A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Similar documents
ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

145 Philosophy of Science

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

imply constrained maximization. are realistic assumptions. are assumptions that may yield testable implications. A and C above.

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Scientific errors should be controlled, not prevented. Daniel Eindhoven University of Technology

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

INTRODUCTION TO HYPOTHESIS TESTING. Unit 4A - Statistical Inference Part 1

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

Some questions about Adams conditionals

On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

The University of Strathclyde 16 Richmond St, Glasgow G1 1XQ

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

The Pursuit of Knowledge and the Problem of the Unconceived Alternatives ABSTRACT

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Final grades will be determined by 6 components: Midterm 20% Final 20% Problem Sets 20% Papers 20% Quizzes 10% Section 10%

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Explanationist Aid for the Theory of Inductive Logic

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Class 6 - Scientific Method

HIGH CONFIRMATION AND INDUCTIVE VALIDITY

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

How to Prove that There Is a God, God Is Real & the Universe Needs a God

Experimental Design. Introduction

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Statistical Inference Without Frequentist Justifications

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

145 Philosophy of Science

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

Statistics, Politics, and Policy

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Induction, Rational Acceptance, and Minimally Inconsistent Sets

MANAGEMENT RESEARCH: A THOUGHT ON VALIDITY OF POSITIVISM

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Review of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics by Thomas Hofweber Billy Dunaway University of Missouri St Louis

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Transcription:

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation Akinobu Harada ABSTRACT From the start of Popper s presentation of the problem about the way for confirmation of a hypothesis from the standpoint of anti-bayesianism, there have been various controversies among philosophers of science. Especially Howson and Gillies have argued much honestly the problem from their own point of view. The problem is still one of the most important interests in philosophy of science. This paper focuses on the problem with reference to the preceding discussions, not from the standpoint both of Bayesianism and of subjectivism of probability. This paper founds a new interpretation of probability from the view of scientific realism. It aims at giving a proposition that it is possible to solve Popper s problem by connecting a function of degree of confirmation with a new kind of probability interpreted here, and that the interpretation of probability is consistent with what is called the zero a priori probability of hypothesis. 1 Introduction 2 Popper on confirmation 3 Scientific realism-based interpretation 4 A probabilistic approach to Popper s problem of confirmation 1 Introduction Confirmation theory of hypothesis [1] has been one of the most important interests in philosophy of science since Popper[ l934] claimed that confirmation is not subject to the axioms of classical probability. With Popper s anti-bayesian thesis on confirmation as a trigger, this is still a matter of controversy among philosophers of science. Do we accept the statement that the problem of confirmation posed by Popper can be solved by interpreting validity of theory or hypothesis as nothing but severity of the test (or temporary justification of theory or hypothesis)? We will present a new interpretation of probability, based on scientific realism, after the nature of Popper s problem of confirmation is made clear. This paper aims for a new approach to the solution of Popper s problem in terms of scientific realism-based probability defined newly.

Finally we will claim that it is possible to connect a function of degree of confirmation with the new interpretation of probability, and that the interpretation of probability is consistent with what is called the zero a priori probability of hypothesis. 2 Popper on confirmation Let us write C(h,e) for the degree of confirmation of a hypothesis h given evidence e, and P(h,e) for the probability of h given e. We call C(h,e) a function of degree of confirmation of the hypothesis. We assume that P(h,e) is a probability function. It is a basic equation of equivalence based on the assumptions of Bayesianism that C(h,e) = P(h,e). However Popper denies the equivalence, and claims instead that C(h,e) P(h,e) and that the function of degree of confirmation is not a probability function. The reason why Popper thought of the inequivalence is what is called the zero a priori logical probability of hypothesis or law. He claims that in an infinite universe, the logical probability of a universal law, even upon the most favorable empirical evidence, will always equal zero (Popper[1983], p. 127). According to him, the inequivalence mentioned above is kept even though a hypothesis h is changed to a universal law. As anti-inductivist Popper rejects Bayesian form of inductive inference, C(h,e) is always zero and is meaningless because P(h,e) is ordinarily zero. Although Popper thought that C(h,e) P(h,e) and no law [hypothesis] is confirmable (Popper[1983], p. 127), he held hat C(h,e) can be defined in terms another form expressed as p(e,hb) - p(e,b) (Popper[1983], p.240). Here we have to pay attention to the fact that definition by Popper of the probability function p(*) is different from the P(*) in this paper. Popper presents the suggestion [2]...that we define C(h,e,b), that is the degree of corroboration of h by e in the presence of the background knowledge b, by the difference [3] p(e,hb) - p(e,b), where P(e,hb) means a measure of the degree of support given by e to h in the presence of the background knowledge b (Popper[1983], p.240). We here call Popper s suggestion of C(h,e,b) mentioned above Popper s problem [4] of confirmation, while Popper calls it the problem of degree of support or degree of corroboration (Popper[1983], p.240). We use the terms confirmation and corroboration as synonyms. 3 Scientific realism-based interpretation of probability Scientific realism [5] means an epistemological view that hypothetica1 (or theoretical) entities characterized by a true hypothesis (or theory) actually exist even though they cannot be directly observed and that evidence confirming a hypothesis (or theory) also serves to confirm the

