then (normative claim about believing A, B, and C). Variations: type of deontic operator, polarity, scope. Wr+ you have reason to see to it that if you believe A and you believe B, you believe C. Seemingly, an uncontroversial bridge principle has yet to be formulated. Should we go probabilistic? But would it really change the terms of the debate? 20

Bridge principles (MacFarlane 2004) If A, B => C, then (normative claim about believing A, B, and C). Variations: type of deontic operator, polarity, scope. Wr+ you have reason to see to it that if you believe A and you believe B, you believe C. Seemingly, an uncontroversial bridge principle has yet to be formulated. Should we go probabilistic? But would it really change the terms of the debate? 21

Milne on assertion (2009) Milne is the only one who approaches the issue with a detour via assertion (public sphere). He then wants to make his way back to belief, but ends up with a rather confusing discussion. Amongst the conventions governing assertion one stands out dramatically for present purposes: that one stands by the logical consequences of what one asserts. Brandom s GOGAR: one is committed (obligated) to the consequences of one s assertions. 22

Milne on assertion (2009) Milne is the only one who approaches the issue with a detour via assertion (public sphere). He then wants to make his way back to belief, but ends up with a rather confusing discussion. Amongst the conventions governing assertion one stands out dramatically for present purposes: that one stands by the logical consequences of what one asserts. Brandom s GOGAR: one is committed (obligated) to the consequences of one s assertions. 23

Milne on assertion (2009) Milne is the only one who approaches the issue with a detour via assertion (public sphere). He then wants to make his way back to belief, but ends up with a rather confusing discussion. Amongst the conventions governing assertion one stands out dramatically for present purposes: that one stands by the logical consequences of what one asserts. Brandom s GOGAR: one is committed (obligated) to the consequences of one s assertions. 24

Milne on assertion (2009) Milne is the only one who approaches the issue with a detour via assertion (public sphere). He then wants to make his way back to belief, but ends up with a rather confusing discussion. Amongst the conventions governing assertion one stands out dramatically for present purposes: that one stands by the logical consequences of what one asserts. Brandom s GOGAR: one is committed (obligated) to the consequences of one s assertions. 25

The forgotten dialogical origins of logic 26

The dialogical origins of logic Background: dialectical practices in the early Academy (Marion & Castelnerac 2009) Aristotle s older logical texts (Topics and Sophistical Refutations) are explicitly about debating. Syllogistic is less obviously about debating, but: A deduction is a discourse Latin Middle Ages: logica = dialectica Domingo de Soto (16 th century): Dialectic is the art or science of disputing. 27

The dialogical origins of logic Background: dialectical practices in the early Academy (Marion & Castelnerac 2009) Aristotle s older logical texts (Topics and Sophistical Refutations) are explicitly about debating. Syllogistic is less obviously about debating, but: A deduction is a discourse Latin Middle Ages: logica = dialectica Domingo de Soto (16 th century): Dialectic is the art or science of disputing. 28

The dialogical origins of logic Background: dialectical practices in the early Academy (Marion & Castelnerac 2009) Aristotle s older logical texts (Topics and Sophistical Refutations) are explicitly about debating. Syllogistic is less obviously about debating, but: A deduction is a discourse Latin Middle Ages: logica = dialectica Domingo de Soto (16 th century): Dialectic is the art or science of disputing. 29

The dialogical origins of logic Background: dialectical practices in the early Academy (Marion & Castelnerac 2009) Aristotle s older logical texts (Topics and Sophistical Refutations) are explicitly about debating. Syllogistic is less obviously about debating, but: A deduction is a discourse Latin Middle Ages: logica = dialectica Domingo de Soto (16 th century): Dialectic is the art or science of disputing. 30

The dialogical origins of logic Background: dialectical practices in the early Academy (Marion & Castelnerac 2009) Aristotle s older logical texts (Topics and Sophistical Refutations) are explicitly about debating. Syllogistic is less obviously about debating, but: A deduction is a discourse Latin Middle Ages: logica = dialectica Domingo de Soto (16 th century): Dialectic is the art or science of disputing. 31

