Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Similar documents
Martin s case for disjunctivism

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Idealism. Contents EMPIRICISM. George Berkeley and Idealism. Preview: Hume. Idealism: other versions. Idealism: simplest definition

Two books, one title. And what a title! Two leading academic publishers have

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Mind s Eye Idea Object

The British Empiricism

Realism and its competitors. Scepticism, idealism, phenomenalism

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

The Empirical Skepticism of David Hume. Dustin M. Sigsbee

Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 45, Number 3, July 2007, pp (Article) DOI: /hph

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Empiricism. HZT4U1 - Mr. Wittmann - Unit 3 - Lecture 3

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

Idealism from A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I by George Berkeley (1720)

The Reality of Appearances

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

Part One. On Being Alienated

What is consciousness? Although it is possible to offer

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

The Existence of Material Substance. A Response to George Berkeley s Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Philosophy 104

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

From Descartes to Locke. Sense Perception And The External World

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Perceptual Justification and the Phenomenology of Experience. Jorg DhiptaWillhoft UCL Submitted for the Degree of PhD

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Classical Theory of Concepts

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

Kant's One World: Interpreting 'Transcendental Idealism'

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Reid Against Skepticism

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

Unit 2. WoK 1 - Perception. Tuesday, October 7, 14

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

BERKELEY S COMMON SENSE APPROACH TO LOCKE S THEORY OF INFERENTIAL KNOWLEDGE *

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

does. All reality is mental, consisting only of minds and their ideas. Ideas are passive, whereas minds are active. Every idea needs a mind to be in.

Is Epicurus a Direct Realist?

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Direct Realism, Introspection, and Cognitive Science 1

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Berkeley s Ideas of Reflection

Kantian Realism. Jake Quilty-Dunn. Kantian Realism 75

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

Chapter I. Introduction

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

On C.D. Broad s Sensa

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Hume s Missing Shade of Blue as a Possible Key. to Certainty in Geometry

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

C.D. Broad on Moral Sense Theories in Ethics

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JUNE 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Entitlement, epistemic risk and scepticism

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

Knowledge and Reality

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

The Critique of Berkeley and Hume. Sunday, April 19, 2015

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

John Locke. British Empiricism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7a The World

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Recap. Contents EMPIRICISM. Reductionism and Idealism. Early Carnap. Game plan. Reading and final essay. Recap: Russell s phenomenalism

Transcription:

1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience itself has a relational structure, i.e. consists in someone being presented with an external object. Philosophers have used the argument from illusion to undermine naïve realism. But there are many problems with the argument. The best thing to say is just this: in cases of illusion, we see ordinary things, but these things seem to have properties that they do not really have, e.g. I see the straight stick looking bent. However, the naive realist also has the argument from hallucination to contend with. As we will see, this argument is much more powerful. 2 Developing the argument You are now having a genuinely perceptual experience. It involves genuine awareness of things in the world. It would be possible, however, for you to have a subjectively matching hallucination. That is, it would be possible for you to have a hallucinatory experience which is, as far as you can tell, experientially just like the perceptual experience that you are now having. So now imagine these two cases. In one case, you have a genuinely perceptual experience (as of a pink elephant, say). In the other, you have a subjectively matching hallucination (again as of a pink elephant). One of these experiences is a perception, the other is an hallucination. But they are indistinguishable from the inside. There is no difference in how things seem to you in each case. Things are experientially the same in both cases. The argument (1) The hallucinatory experience consists in the presentation of a minddependent object (rather than a mind-independent one). (2) The perceptual and the hallucinatory experience have the same nature. Hence: (C) The perceptual experience consists in the presentation of a mind-dependent object (rather than a mind-independent one). 1