existence of any hypothetical (or theoretical) realities characterized by that hypothesis (or theory). For instance, Robbins s economic man [6] is an economic hypothetical entity, and existing economic entity corresponding to it is me. From the point of view of scientific realism, there does exist an epistemological distance between hypothetical truth, (i.e., economic man as fiction) and the counterpart in reality (i.e., me as fact) of it. Therefore, concerning the distance, in a scientific realism-based inductive inquiry [7], we have to construct a ladder from the quantitative surface of an objective world to the qualitative underneath of the world, or a link between the inside of an analytical model and the outside of the model. Although the notion such as the ladder or the link depends on a unique interpretation of probability corresponding to the circumstance of the inquiry, scientific realism-based approach is not founded on the probability in classical statistics. Inductive reasoning needs to construct a logical bridge from a real entity to a hypothetical (or theoretical) entity corresponding to it. The bridge [8] is taken as a hypothetical device characterized by specific theory of probability. Now we define the scientific realism-based interpretation of probability as P*(<He,Re(e)>) given hypothetical entity He, and the counterpart of He, namely real entity Re(e) depending on empirical evidence e. P*(<He,Re(e)>) is subject to the following conditions. (P1) <A,B> is defined as a logical relation between an epistemological entity A and another entity B, and <A,B>=<B, A>. (P2) P*(<A,B>) stands for the probability based on scientific realism, which measures the strength of the logical relation <A,B>, and 0 P*(<A,B>) 1. (P3) P*(<A, A >) = 1. (P4) P*(<A, A c >)=0, where A c stands for an entity contradictory to A. (P5) P*(<Φ, A >)=0, Φ stands for a priori empty entity in the case that we cannot create in the face of perceiving the counterpart of A, namely stands for a priori an unidentified entity relative to the counterpart of A Finally, concerning whether the zero a priori probability of hypothesis presented by Popper holds for the scientific realism-based interpretation of probability, it is no problem because the zero a priori probability is just fit to the condition (P5) above mentioned. 4 A probabilistic approach to Popper s problem of confirmation Let us write h for a hypothetical proposition described in terms both of a real entity Re(e) implying a conclusion (i.e., a counterpart, transformed from statistical evidence, in reality of hypothetically-given entity He) and of a hypothetical entity He implying a premise. Then we can get the following equation: C(h,e) =P*(<He,Re(e)>). This is a probabilistic approach to Popper s problem of confirmation from the point of view

of scientific realism, as an alternative solution different both from the presentation based on Bayesianism by Howson[1973] and from the presentation based on subjective interpretation of probability by Gillies[1995]. Concerning the realistic structure of hypothesis, we think that the hypothesis h given evidence e is characterized by the real entity Re(e), which is based on the logical relation, on the assumption of hypothetical entity He which is the subject involved in the hypothesis. On emergence of Re(e), we have to rely on experience [9]. For instance, as an example of He in economics, we can immediately image the marginal propensity to consume (MWC), and as an example of Re(e), a counterpart of He, we can do the statistical estimator (β*1) relative to the regression coefficient of national disposable income (NDI) variable in the simple regression analysis of final consumption expenditure of households (FCEH) to NDI. Let us write h for a null hypothesis standing for MPC=0. In this case, C(h,e) = P*(<MPC, β*1>). Especially, in a statistical inquiry, if we can assume that Re(e) is a statistic (or random variable) with nominal distribution of probability given standard deviationσ, then we can realize that the linearly-transformed random variable Z = (Re(e) -He) /σ is subject to the standard normal distribution N(0, 1 2 ). Moreover, if there exist h and e such as: C(h,e) = P*(<He, the mean of Re(e) >), then we can get C(h,e) = 1. Notes [1] Gillies[1991] regards confirmation theory as a central area of philosophy of science (Gillies [1991],p.518). [2] About the original presentation of Popper s suggestion, see Popper[1934,p.400], where the relation between confirmation function and probability function is discussed tentatively. [3] Gillies[1995] calls the difference [the] central to Popper s account of corroboration (Gillies[1995Lp.115). [4] Gillies[1988] discusses the Popper s problem as an examination of Popper s argument against Bayesianism due to him. He presents perfectly a substitute solution to Popper s problem from the point of view of subjective interpretation of probability (Gillies[1988], pp. 192-195). [5] A realist economist Lawson defines scientific realism as the following. In fact any position might be designated a realism (in the philosophical sense of the term) that asserts the existence of some disputed kind of entity (such as black holes, class relations, economic equilibria, gravitons, tanon-neutrinos, utilities). Clearly on this definition we are all realists of a kind, and there are very much conceivable realisms. In science, a realist position, i.e. a