The birth of deduction in Greek mathematics Greek mathematics reflects the importance of persuasion. It reflects the role of orality, in the use of formulae, in the structure of proofs But this orality is regimented into a written form, where vocabulary is limited, presentations follow a relatively rigid pattern It is at once oral and written (Netz 1999, 297/8) The deductive method emerged as an approach to argumentation (against e.g. Sophists). A proof is and isn t a dialogue: a hybrid entity between orality and writing. 32

The birth of deduction in Greek mathematics Greek mathematics reflects the importance of persuasion. It reflects the role of orality, in the use of formulae, in the structure of proofs But this orality is regimented into a written form, where vocabulary is limited, presentations follow a relatively rigid pattern It is at once oral and written (Netz 1999, 297/8) The deductive method emerged as an approach to argumentation (against e.g. Sophists). A proof is and isn t a dialogue: a hybrid entity between orality and writing. 33

The birth of deduction in Greek mathematics Greek mathematics reflects the importance of persuasion. It reflects the role of orality, in the use of formulae, in the structure of proofs But this orality is regimented into a written form, where vocabulary is limited, presentations follow a relatively rigid pattern It is at once oral and written (Netz 1999, 297/8) The deductive method emerged as an approach to argumentation (against e.g. Sophists). A proof is and isn t a dialogue: a hybrid entity between orality and writing. 34

When logic abandoned its dialogical origins After that, he should study logic. I do not mean the logic of the Schools, for this is strictly speaking nothing but a dialectic which teaches ways of expounding to others what one already knows or even of holding forth without judgment about things one does not know. Such logic corrupts good sense rather than increasing it. I mean instead the kind of logic which teaches us to direct our reason with a view to discovering the truths of which we are ignorant. (Preface to French edition of the Principles, in (Descartes 1988, 186)) 35

Kant and the internalization of logic The idea of logic as pertaining to thinking rather than arguing culminated in Kant. He takes as his starting point the transcendental question, what are the a priori conditions for the representations of objects in general?, and reconfigures the logic of his time for the transcendental project. He modifies the notions of judgment, form, and categories, and uses them to describe the very conditions of possibility of our thinking and perceiving. 36

Kant and the internalization of logic The idea of logic as pertaining to thinking rather than arguing culminated in Kant. He takes as his starting point the transcendental question, what are the a priori conditions for the representations of objects in general?, and reconfigures the logic of his time for the transcendental project. He modifies the notions of judgment, form, and categories, and uses them to describe the very conditions of possibility of our thinking and perceiving. 37

Kant and the internalization of logic The idea of logic as pertaining to thinking rather than arguing culminated in Kant. He takes as his starting point the transcendental question, what are the a priori conditions for the representations of objects in general?, and reconfigures the logic of his time for the transcendental project. He modifies the notions of judgment, form, and categories, and uses them to describe the very conditions of possibility of our thinking and perceiving. 38

Kant and the internalization of logic The concept of judgment, for example, traditionally a linguistic concept, is transformed into the mental act of the understanding for the apperception of objects. (General) logic deals with absolutely necessary rules of thought without which there can be no employment whatsoever of the understanding. (KrV: A52/B76) The laws of general logic are without content and merely formal ; general logic... abstracts from all content of knowledge... and... treats of the form of thought in general. (KrV: A152/B19) 39

Kant and the internalization of logic The concept of judgment, for example, traditionally a linguistic concept, is transformed into the mental act of the understanding for the apperception of objects. (General) logic deals with absolutely necessary rules of thought without which there can be no employment whatsoever of the understanding. (KrV: A52/B76) The laws of general logic are without content and merely formal ; general logic... abstracts from all content of knowledge... and... treats of the form of thought in general. (KrV: A152/B19) 40

Kant and the internalization of logic The concept of judgment, for example, traditionally a linguistic concept, is transformed into the mental act of the understanding for the apperception of objects. (General) logic deals with absolutely necessary rules of thought without which there can be no employment whatsoever of the understanding. (KrV: A52/B76) The laws of general logic are without content and merely formal ; general logic... abstracts from all content of knowledge... and... treats of the form of thought in general. (KrV: A152/B19) 41

