The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

Similar documents
Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

The CopernicanRevolution

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Kant and his Successors

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

1/9. The First Analogy

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

1/12. The A Paralogisms

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

The Supplement of Copula

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The Ontological Argument

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

A Most Affecting View: Transcendental Affection as Causation De-Schematized. Chad Mohler

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Habermas and Critical Thinking

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Inner Sense, Self-A ection, & Temporal Consciousness .,. ( )

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

Human Dignity 1. Universität Zürich Institut für Sozialethik Prof. Dr. Johannes Fischer November in Zürich.

15 Does God have a Nature?

The Philosophy of Consciousness Without an Object

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Kantian Realism. Jake Quilty-Dunn. Kantian Realism 75

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Varieties of Apriority

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Chapter 2 AN EXPOSITION AND EXAMINATION CONCERNING FREEDOM AND CAUSATION IN IMMANUEL KANT'S PHILOSOPHY

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Experiences Don t Sum

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Why Computers are not Intelligent: An Argument. Richard Oxenberg

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Transcription:

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

The familiar problems of skepticism necessarily entangled in empiricist epistemology can only be avoided with recourse to a certain knowledge that precedes the vicissitudes of experience. This, the search for a priori truth that might anchor human existence, is among others the theme that is perhaps the most important in Kant s enterprise. In short, the key was thought by Kant to have been found in the concepts of space and time. His solution is not without serious difficulties. Out of these difficulties arises the specific question: What, precisely, is the intended philosophical status of these concepts, particularly space? The problem, it will be argued here, becomes a conflict between two general approaches to the question. We find that we are torn between one reading that hopes to rescue Kant at the cost of fatally deflating him, and a second reading that creates incoherence only by over-investing in Kant s vocabulary. To Kant, a priori truth comes to us in the concepts of space and time. These concepts are unique for it is only their presupposition that makes experience possible. The focus here will be set only on the former. Objects outside of a subject can only be represented in space; there is simply no way to conceive of an object as represented in a non-spatial fashion. Space, furthermore, is not a concept that is learned through experience; it is impossible to conceive of space as being discovered in the course of human adventures; it is, after all, impossible to imagine experience at any point to be outside of space. Here the a priori nature of space is thought by Kant to be sufficiently proven. i It is necessary also to demonstrate that space is intuition. Kant argues that space is not a discursive concept that can be discriminately applied when appropriate and withheld from our recognition at other points. Space consists in everything.

Additionally, there cannot be a number of divisible spaces because even this notion requires one to imagine gaps of non-spatial vacuity between the walls of specific spaces, which is impossible to conceive. The conception of multiple spaces demands no less than other objects a broader space in which the multiple spaces are found. Finally, the argument is advanced that empirical concepts are necessarily limited and invoked to signify certain ideas at the exclusion of others. Empirical concepts inherently imply selective exclusion, whereas space is entirely all-inclusive. If we wished to call it an empirical concept we would be forced to say that everything ever known falls under its signification and we would therefore remove from it the limiting and exclusionary nature of empirical concepts. Thus, in addition to being a priori, space is an intuition. ii It is equally important to Kant s project that space does not hold for things-inthemselves. Kant argues that space is empirically real, i.e. it is always present insofar as objects in the world can be represented to human sensibility. At the same time, however, it cannot be said to exist as a thing-in-itself or in things-in-themselves; it is transcendentally ideal, i.e. nothing at all. iii It is easily seen why Kant s success in defeating empiricist skepticism and relativism must turn on the character he intended to attribute to the concept of space. If space were an object in the world like any other, it would immediately lose its privilege as the key to a priori truth; for then our understanding of the concept of space would be no less contaminated and contingent than the other fleeting appearances in experience. If space were a thing-in-itself or a property of things-in-themselves, our knowledge of the very concept would suffer from all of the same epistemological riddles which plague the empiricist framework. We realize, then, that in order for Kant to get where he wishes to

go, things-in-themselves must be spaceless. And it is at this point that the major difficulty begins to surface. It has been argued that Kant s thing-in-itself is not to be understood as something that actually exists. This is to say that it is purely an abstraction invoked to signify the impossible notion of a pure and unmediated communion between object and subject. The thing-in-itself is an object experienced without subjectivity, i.e. without a subject. Experience without a subject, of course, is impossible. On this account, then, the thingin-itself is a concept that essentially has negative signification: it is that which cannot be experienced so long as we experience. It is necessary, before moving on, to fully understand the implications of this account. For if this is what Kant means when he speaks of things-in-themselves, what we must first recognize is how little else can be coherently said regarding these impossible things-in-themselves. Ultimately and this is the problem one can say nothing about them. One cannot say anything about them, because the term has no referent. The term has purely negative signification that serves only as a marker of the impossible. The thing-in-itself is not a thing at all; it is not even a positive concept that represents things about which we could speak. In short, this interpretation offers an account in which there is nothing within the signification of the term on which a predicate could hope to latch. This interpretation certainly fails to help Kant; indeed it sets him back a great deal. If this interpretation captures Kant s intention, then Kant is unable to make the necessary move to the non-spatiality of the thing-in-itself. He is prevented from doing so because this interpretation offers a thing-in-itself that Kant simply cannot describe as non-spatial (or as anything else) without transgressing the supposed character of the term.

If the thing-in-itself serves only to mark an impossible experience, what could it mean to call it non-spatial? To call it non-spatial is to presuppose it is something that could possess an identity or at least take on a predicate. At the point things-in-themselves are required to be non-spatial in order for Kant to proceed, it seems that the concept of the thing-in-itself is forced into what one might, for now, call an ontological character even if this character turns out to be largely unintelligible. To attribute non-spatiality to the thing-in-itself is, after all, to comment on its character as though it were a thing of which one had knowledge. Essentially, even the slightest description of the thing-in-itself is a move toward an ontological conception of it. To say anything of the thing-in-itself is to presuppose it as something that can possess a character. In the best-case scenario, it could be argued that non-spatiality does not necessarily imply a concrete and specific physical existence. At best, this makes ontological an awkward choice of label. But the fact would remain that to call the thing-in-itself non-spatial would, paradoxically, be attaching to it a positive albeit limited identity. It would be claiming knowledge of its character as a thing or at least as a concept, and would thus step out of the strictly negative and abstract status assigned to it in the first interpretation. It appears, then, that at any point between these two competing interpretations, Kant fails. He fails, that is, to achieve a coherent conception of the non-spatial thing-initself. Sliding toward the first interpretation relieves Kant of having to defend that reality is supersensible and that we can have no knowledge of it. iv However, it can only do so by simultaneously hollowing-out the concept of the thing-in-itself to such a

degree that it becomes hopelessly sterile. Most significantly, the element of nonspatiality is removed from the table. To move away from this sterility by reinvesting the hollowed-out thing-in-itself with the character of non-spatiality is no less self-defeating. For the property of non-spatiality is purchased at too high a cost: at worst it presupposes an existing character in the world, and at the very best it at least presupposes a limited knowledge of the thing-in-itself. At any rate, for Kant to claim the non-spatiality of the thing-in-itself he must invest far more into the concept than coherence will allow. i Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: Palgrave Macmillian, 2003, pp. 68. ii Ibid, pp. 69-70. iii Ibid, pp. 72. iv Strawson, Bounds of Sense, pp. 16.