scientific realism, asserts that the ultimate objects of scientific investigation exist for the most part quite independent of, or at least prior to, their investigation (Lawson[1997], p. 15) [6] What a realist English-speaking economist Robbins explains about economic man as a hypothetical entity is as follows. Economic man is only an expository device-a first approximation used very cautiously at one stage in the development of arguments which, in their full development neither employ any such assumption nor demand it in any way for a justification of their procedure-it is improbable that he would be sure a universal bogey. (Robbins[1949], p. 97) [7] For instance, scientific realism-based econometrics (or econometric inference) discusses the measuring of counterpart in facts of econometric (or social) entity in economic theory. Such econometrics assumes the superiority of existence of a priori theoretical entities in scientific reasoning, where the hypothetical (or theoretica1) entities can be inferred inductively from real entities as the counterpart by the logical relation between real entities in facts and socia1 (or hypothetical ) entities in economic theory. Carnap refers to an inductive inference as following. That is, [w]hen an inductive inference is made in this way, from a sample to the population, from one sample to an unknown future sample, or from one Sample to an unknown future instance, I speak of it as indirect Probability inference or indirect inductive inference. (Carnap[1966], p. 39) [8] Positivist and anti-realist Keuzenkamp[2000] objects to the scientific realism in economics: in economics, the object is not independent of the subject. In other wards, behavior (like option pricing) is affected by economics (the option pricing model). An independent truth does not exist... The price elasticity of demand for doughnuts is not a real entity, existing outside the context of a specific economic model. (Keuzenkamp [2000], p. 216) Keuzenkamp does not approve that the logical relation (or correspondence) between He and Re(e) does exist and that the evidence which confirm a true hypothesis (or theory) also serves to confirm the existence of a hypothetical (or theoretical) entity characterized by the hypothesis (or theory). However I think that the object in economics can be inferred from the bridge from a real entity to a hypothetical entity regardless of dependence or independence of the observer. [9] On experience, Robbins considers it in relation to immediate acquaintance. In economics, as we have seen, the ultimate constituents of our fundamental generalizations are known to us by immediate acquaintance. In the natural sciences they are known to only inferentially. There is much less reason to doubt the counterpart in reality [i.e., a Re(e) ] of the assumption of individual preferences [i.e., a He] than that of the assumption of the electron. (Robbins[1949], p. 105)

References Carnap, R. [1966]: Philosophical Foundations of Physics, New York: Basic Books. Gillies, D. A. [1988]: 'Induction and Probability', in G. H. R. Parkinson (ed.), 1988, An Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge, pp. 179-204. Gillies, D. A. [1991] : Intersubjective Probability and Confirmation Theory, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 42, pp.513-533. Gillies, D. A [1995]: Popper s Contribution to the Philosophy of Probability, in Anthony O Hear (ed.), 1995, Popper: Philosophy and Problems, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 103-120. Howson, C. [1973]: Must the Logical Probability of Laws be Zero?, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24, pp. 153-163. Keuzenkamp, H. A. [2000] : Probability, Econometrics and Truth / the methodology of econometrics, Cambridge : Cambridge University Press. Lawson, T. [1997]: Economics and Reality, London: Routledge. Popper, K. R [1934]: The Logic of Scientific Discovery, English translation, London: Hutchinson, 1980. Popper, K. R. [1983]: Realism and the Aim of Science, London: Hutchinson, 1988. Robbins, L. [1949] : An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, London: Macmillan (first published in 1932).