The built-in opponent conception of deduction 42

A long quote Logic originated as a model of what we might call adversarial communication at least in a technical sense of adversarial. What follows in deduction is anything that is true in all interpretations of the premises that is the definition of logically valid inference. Our job, as speaker or hearer of a discourse that purports to be a deduction, is to test the drawing of inferences to destruction, to ensure that what is inferred is true in all models of the premises, not just the intended one. It is in this technical sense that logic models adversarial discourse. We may actually be socially cooperating in testing a deduction for validity [ ], but there is a core of seeking out all possible assignments of things, not simply finding one intended one. This is perhaps not accidentally related to the fact that logic arose as a model of legal and political debate. (Stenning 2002, 138) 43

Deduction as a dialogical notion Proofs as adversarial dialogues of a special kind. The participants have opposite goals: - Proponent: establishing the conclusion. - Opponent: blocking the establishment of the conclusion. The dialogue starts with mutually accepted statements (premises), and proceeds in successive argumentative (inferential) steps. The property of monotonicity can be explained in terms of the concept of a winning strategy. 44

Deduction as a dialogical notion Proofs as adversarial dialogues of a special kind. The participants have opposite goals: - Proponent: establishing the conclusion. - Opponent: blocking the establishment of the conclusion. The dialogue starts with mutually accepted statements (premises), and proceeds in successive argumentative (inferential) steps. The property of monotonicity can be explained in terms of the concept of a winning strategy. 45

Deduction as a dialogical notion Proofs as adversarial dialogues of a special kind. The participants have opposite goals: - Proponent: establishing the conclusion. - Opponent: blocking the establishment of the conclusion. The dialogue starts with mutually accepted statements (premises), and proceeds in successive argumentative (inferential) steps. The property of monotonicity can be explained in terms of the concept of a winning strategy. 46

Deduction as a dialogical notion Proofs as adversarial dialogues of a special kind. The participants have opposite goals: - Proponent: establishing the conclusion. - Opponent: blocking the establishment of the conclusion. The dialogue starts with mutually accepted statements (premises), and proceeds in successive argumentative (inferential) steps. The property of monotonicity can be explained in terms of the concept of a winning strategy. 47

Deduction as a dialogical notion Proofs as adversarial dialogues of a special kind. The participants have opposite goals: - Proponent: establishing the conclusion. - Opponent: blocking the establishment of the conclusion. The dialogue starts with mutually accepted statements (premises), and proceeds in successive argumentative (inferential) steps. The property of monotonicity can be explained in terms of the concept of a winning strategy. 48

Indefeasibility and necessary truth-preservation A winning strategy for proponent consists in a sequence of inferential steps to which there are no counterexamples: indefeasible steps. No matter what external information an ideal opponent brings in, in a winning strategy it will not defeat the individual inferential steps. Validity come what may as strategic component. Thus, necessary truth-preservation can be accounted for in terms of indefeasibility. 49

Indefeasibility and necessary truth-preservation A winning strategy for proponent consists in a sequence of inferential steps to which there are no counterexamples: indefeasible steps. No matter what external information an ideal opponent brings in, in a winning strategy it will not defeat the individual inferential steps. Validity come what may as strategic component. Thus, necessary truth-preservation can be accounted for in terms of indefeasibility. 50

Indefeasibility and necessary truth-preservation A winning strategy for proponent consists in a sequence of inferential steps to which there are no counterexamples: indefeasible steps. No matter what external information an ideal opponent brings in, in a winning strategy it will not defeat the individual inferential steps. Validity come what may as strategic component. Thus, necessary truth-preservation can be accounted for in terms of indefeasibility. 51

Indefeasibility and necessary truth-preservation A winning strategy for proponent consists in a sequence of inferential steps to which there are no counterexamples: indefeasible steps. No matter what external information an ideal opponent brings in, in a winning strategy it will not defeat the individual inferential steps. Validity come what may as strategic component. Thus, necessary truth-preservation can be accounted for in terms of indefeasibility. 52