The argument is valid, given the relevant reading of premise (2), so that: If two experiences x and y have the same nature, then if x consists in the presentation of a mind-dependent object, so too does y. The argument easily generalises. It can be applied to any perceptual experience whatever. (For each perceptual experience, there is a (possible) subjectively matching hallucination). So naïve realists face a challenge here. 2.1 Arguing for premise (1) We can argue for premise (1) in the following way: i. In the hallucinatory case, one is presented with something. It is just false to say that nothing whatsoever is presented to the mind in cases of hallucinatory experience. ii. But if one is presented with something in the hallucinatory case, then it could only be a mind-dependent object (a mere image, as Hume puts it). iii. Thus, in the hallucinatory case, one is presented with a mind-dependent object (and nothing else). These four points can be made in favour of the first premise: (A) (B) (C) It is just very intuitive to think that something must be present to the mind, even in cases of hallucination. It is not as if one s mind is simply blank! (cf. Pautz: 2007). When one hallucinates, there seems to be an item that one can attend to, concentrate on, etc. But how can one attend to something that does not exist? When one has a hallucinatory experience, as of a pink elephant, say, there is a distinctive sense in which it seems to one as if a pink elephant is there. More generally, when one hallucinates, there are certain facts concerning how things are, experientially, with one. Arguably, the best explanation of these facts is that one really is presented with an object, having certain sensible qualities. (Compare C. D. Broad s defense of the phenomenal principle from the first lecture.) These first three points are all made by A. D. Smith in the following passage: 2

To say simply that [one] is not aware of anything is surely to under-describe this situation dramatically. Perhaps we can make sense of there being mock thoughts, but can there really be such a thing as mock sensory awareness? Perhaps there can be an illusion of understanding, but can there be an illusion of awareness? [Moreover, the] sensory features of the situation need to be accounted for...if we take as our example subjects who are fully attentive and focused, we need to do justice to the fact that such subjects in some sense take cognizance of, indeed fully attend to, sensory presentations. (2002, pp. 224-225) The fourth and final point is made by Mark Johnston (2004). The basic idea is this. Hallucinatory experience can provide a distinctive kind of knowledge of sensible qualities. But this is only possible if such experience presents an object, one which really has the sensible qualities in question. The case of Mary: Mary spends her whole life in a black and white room. But one day she leaves the room, and for the first time, sees a red thing. When she sees the red thing, she comes to know what red is like, and what red things are like. This is something she did not know before. By seeing a red thing, Mary comes to know what red is like. But she could have gained this knowledge by hallucinating. But how could Mary come to know what red is like, and what red things are like, on the basis of having a hallucination, if her hallucination did not involve awareness of something red? Here is how Johnston puts the point: I can learn from my hallucination what a certain shade of red is like. How can I do this unless my hallucination involves awareness of that shade, unless that shade is an object of my awareness? (2004, p. 131) But we can also ask: how can a shade of red be the object of an experience, unless the experience itself presents to one an object with that very shade? We can bolster the argument, perhaps, by considering after-images: Fig1 The after-image experience seems to acquaint you with a shade of blue (cyan). But how could it do this without presenting to you an object that instantiates that specific shade of blue (cyan)? 3

In favour of the second premise, the following two things can be said: (D) (E) Hallucinatory experience does not present mind-independent things. But what else could the object of hallucination be, if not a mind-dependent thing? The object of a hallucinatory experience seems only to exist when one is aware of it, and seems to cease to exist when one is not aware of it. The best way to explain this is to say that the object is minddependent, i.e. dependent for its being on the experience one has. 2.2 Arguing for premise (2) Perceiving and hallucinating are different. But the kind of experience involved in each case may be the same. As Johnston explains, we must draw:...a distinction between the fact that someone is hallucinating, which entails that he is not seeing, and the fact that he is enjoying an act of awareness of a certain kind namely the act of awareness that happens to be involved in hallucination. The point of the distinction is to suggest that this second is a kind of act that might happen to occur in non-hallucinatory cases as well. (Johnston: 2004, p. 115) The argument for premise (2) i.e. the premise that the perceptual experience and the hallucinatory experience have the same nature is essentially this: i. The perceptual experience and the hallucinatory experience are subjectively indistinguishable. ii. If two experiences are subjectively indistinguishable, then they have the same basic nature. iii. Therefore: the perceptual and the hallucinatory experience have the same basic nature. Here is how Foster puts the point: once we have come to accept the presence of internal objects of awareness in the case of hallucination, it then becomes tempting to recognize their presence in the case of perception too. For if perception and hallucination have the same subjective character [i.e. seem the same from the inside ], the simplest and most obvious way of accounting for this would be to suppose that they also have, at the fundamental level of description, the same psychological character through and through (2000, p. 8) 4

