VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

Similar documents
BOOK REVIEWS. 259 H. C. STEVENS. University of Chicago.

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

SENSE-DATA G. E. Moore

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

CONTENTS. INTRODUCTORY Chapter I ETHICAL NEUTRALITY AND PRAGMATISM

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

1/9. The First Analogy

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

VI. CRITICAL NOTICES.

The Subject-matter of Philosophy, and its Relations to the Special Sciences

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Introduction to Philosophy

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

1/12. The A Paralogisms

BERTRAND RUSSELL, as Philosopher

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively.

A Note on Straight-Thinking

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

Gunky time and indeterminate existence

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Realism and instrumentalism

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Difference between Science and Religion? - A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

The Question of Metaphysics

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

Transcription:

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES. Our Knowledge of the External World. By BBBTBAND RUSSELL. Open Court Co. Pp. ix, 245. THIS book Mr. Russell's Lowell Lectures though intentionally somewhat popular in tone, contains some most important and interesting contributions to philosophy. Its scope is very accurately conveyed by its complete title; Mr. Russell deals with our knowledge of the external world ' as a field for scientific method in philosophy'. The first chapter deals with Current Tendencies; it says something about Pragmatism, Absolute Idealism, and Bergson ; and it tries to delimit the sphere of philosophy. If philosophy is to be a genuine separate soience it must contain propositions about matters not dealt with in other sciences, and these propositions must be proved or rendered probable by the methods common to all science and to the sound reasonings of daily life. The difference between philosophy and the natural sciences (e.g. physics) is not that it deals with a more elevated subject matter, nor that it uses some superior method of argument, but that it consists of propositions about much more abstract entities. Again, like all genuine science (including ethics itself), philosophy must become what it has hardly ever yet been ' ethically neutral'. When philosophy is defined in this way three important results follow : (1) It can never conflict with any discovery of natural science or with any judgment of value ; for propositions about entirely distinct subject matters cannot conflict; (2) We see that a number of problems whioh have been supposed to be pre-eminently philosophical belong to the natural soienoes, and, if answerable at all, must be answered by empirical investigation. Examples of such problems are the immortality of the soul and the existence of God; and (3) the essence of philosophy is seen to consist in logic, defined in a certain sense which Mr. Russell elaborates in his second chapter. In this chapter Mr. Russell gives a very useful account of the main results of the logical studies of Frege, Peano, Dr. Whitehead, and himself, with acknowledgments of further developments and modifications made by Mr. Wittgenstein and not yet revealed tothe profane vulgar. He reiterates his belief that the logical basis

BEBTRAND. RUSSELL, Knowledge of the External World. 251 of most absolute idealism is the erroneous view that all propositions ascribe qualities to subjects. Moreover he insists on the importance of asymmetrical relations and of polyadio relations; by means of the latter, as we know, he considers that the problem of erroneous judgment can be solved. For any extended knowledge we need to know two very different kinds of things: (1) atomic facts, and (2), forms. The first are most obviously supplied by sense-perception and are asserted in such propositions as ' this is red ' and ' this is to the left of that'. The second are the subject matter of pure logic ; they are a priori and they assert of certain ' forms' or prepositional functions that they give true propositions whatever ' matter' be substituted for the variable in them (provided of course that the proper restrictions as to logical type are complied with). The knowledge of forms and of the general propositions about them is essential to all inference; the knowledge of atomic propositions is equally essential if we are to hook our logical implications on to the existent world, to assert our premises, and thus assert our conclusions by themselves. The great use of modern logic as against the traditional logic in philosophy is twofold : (1) It recognises an enormously greater number of primitive logical forms and thus sets free the logical imagination and provides the materials for an immense number of logical constructions to fit empirical facts, and (2) it enables us by means of the symbolic caloulus to work out the results of our hypotheses much more fully and certainly than the ambiguity of words and the restricted apparatus of Aristotelian logic would allow. We no longer proceed in philosophy by gradually cutting out all possible explanations but one ; we see that there is an immense number of logically valid explanations possible for almost anything, and we proceed to determine what is essential logically to them all. The rest of the book, except the last chapter, consists in applying the methods and results of modern logic to the problem of the nature and reality of the external world. It divides into two parts. The first, contained in chapters iii. and iv., is an attempt to determine the relation between the world of sense-data and the world of physics with the fewest possible assumptions by means of the Principle of Abstraction; the second (chaps, v.-vii. inclusive) deals with the mathematical theory of infinity and continuity. The latter is of course comparatively well known to a certain number of persons, though evidently not to most philosophers out of Cambridge. It is valuable as presenting a clear and intelligible account of a somewhat difficult subject by one who is a complete master of it and himself a discoverer in it. The only new part is the little that has been called for by Bergsonian attacks on the mathematical doctrine of continuity and motion. These consist mainly of misunderstandings; but the amended Bergsonian doctrine that the mathematioal theory is flawless but irrelevant to real motion was worth answering. The answer of course is to