The built-in opponent (BIO) conception The role of opponent is to look for counterexamples, i.e. situations where the premises hold but the conclusion (of each individual step) does not. But the deductive method has internalized opponent: every inferential step must be immune to counterexamples. The strategic goal of formulating indefeasible arguments becomes a constitutive feature of the method itself: necessary truth-preservation. No need for an active opponent, once the strategic desideratum becomes a constitutive feature. 53

The built-in opponent (BIO) conception The role of opponent is to look for counterexamples, i.e. situations where the premises hold but the conclusion (of each individual step) does not. But the deductive method has internalized opponent: every inferential step must be immune to counterexamples. The strategic goal of formulating indefeasible arguments becomes a constitutive feature of the method itself: necessary truth-preservation. No need for an active opponent, once the strategic desideratum becomes a constitutive feature. 54

The built-in opponent (BIO) conception The role of opponent is to look for counterexamples, i.e. situations where the premises hold but the conclusion (of each individual step) does not. But the deductive method has internalized opponent: every inferential step must be immune to counterexamples. The strategic goal of formulating indefeasible arguments becomes a constitutive feature of the method itself: necessary truth-preservation. No need for an active opponent, once the strategic desideratum becomes a constitutive feature. 55

The built-in opponent (BIO) conception The role of opponent is to look for counterexamples, i.e. situations where the premises hold but the conclusion (of each individual step) does not. But the deductive method has internalized opponent: every inferential step must be immune to counterexamples. The strategic goal of formulating indefeasible arguments becomes a constitutive feature of the method itself: necessary truth-preservation. No need for an active opponent, once the strategic desideratum becomes a constitutive feature. 56

The BIO conception of proofs as hybrid entities The conception of a (deductive) proof emerged against the background of certain dialogical practices, but it was then modified and regimented. The opponent has been internalized by the proof method, no longer playing the same active role. (The roles were asymmetric all along.) A proof reveals its dialogical origins in the properties of necessary truth-preservation and monotonicity, but it is no longer a dialogue with two active participants. 57

The BIO conception of proofs as hybrid entities The conception of a (deductive) proof emerged against the background of certain dialogical practices, but it was then modified and regimented. The opponent has been internalized by the proof method, no longer playing the same active role. (The roles were asymmetric all along.) A proof reveals its dialogical origins in the properties of necessary truth-preservation and monotonicity, but it is no longer a dialogue with two active participants. 58

The BIO conception of proofs as hybrid entities The conception of a (deductive) proof emerged against the background of certain dialogical practices, but it was then modified and regimented. The opponent has been internalized by the proof method, no longer playing the same active role. (The roles were asymmetric all along.) A proof reveals its dialogical origins in the properties of necessary truth-preservation and monotonicity, but it is no longer a dialogue with two active participants. 59

The BIO conception of proofs as hybrid entities The conception of a (deductive) proof emerged against the background of certain dialogical practices, but it was then modified and regimented. The opponent has been internalized by the proof method, no longer playing the same active role. (The roles were asymmetric all along.) A proof reveals its dialogical origins in the properties of necessary truth-preservation and monotonicity, but it is no longer a dialogue with two active participants. 60

Back to the normativity of logic 61

Necessary truth-preservation and belief management Necessary truth-preservation is prima facie not a reasonable norm for the management of one s beliefs. Harman s arguments: mind-cluttering, logical omniscience etc. A few more: deductive reasoning is - costly: a lot of input for little output. - inefficient: usually, available information underdetermines deductive conclusion. 62

Necessary truth-preservation and belief management Necessary truth-preservation is prima facie not a reasonable norm for the management of one s beliefs. Harman s arguments: mind-cluttering, logical omniscience etc. A few more: deductive reasoning is - costly: a lot of input for little output. - inefficient: usually, available information underdetermines deductive conclusion. 63

Necessary truth-preservation and belief management Necessary truth-preservation is prima facie not a reasonable norm for the management of one s beliefs. Harman s arguments: mind-cluttering, logical omniscience etc. A few more: deductive reasoning is - costly: a lot of input for little output. - inefficient: usually, available information underdetermines deductive conclusion. 64

