At the Frontiers of Reality

Similar documents
Realism and instrumentalism

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Machine Consciousness, Mind & Consciousness

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Christian Coseru University of Charleston, USA

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Department of Philosophy

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Varieties of Apriority

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Jesus Christ and the Life of the Mind. By Mark A. Noll. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2011, xii+

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Philosophy Courses-1

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Epistemology and sensation

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

Transcendence J. J. Valberg *

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Philosophy Courses-1

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Department of Philosophy

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Illusionism and Givenness: Comments on Frankish *

Self-Consciousness, Interaction, and Understanding Others

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Sacha Golub. Heidegger on Concepts, Freedom, and Normativity. Cambridge University Press pp. $95.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN ).

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First, we will present the hard problem

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

THE NATURE OF MIND Oxford University Press. Table of Contents

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity


Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Read, Write, Laugh and Learn: A Student's Perspective

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Naturalism and Subjectivity

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

CURRICULUM VITAE : Thomas Jack Lynch Teacher-Scholar Postdoctoral Fellow, Wake Forest University

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Summary Kooij.indd :14

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Minds and Machines spring Hill and Nagel on the appearance of contingency, contd spring 03

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Transcription:

At the Frontiers of Reality by Christophe Al-Saleh Do the objects that surround us continue to exist when our backs are turned? This is what we spontaneously believe. But what is the origin of this belief that, according to Étienne Bimbenet, builds our humanity? Reviewed : Étienne Bimbenet, L invention du réalisme, Paris, Éditions du Cerf, 2015, 317 p., 29. Realism is, among other things, the belief in the existence of the world. As a realist, I believe that the world exists independently of me. When I stop looking at the apple, I do not believe that the apple has ceased to exist. And when I look at the apple, I consider that everything I see is as it should be because the apple enjoys those properties, those modes of being or appearing, independently of what I may believe or think. I also consider that other human beings have similar thoughts, and that they form thoughts about me. They can attribute to me beliefs, desires, and intentions, and I behave in the same way towards them. Étienne Bimbenet takes for granted two theses he had developed in L animal que je ne suis plus ( The animal I no longer am, Gallimard, 2011). The fist thesis is that human beings once were but no longer are animals. This means that the entry into humanity consists in exempting oneself from the evolutionary and behavioral laws that govern the animal kingdom. This does not mean that human beings are not, as are all living beings, subject to Darwinian laws; yet this legality is to be examined in relation to a more fundamental dimension of being human, namely worldhood, which is made possible by the mediation of language. Indeed, humans share a world for the reason that they live in language, and therein lies the fundamental dimension of human existence. In this sense, humans can contemplate their animal past from the perspective of their own specific world. Thus, as a human, I can speak of myself as the animal I no longer am.

Second, Bimbenet attributes animals with phenomenalism. This is a consequence of the first thesis. Deprived of the world, or lacking in world as Heidegger put it, animals are governed by specific sensations in determined environments. They are idealistic in the sense that while they do have a world, this world is reduced to an environment determined by the play of impulses and needs. They lack the mediation of language that would allow them to refer to the world as being other and as standing independently of the circle of needs and impulses. This raises the question of how we became realistic. For we were once animals, before we invented the world. But how could we invent the world out of its deprivation? In L animal que je ne suis plus, Bimbenet raised this problem in the following terms: Realism is a problem and [...] appears as a genuine metaphysical coup de force - the coup de force of metaphysics (of the thing-in-itself) in the history of life. How can animality [...] open itself to what is not itself? How can realism emerge out of animal idealism (phenomenalism)? (p. 141, see also the conclusion of the book, pp. 404-409). Realism as Transcendence of the Social World The problem, then, is to determine the origin of a belief that presumably distinguishes us from animals, namely the belief in the existence of the world. To do this, the inquiry focuses on the attitude that must, according to Husserl s phenomenological method, be put in brackets so that the experiences of consciousness may be correctly described. This method states, for instance, that if I want to describe perceptual phenomena correctly, I must first look at how they appear to me. It is indeed more convenient to put aside the idea that what I see is an apple when seeking to describe phenomena, that is to say, the ways in which the apple appears to me. This is a method for directing attention which consists in unchecking, so to speak, the box existence of the world in the belief section. The thesis defended in this book is as follows. The belief in the existence of the world is induced by adherence to the values of a group of human beings. This adherence is permitted by language. Learning to believe in the world means learning to use the referential function of words. However, to use words in such a way as to assign a reference to them, one must be sure to have enough authority to do so. Yet only the group can guarantee that authority to one of its members. For it is in a common and social world that words take on meaning (i.e., that they can have a reference). The group s authority over the individual manifests itself in the institution of language. I do not decide the meaning of words, let alone their reference. Thus, the individual is transcended in two ways. He or she is transcended by the world, the ideality of which he or she must recognize. He or she is transcended by the group. Reality in us proceeds from authority. (p. 253) 2