252 CRITICAL NOTICES: distinguish between movement as a sense-datum and the movement constructed logically for the purposes of physics. Mr. Russell gives a physiological explanation of the sense-datum ; but he is not content with this. He further points out that, even in perceived motion, what we must have is not something unitary and indivisible; but at each instant We perceive a slightly different extended.motion. Thus we are again brought to a compact series, this time of sense-data. Of course, as Mr. Russell instate, two sense-data may differ and be proved to 'differ though they cannot be perceived to do so. \ The most interesting part of the book ty those who are already familiar with the mathematical doctrine ofiinfinity and continuity will be ohapters iii. and iv. In general we may say that they consist of an attempt to state phenomenalism in a logioally satisfactory way by means of the notions and results of modern mathematical logic In particular they make use of»the Principle of Abstraction (whioh has proved so useful in the definition of -cardinal and ordinal numbers and in the proof of existence theorems for these) to define the space, time, and matter of physics as logical functions of sense-data, and their immediately given relations. Traditionally physical matter has been supposed to be inferred as the cause of sense-data, whilst the evidence for mathematical space and time has hardly been considered at all. Since any consistent logical function of actual sense-data must exist in the logical sense there can be no doubt of the existence of the space, time, and matter of physics if they can be exhibited as logical funotions of actual sense-data. Whether they also exist in any other sense must remain an open question; Mr. Russell does not say exactly what this question means, but I think it means: Are there entities.of the same logical type as sense-data, which have (apart from differences due to difference of type) qualities and relations with the same logical properties as those possessed by the funotions of sense-data whioh fulfil the demands made by physics on its space, time, and matter? Mr. Russell is not content with suggesting the possibility of defining the entities of physics in terms of sense-data, he proceeds to offer a tentative sketch of how this might be done. It does not profess to be complete, for it assumes both the sense-data of other people accepted on testimony, and possible sense-data; but Mr. Russell hopes, by introducing additional complications, to eliminate the3e and produce a purely solipsistic physics. His tentative theory (constructed to deal mainly with the data of sight) is roughly as follows. Each man's sense-data form an extended world and no sense-data are common to two private worlds. But there are correlations between similar sense-data in the various private worlds. A thing is the class of all the similar sense-data in all the private worlds. (We may compare Lotze's view that things are the laws of their states. The

BERTRAND RUSSELL, Knowledge of the External World. 253 superiority of Mr. Russell's theory is that he tells us much more carefully than Lotze what is meant by ' their' in this connexion.) The next task is to define a common space and a common time ' in' which these things shall be and ' in' which their changes shall take place. We construct a common space by taking each private world as a whole as one point in the new space; it is here that we have to introduce possible private worlds as well as our own and those which we know about by testimony. It is an empirical fact that the space so constructed has three dimensions. Next we notice that if we consider, e.g. all the private worlds which contain a round appearance of a penny and arrange them in an order in accordance with the sizes of the round sense-data they form a straight line in the common-space. Likewise all the private spaces whioh contain a straight appearance of the penny (i.e. as we say ' the penny viewed edgewise') constitute straight lines in the common space. And it is found that all these lines intersect each other when produced and intersect the line defined by the ronnd sense-data at a common point in the common-space. This point of intersection is denned as ' the place where the penny is'. The particular private space in which there is a particular sense-datum of any shape whioh is a member of the class constituting the physical penny is called ' the place from where the penny has an appearance of this shape'. Physics is mainly interested in the places where things are, psychology is mainly interested in the places from which physical things have such and such an appearance. The next task is to define the points of space themselves. Broadly speaking a point is defined as the class of all the sensedata containing the point. (When fully stated this definition is not circular.) Certain assumptions have to be made about sensedata in order to give to space the continuity which physios commonly ascribes to it. This way of looking at geometry has been carefully worked out by Dr. Whitehead and Prof. Huntington, and it is Dr. Whitehead's work which has inspired Mr. Bussell to his attempted reconstruction of physios. Finally a common temporal order for the states of things has to be constructed and here the effects of an intervening medium have to be interpreted in terms of the theory, and account has to be taken of the results that are summarised in the Theory of Relativity. When the common temporal order has been constructed it is a comparatively easy task to proceed to a further degree of abstraction and to define instants and their relations in terms of events and their relations. The logical apparatus needed for this has been constructed by Mr. Norbert Wiener in a very interesting paper in the Cambridge Philosophical Transactions. (It is unfortunate that, through a misprint in the present work, Mr. Wiener appears as Wilner.) This, in the barest outline, is Mr. Russell's reconstruction of

254 CBITICAX NOTICES: physics. Whether it ultimately prove valid or not it is clear to me that it is of the most vital philosophical importance. It is hardly possible to attempt any criticism within the limits of a review; where I think further investigation is most needed is as to the grounds on which we classify together such varied appearances as a set of oircles and a set of straight lines as the appearances of one penny, and yet classify several sets of round appearances as two different pennies. But I feel tolerably confident that any difficulties that may arise are difficulties of detail, and that, even if it be found necessary to introduce rather more ultimate assumption than Mr. Bussell would like, he is on the right track. The last ohapter deals with Causation with especial reference to the problem of Free-Will. It is on the lines of Mr. Russell's paper in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Indeterminism remains a possibility, for there is no self-evident law that all events must have causes, when we are clear that causation means nothing but functional correlation. But there is no more reason for assuming indeterminism in human actions than in the physical world, and it is a fact that the general modes of reaction of well-known people to definite general types of situation can be foretold with about as muoh confidence as those of physical systems. In both oases if you insist on going into extreme detail your predictions may be falsified, and this may be due to the events in question obeying no law, though it may equally be due to our ignorance of the complete statement of the law. C. D. BROAD. The Great Society. A Psychological Analysis. By GRAHAM WALLAS. London : Macmillan, 1914. Pp. xii, 406. THE author perhaps it is his modesty says that while he was writing <this book he saw more clearly than before what it was about, and particularly its relation-to his previous book Human Nature in Politics. But I can scarcely conceive that he had not present in his mind, for some time before he began to write, a fairly shrewd conception as to its relation to his former book and indeed to psychological and political thought generally. Its genesis, as it appears to me, is explained by the following considerations, though I do not know that Mr. Wallas would accept this account. Just as nineteenth century science claimed to reduce all knowledge to terms of itself, discarding and even vehemently denouncing as nescience what it could not thus embrace, so the growing analyses of sensation and the triumphs of psychology along the lower mental levels tended to explain all mental processes in terms of images and sensations and conative trends of the