Necessary truth-preservation and belief management Necessary truth-preservation is prima facie not a reasonable norm for the management of one s beliefs. Harman s arguments: mind-cluttering, logical omniscience etc. A few more: deductive reasoning is - costly: a lot of input for little output. - inefficient: usually, available information underdetermines deductive conclusion. 65

From strategic to constitutive norms According to BIO, the concept of necessary truthpreservation arose as a strategic component of specific dialectical games: indefeasibility. With internalization of opponent, it became a constitutive norm of the deductive method. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary condition for validity: it does not say that it is sufficient. The corresponding consequence relations may still exclude monotonicity (relevant logics) or reflexivity (syllogistic). 66

From strategic to constitutive norms According to BIO, the concept of necessary truthpreservation arose as a strategic component of specific dialectical games: indefeasibility. With internalization of opponent, it became a constitutive norm of the deductive method. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary condition for validity: it does not say that it is sufficient. The corresponding consequence relations may still exclude monotonicity (relevant logics) or reflexivity (syllogistic). 67

From strategic to constitutive norms According to BIO, the concept of necessary truthpreservation arose as a strategic component of specific dialectical games: indefeasibility. With internalization of opponent, it became a constitutive norm of the deductive method. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary condition for validity: it does not say that it is sufficient. The corresponding consequence relations may still exclude monotonicity (relevant logics) or reflexivity (syllogistic). 68

From strategic to constitutive norms According to BIO, the concept of necessary truthpreservation arose as a strategic component of specific dialectical games: indefeasibility. With internalization of opponent, it became a constitutive norm of the deductive method. Necessary truth-preservation as necessary condition for validity: it does not say that it is sufficient. The corresponding consequence relations may still exclude monotonicity (relevant logics) or reflexivity (syllogistic). 69

The nature and scope of the normative import Not a transcendental kind of normativity: internal to the game, embedded in practices. But contrary to e.g. Brandom, the claim is that necessary truth-preservation has a normative import only for rather specific, contrived forms of dialogical interaction: circles of specialists. Geach: a set of norms only works if it is followed most of the time (performance/competence gap). Empirical results from psychology suggest that untrained people are not extensively familiar with the game of deduction. 70

The nature and scope of the normative import Not a transcendental kind of normativity: internal to the game, embedded in practices. But contrary to e.g. Brandom, the claim is that necessary truth-preservation has a normative import only for rather specific, contrived forms of dialogical interaction: circles of specialists. Geach: a set of norms only works if it is followed most of the time (performance/competence gap). Empirical results from psychology suggest that untrained people are not extensively familiar with the game of deduction. 71

The nature and scope of the normative import Not a transcendental kind of normativity: internal to the game, embedded in practices. But contrary to e.g. Brandom, the claim is that necessary truth-preservation has a normative import only for rather specific, contrived forms of dialogical interaction: circles of specialists. Geach: a set of norms only works if it is followed most of the time (performance/competence gap). Empirical results from psychology suggest that untrained people are not extensively familiar with the game of deduction. 72

The nature and scope of the normative import Not a transcendental kind of normativity: internal to the game, embedded in practices. But contrary to e.g. Brandom, the claim is that necessary truth-preservation has a normative import only for rather specific, contrived forms of dialogical interaction: circles of specialists. Geach: a set of norms only works if it is followed most of the time (performance/competence gap). Empirical results from psychology suggest that untrained people are not extensively familiar with the game of deduction. 73

Dialogical, multi-agent bridge principles If A, B => C, then (if Opponent has granted A and B, then Opponent must concede C if asserted by Proponent) If A, B => C, then (if Opponent has granted A and B, then Proponent may assert C) 74

Dialogical, multi-agent bridge principles If A, B => C, then (if Opponent has granted A and B, then Opponent must concede C if asserted by Proponent) If A, B => C, then (if Opponent has granted A and B, then Proponent may assert C) 75

