The Protagoras: Judge... Jury... and Explication

Similar documents
Bitter Knowledge: Socrates and Teaching by Disillusionment Appendix A - the Protagoras

Unit 1 Guided Notes The Epic and Epic Heroes

Cover Design: Jim Manis. Copyright 1999 The Pennsylvania State University. The Pennsylvania State University is an equal opportunity university.

(born 470, died 399, Athens) Details about Socrates are derived from three contemporary sources: Besides the dialogues of Plato there are the plays

Plato BCE Republic, ca BCE

Coimisiún na Scrúduithe Stáit State Examinations Commission

The Power of Voice in Achilles. Pantelis Michelakis writes that the reception of Achilles into the arts and thoughts of the

Plato & Socrates. Plato ( B.C.E.) was the student of Socrates ( B.C.E.) and the founder of the Academy in Athens.

Metaphysics and Epistemology

Tufts University - Spring Courses 2013 CLS 0084: Greek Political Thought

Sophie s World. Chapter 4 The Natural Philosophers

Allusion Notebook. Source Citation: Dumas, Alexandre. The Three Musketeers. Trans. Lowell Bair. New York: Bantam Dell, 1984.

Socrates and Justice By Parviz Dehghani

Introduction "The Hero's Journey" track & field "The Odyssey" "Hero's Journey Template"

Conclusions are only Partial Truths. Plato tells us that oratory is the art of enchanting the soul (Phaedrus). In his piece,

Gorgias (Penguin Classics) By Walter Hamilton, Plato READ ONLINE

Excerpts from Aristotle

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS series TRINITY COLLEGE DUBLIN

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers

SOCRATES 469 BC BC ATHENS

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Can Excellence Be Taught?

Other traveling poets (called rhapsodes) memorized and recited these epics in the banquet halls of kings and noble families.

How the Aeneid ends. Denis Feeney

PROTAGORAS by Plato Get any book for free on:

Cleon Useful vs. Right 1) - The Mytilenian Debate was based around the fact that

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

TB_02_01_Socrates: A Model for Humanity, Remember, LO_2.1

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Greek & Roman Mythology. Jenny Anderson & Andrea Rake

The Sophists. Wednesday, February 24, 2016

The Relationship between Rhetoric and Truth. Plato tells us that oratory is the art of enchanting the soul (Phaedrus).

Mycenae. Heinrch Schleiman Excavations at Troy Discovered Mycenae

PETE BUMGARNER MINISTRIES

Lesser Hippias by Plato (see Appendix I)

The Charges Against Socrates

Can virtue be taught? Nature vs. Nurture Sophists But, what is virtue? Gorgias Protagoras Prodicus

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

GREAT WORKS TEACHING THE PRINCIPLES OF GLOBAL CITIZENSHIP GREAT HEARTS

The Rhetoric Of Morality And Philosophy: Plato's Gorgias And Phaedrus By Seth Benardete

John Paul II Catholic High School The Journey: A Spiritual Roadmap for Modern Pilgrims by Peter Kreeft

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Socratic Hubris; a Way to Understanding Socrates Trial and Execution

If we receive the testimony of men, the testimony of God is greater, for this is the testimony of God that he has borne concerning his Son.

CLAS 170: Greek and Roman Mythology Summer Session II, 2015 Course Syllabus

Thank You for Arguing: What Aristotle, Lincoln and Homer Simpson Can Teach Us About the Art of Persuasion. Author: Jay Heinrichs

Of All Professions, Prostitution is the Oldest (Except Possibly for Teaching)

Allegory of the Cave By Plato 380 B.C.

Copyright laws are changing all over the world, be sure to check the copyright laws for your country before posting these files!!