Arguably, we can motivate ii. on general methodological grounds: In general, it is a sound methodological principle to assume that two things which can t be told apart are relevantly similar until one finds reason to overturn that assumption. (Martin: 1997, p. 81) The idea that subjective indistinguishables must share the same basic or fundamental nature so that one presents only a mind-dependent object given that the other does is a powerful idea, which has driven much work in the philosophy of mind. (For a defence of this idea, see Crane: 2005.) (N.b. We can also motivate premise (2) by appealing to causal considerations. We will go into this in more detail in the final lecture (i.e. 4).) 2.3 A note about the argument Note that premise (1) may not be necessary to refute naïve realism. We only really need the sameness of nature premise, given the evident fact that hallucinations do not present ordinary, mind-independent things: (1*) The hallucinatory experience does not consist in the presentation of ordinary, mind-independent things. (2*) The perceptual and the hallucinatory perceptual experience have the same nature. Therefore: (3* ) The perceptual experience does not consist in the presentation of ordinary, mind-independent things. However, it has been traditional to use the argument from hallucination, not only to refute naïve realism, but also to establish the further claim that perceptual experiences present mind-dependent things to subjects. 3 Some ways of coping In the rest of the lecture, we will consider some ways of living with the conclusion forced upon us by the argument from hallucination. First we will consider a representative realist (or indirect realist) view, of the sort that Locke arguably endorsed. Then we will consider some non-realist views, namely the idealism of Berkeley, and the phenomenalism of later thinkers, e.g. J. S. Mill and Bertrand Russell. 5

3.1 Representative Realism The conclusion of the argument tells us something about the nature of perceptual experience, or about its structure. It tells us, in particular, that each perceptual experience consists in the presentation of a minddependent thing. Does it follow from this that we only perceive or sense mere images, mere mind-dependent things? Not necessarily. We can also allow that perceptual experiences have indirect objects, which represent their direct ones. Tom perceives a lavender bush = (i) Tom has a perceptual experience, which consists in the presentation of a mind-dependent, mental object. (ii) The lavender bush is the cause of the perceptual experience Tom has. The direct object enters into the structure of the experience, and so partly constitutes it. The indirect object is merely the cause of the experience. 3.1.1 Background Locke arguably held a view of this kind (1690). He called the minddependent direct objects ideas. Contemporary forms of the view are held by Jackson (1977) and Robinson (1994). As is common now, they call the minddependent objects sense data. But this terminology can be confusing: G. E. Moore (e.g. Moore: 1953, p. 30) introduced the term sense datum as a neutral term designed to pick out whatever is given to the mind. So Moorean sense data need not be mind-dependent. (Moore could never make up his mind about this question! See further Snowdon: 2007). Other 20 th Century sense-datum theorists (Broad, Price) insisted that sense data were (i) non-physical, (ii) non-ordinary, but also (iii) mind-independent objects, which, in some cases at least, belonged to the more familiar things we see. This is a pretty strange view, which has rightly ceased to be popular! 3.1.2 Varieties of the view The naïve view: sense data fully resemble their indirect objects. The Lockean view: sense data only partially resemble their indirect objects. The Kantian view: sense data do not even partially resemble their indirect objects. 6