Back to mono-agent thinking As Milne (2009), we may inquire into the possible transposition of these dialogical norms to mono-agent thinking situations. While it has its origins in multi-agent situations, the internalization of opponent makes it so that the canons of logic may also be fruitfully applied in at least some mono-agent situations. In situations of scientific inquiry, it becomes relevant to counter our natural tendency towards doxastic conservativeness: deductive method allows for that. 76

Back to mono-agent thinking As Milne (2009), we may inquire into the possible transposition of these dialogical norms to mono-agent thinking situations. While it has its origins in multi-agent situations, the internalization of opponent makes it so that the canons of logic may also be fruitfully applied in at least some mono-agent situations. In situations of scientific inquiry, it becomes relevant to counter our natural tendency towards doxastic conservativeness: deductive method allows for that. 77

Back to mono-agent thinking As Milne (2009), we may inquire into the possible transposition of these dialogical norms to mono-agent thinking situations. While it has its origins in multi-agent situations, the internalization of opponent makes it so that the canons of logic may also be fruitfully applied in at least some mono-agent situations. In situations of scientific inquiry, it becomes relevant to counter our natural tendency towards doxastic conservativeness: deductive method allows for that. 78

The de-biasing effect of deductive reasoning A fundamental computational bias (Stanovich): the tendency to automatically bring prior knowledge to bear when solving problems. As an upshot of internalization of opponent, the deductive method forces the agent: - to reason only with information explicitly on the table. - to consider all the situations in which premises are the case, not only her preferred ones. Thus, in this specific, narrow sense, deductive logic does have some normative import for thinking. 79

The de-biasing effect of deductive reasoning A fundamental computational bias (Stanovich): the tendency to automatically bring prior knowledge to bear when solving problems. As an upshot of internalization of opponent, the deductive method forces the agent: - to reason only with information explicitly on the table. - to consider all the situations in which premises are the case, not only her preferred ones. Thus, in this specific, narrow sense, deductive logic does have some normative import for thinking. 80

The de-biasing effect of deductive reasoning A fundamental computational bias (Stanovich): the tendency to automatically bring prior knowledge to bear when solving problems. As an upshot of internalization of opponent, the deductive method forces the agent: - to reason only with information explicitly on the table. - to consider all the situations in which premises are the case, not only her preferred ones. Thus, in this specific, narrow sense, deductive logic does have some normative import for thinking. 81

The de-biasing effect of deductive reasoning A fundamental computational bias (Stanovich): the tendency to automatically bring prior knowledge to bear when solving problems. As an upshot of internalization of opponent, the deductive method forces the agent: - to reason only with information explicitly on the table. - to consider all the situations in which premises are the case, not only her preferred ones. Thus, in this specific, narrow sense, deductive logic does have some normative import for thinking. 82

Conclusions It is a mistake to start with the normative import of deductive logic for thought. Instead, originally logic emerged as a normative theory of specific dialogical practices: multi-agent setting. With the internalization of opponent, the deductive method is in between multi- and mono-agency. Deductive logic can be viewed as having normative grip on some mono-agent thinking situations: to counter doxastic conservativeness when needed. 83

Conclusions It is a mistake to start with the normative import of deductive logic for thought. Instead, originally logic emerged as a normative theory of specific dialogical practices: multi-agent setting. With the internalization of opponent, the deductive method is in between multi- and mono-agency. Deductive logic can be viewed as having normative grip on some mono-agent thinking situations: to counter doxastic conservativeness when needed. 84

Conclusions It is a mistake to start with the normative import of deductive logic for thought. Instead, originally logic emerged as a normative theory of specific dialogical practices: multi-agent setting. With the internalization of opponent, the deductive method is in between multi- and mono-agency. Deductive logic can be viewed as having normative grip on some mono-agent thinking situations: to counter doxastic conservativeness when needed. 85

Conclusions It is a mistake to start with the normative import of deductive logic for thought. Instead, originally logic emerged as a normative theory of specific dialogical practices: multi-agent setting. With the internalization of opponent, the deductive method is in between multi- and mono-agency. Deductive logic can be viewed as having normative grip on some mono-agent thinking situations: to counter doxastic conservativeness when needed. 86