The authority of language lies in the fact that words have power. This is what is called the illocutionary dimension of language. One might, for instance, make a promise or give an order. Moreover, if we follow Searle and Kripke, the social world is constructed through adherence to a certain number of rules that merely perennialize the effectiveness of illocutionary acts. The reference comes after this. It is because an individual is supported by the social world and its authority that he or she has the authority to name the things of the world and to believe that he or she relates to a world which remains as it is. Realism is a language game (p. 239) or a transcendental fiction (p. 240). The mechanism of joint attention, discussed by the author in Chapter 9, provides sufficient evidence of this dimension whereby one learns the reference of words by being-with-another. Realism and essentialism (thinking that words designate essences beyond the things actually encountered) are natural attitudes in the sense that belonging to a human group suffices to develop them. In this regard, one does not learn to be a realist or an essentialist as one learns to be a Husserlian. This does not require any particular socialization. The fact remains that, according to the author, it would be wrong to think that natural attitudes are self-evident. The natural attitude is nothing natural [...] in the sense that it is not a given: It derives all its power of imposition from human institutions and from their specific normativity (p. 224). The Social World and the Physical World Bimbenet provides commentary on texts that, although not systematically cited at the end of the book, constitute an abundant bibliography. As could already be observed in L animal que je ne suis plus, his reflections definitely originate in phenomenology (Merleau- Ponty) and social philosophy (Durkheim), but they are also enriched by his scholarly and subtle commentary on authors of the analytical tradition. One will appreciate the very fine use of John McDowell s Mind and World, as well as the relevant reference to Tyler Burge, an author rarely cited by French philosophers of non-analytical obedience. The book is largely devoted to taking position in relation to other philosophies, such as naturalism, transcendental pragmatism, or Heideggerian philosophy. In this respect, it makes for a very rich and suggestive read. For instance, the resumption in chapter 10 of the rule-following debate, launched by Kripke s reading of Wittgenstein and introduced in France by Bouveresse with La force de la règle in 1987, is highly stimulating. Bimbenet, it would seem, seeks to join the French philosophical tradition by distancing himself from philosophical options that have relevance far beyond the French context. Commentary is clearly the author s central method. However, the book s ambition is to consider realism as an attitude or a form of life, not as a doctrine or a philosophical theory (p. 47). And it is true that the author also draws on works in ethology and 3