Q1. How can we know that external objects exist? Q2. How can we know what external objects are like? Locke s reply: (1*) The existence of external things, as causes of our perceptual experiences, best explains the order and coherence of our sensations (and also their passivity, i.e. we do not create them as when e.g. we imagine.) (2*) Given that external things exist, we can use scientific investigation to discover what these things are like. But science only tells us about the so-called primary qualities of things (Locke thought that these include: solidity, shape, size, texture.) It does not tell us about the secondary qualities (colour, sound, taste). We end up with: Locke s view. External objects only have scientific properties (the primary qualities). They do not have many of the properties that they seem to have (colours, sounds, tastes). In this sense, do not have the secondary qualities. However, they do have powers to cause in us experiences of ideas with secondary qualities. (Locke sometimes uses secondary quality to refer to these powers. So in this sense, external things do have secondary qualities, even on Locke s view. This can get confusing, but see Mackie: 1976.) Campbell s worry: Assume the naïve version of the view. When you experience the lavender bush, you are directly aware of an idea or sense datum, which has the colour, size, shape of a lavender bush. But you are also indirectly aware of a lavender bush, which also has these properties. But this seems like one too many bushes! As Campbell writes: We seem to be faced with the idea of an absurd duplication of the material world in some other area (2002, p. 156). Johnston s Worry someone who accepted and lucidly understood the [view] would be justified in regarding the presence of external particulars as at most a conjecture concerning extrinsic connections between his visual experience and external causes. But as against this implication of the [view], our relation to the things we are seeing is not well captured in this way. We can successfully demonstrate them without relying explicitly or implicitly on such a conjectural causal description. When we see particular things, they are just presented as there to be attended to and demonstrated. (2004, p. 119) In short: representative realism makes our access to things too indirect 7

3.2 Idealism Berkeley thinks we should identify the mind-dependent objects of perceptual experience with ordinary things. He agrees with Locke that the objects of perception are mind-dependent ideas. As he says in the Principles That neither our thoughts, nor passions, nor ideas formed by the imagination, exist without the mind, is what everybody will allow. And it seems no less evident that the various sensations or ideas imprinted on the senses cannot exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving them Their esse is percipi, nor is it possible they should have any existence, out of the minds o thinking things which perceive them (1710, 3) Berkeley does not really argue for this assumption in the Principles. But he does appeal to the argument from illusion in Three Dialogues. (See Robinson: 1985 for a Berkelean argument using the argument from hallucination.) The essence of the view is set out here: It is indeed an opinion strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a word all sensible objects have an existence natural or real, distinct from their being perceived [Yet this involves] a manifest contradiction. For what are the fore-mentioned objects but the things we perceive by sense, and what do we perceive besides or own ideas or sensations and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of these or any combination of them should exist unperceived? (1710, 4) Can t ordinary things continuing existing unperceived by us? Yes, God perceives them all the while. 3.3 Phenomenalism According to Phenomenalism, ordinary physical things are constructions out of actual and possible sense data (J. S. Mill, Bertrand Russell). According to the phenomenalist, to believe that a material or physical object of a certain sort exists is just to believe that sense-data of various sorts have been experienced, are being experienced, will be experienced, and/or would be experienced under certain specifiable conditions. (Laurence: 2016, 2.1) Notably, Berkeley himself may have anticipated such a view: The table I write on, I say, exists, that is, I see and feel it; and if I were out of my study I should say it existed, meaning thereby that if I was in my study I might perceive it, or that some other spirit actually does perceive it (1710, 3) 8

Bibliography G. Berkeley (1710/1713) Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues, Oxford World Classics, (ed.) Robinson, H. Crane, T. (2005) What is the Problem of Perception? Synthesis Philosophica Vol. 20, pp. 237-264 Foster, J. (2000) The Nature of Perception, Oxford University Press. Jackson, F. (1977) Perception: A Representative Theory, Cambridge University Press. Johnston, M. (2004) The Obscure Object of Hallucination, Philosophical Studies 120: pp. 113 183. Laurence, B. (2016) "Epistemological Problems of Perception", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/perception-episprob/>. Locke, J. (1969) Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Oxford: Clarendon Press, (ed.) P. Nidditch, 1975. Martin, M. G. F. (1997) The Reality of Appearances, in Thought and Ontology, Sainsbury, M. (ed.), Franco Angeli. Moore, G. E. (1953) Some Main Problems of Philosophy, London: George, Allen and Unwin. Pautz, A. (2007) Intentionalism and Perceptual Presence, Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 21, Philosophy of Mind. Robinson, H. (1985) The General Form of the Argument for Berkelian Idealism, In John Foster & Howard Robinson (eds.) Essays on Berkeley, OUP. Robinson, H. (1994) Perception, Routledge, London and New York. Smith, A. D. (2002). The problem of perception. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Snowdon, P. (2007) G. E. Moore on Sense-Data and Perception, in Themes From G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics, Nuccetelli, S. and Seay. G. (eds.), Clarendon Press. 9