developmental psychology to define realism as a natural attitude, showing both its absence in animals and its genesis in children. Thus, according to Bimbenet, the belief in the social world precedes the belief in the physical world. In other words, one can believe in a world of objects with their simple physical characteristics only if one believes in the social world (which is how I translate, in terms of beliefs, the notions of authority and adherence to the power of the social). In other words, the belief in a world of objects depends ontologically, and not merely empirically or psychologically, on the belief in the social world. Yet such a thesis has empirical consequences. One of these consequences is that it is impossible to understand the objects of the physical world without adhering to the social world, and, in particular, without being able to learn in a socializing framework and according to intersubjective modalities how to speak. Cognitive sciences investigate, among other things, our abilities to interpret the behavior of others (folk psychology) and to understand the events of the physical world, notably by identifying causal links (folk physics). In a 1997 article entitled Are Children with Autism Superior at Folk Physics?, 1 Simon Baron-Cohen recalls that while folk psychology develops around the end of the first year of child development, folk physics i.e., the ability to project causal relationships onto objects and to anticipate the movements and reactions of things in the world appears much earlier in the ontogenesis of the young child. In addition, children with pervasive developmental disorders perform better in folk physics than do other children, even though they are seriously deficient in the area of folk psychology, which results in non-specific language disorders (dyslexia, dysphasia, etc.). What should we conclude if this observation is to remain compatible with one of the central theses of Bimbenet s book whereby the transcendence of the world in general, and hence of the physical world, presupposes the transcendence of the social world, or, to formulate it in the style of the book, whereby the world of things and objects stands out from the transcendent background of the social world? The following conclusions should be drawn. First, the beliefs of children with pervasive developmental disorders about the physical world are proto-beliefs that differ from the beliefs of children without these disorders. There are two types of beliefs about the things of the physical world. On the one hand, there are realistic beliefs, guaranteed by an intact brain structure and adequate neurodevelopment (what is called a neuro-typical structure), and, on the other hand, unrealistic beliefs, particularly those specific to children with neurodevelopmental disorders such as pervasive developmental disorders. 1 In Wellman, H. and Inagaki, K. (eds), The Emergence of Core Domains of Thought, New Directions for Child Development Series 75, 1997, pp. 45-54. 4

Second, children with pervasive developmental disorders are able to anticipate events in the physical world perfectly, but without their attitude being the mere reflection of a realistic attitude. Their ability to identify causal links in the world differs from that of neurotypical children. Finally, the folk physics we develop, whether or not we have pervasive developmental disorders, has nothing to do with our belief in the existence of the physical world, since it is through social interaction and the learning of language that we learn to believe in it. A Full Presence in the World The problem with all these consequences is that they lead to an impasse. By linking all belief in the physical world to the belief in the social world, the author leaves us no choice but to reduce the folk physics of children with developmental disorders to a set of propensities to react to events, as can be observed in non-human organisms, including very rudimentary ones. But in this case, how can it be explained that in experiments such as those reported by Baron- Cohen in the article cited above, the folk physics skills of children with pervasive developmental disorders are determined on the basis of their ability to verbalize expected sequences of events, for instance, starting from narratives of movement of objects? In addition, folk physics is rightly connected to language in children who otherwise have a great deal of difficulty using the same language to correctly answer questions on tests that measure folk psychology skills. This difference is difficult to explain when we assume, as the author does, that mastery of language including when it comes to talking about physical objects presupposes normal integration into the social world. Thus, neuro-typical children and neuro-atypical children share the same folk physics, but children with pervasive developmental disorders deploy this skill earlier and better. Moreover, there is no reason to assume, particularly since their verbalization of physical events is not challenged, that their attitudes cannot be connected to a form of realism, even though their belief in the social world is not at all self-evident. Yet for children with pervasive developmental disorders, theirs is a full-fledged presence in the world, even though it does not allow them to spontaneously adopt attitudes suitable for life in society. These children are able to engage fully in the physical world, to develop a fascination, for instance, with machines or with material structures. The presence in the world of the child with pervasive developmental disorders, however, remains the blind spot of the philosophy proposed by Bimbenet. This theoretical possibility is never contemplated. 5

Ultimately, the refusal to take seriously, for reasons that are never given, the specificity of the cognitive architecture of the mind and its connection with neural structures leads Bimbenet to exclude a whole section of humanity from this human world. These are the humans for whom the transcendence of the social world is not self-evident, but who are effectively present in the world. Published in laviedesidees.fr, 20 March 2018. Translated from the French by Renuka George with the support of the Florence Gould Foundation. First published in laviedesidees.fr, 30 March 2017. Translated from the French by Arianne Dorval. Published in Books & Ideas, 7 June 2018. 6