General Studies 145C: Antiquity

On Akrasia and Empathy

Coimisiún na Scrúduithe Stáit State Examinations Commission

Dear Incoming Students,

Multi-Paragraph Essay

Plato s Legacy: Whether the Republic or the Timaeus Reigns Supreme. Thomas Arralde, 2013

Plato s Protagoras: Negotiating Impartial, Common Standards of Discourse

Series: Walking by Faith # 2 The Commitment of Hannah 1 Samuel 1: 1-20

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

The Iliad -- Study Guide #1 -- Ancient Studies Tuttle/Rogers

Series: Battle Plan for Prayer - Sermon: Prayer Conditioning Luke 18:9-14 Pastor Jon Haakana

Protagoras By Plato 1

Meno. 70a. 70b. 70c. 71a. Cambridge University Press Meno and Phaedo Edited by David Sedley and Alex Long Excerpt More information

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Closing Arguments in Punishment

2017 Summer Reading & Writing Assignment AP English Literature & Composition (Mrs. Martling)

This Message Don t Take Away My Hopes

The Gospel Story: Not by Works A Study of Romans Romans 3:1-20 Pastor Bryan Clark

Ancient Philosophy. Cal State Fullerton Instructor: Jason Sheley

POLS 3000 INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL THEORY

Classical Civilisation

OUR NEED FOR DIRECTION

The Odyssey and The Iliad were written by Homer

Appendix: Socrates. Shanyu Ji. July 15, 2013

Commentary on Genesis 39:7-21 International Bible Lessons Sunday, January 1, 2012 L.G. Parkhurst, Jr.

(Genesis 39:7) And after a time his master s wife cast her eyes on Joseph and said, Lie with me.

AP English Literature & Composition 2018 Summer Reading & Writing Assignment

Plato s Meno. Socrates ( B.C.) Plato ( B.C.) Spring, The Agora in Athens 1/10/2008. But, what is virtue? Can virtue be taught?

Allegory of the Cave By Plato 380 B.C.

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

Supreme Court Script: Video: Justice Broderick arrives pile of papers in hand. Good morning

In champaign county court 101 E. Main st. Urbana IL James F. Osterbur 2191 county road 2500 E. St. Joseph IL

Lesson Plans 12: Argument and Piety in the Euthyphro e Civic Knowledge Project: Winning Words

The Context of Plato. CommonKnowledge. Pacific University. Michelle Bingaman Pacific University

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Collection and Division in the Philebus

The Assurance of God's Faithfulness

3.2 Demonstration of a Beneficial myth/hypothesis Protagoras

Advising Letter Department of Philosophy, Religion, and Classical Studies Spring 2019 Registration for Fall 2019 Term

Coimisiún na Scrúduithe Stáit State Examinations Commission

To Trust a Wife or Son. son and face the discontentment of the gods, or trust his wife and forever lose his only

LS 151L: Introduction to the Humanities Fall Semester 2011 Section 80 (71626): T Th 12:40 2:00 pm (DHC 117), Th 11:10-12:00 (NUULH)

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Apparently, the Jews were demanding witnesses to confirm that Jesus is who he claims to be. They

Shedding Grace. Summer Reading Assignment. Name

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Who is the Sophist? Problems and Approaches

Hi and welcomed back if you have watched any of the previous videos. My name is Tim Spiess and

Introduction to Ethics

Gorgias (Agora Editions) By Plato, James H. Nichols Jr. READ ONLINE

Toronto School of Communication

Transcription:

Anthós (1990-1996) Volume 1 Number 3 Article 8 6-1992 The Protagoras: Judge... Jury... and Explication Patrick Hamilton Portland State University Let us know how access to this document benefits you. Follow this and additional works at: http://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/anthos_archives Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons, and the Epistemology Commons Recommended Citation Hamilton, Patrick (1992) "The Protagoras: Judge... Jury... and Explication," Anthós (1990-1996): Vol. 1: No. 3, Article 8. Available at: http://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/anthos_archives/vol1/iss3/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Anthós (1990-1996) by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. For more information, please contact pdxscholar@pdx.edu.

THE PROTAGORAS: JUDGE... JURY... AND EXPLICATION Patrick Hamilton I n The Protagoras, Plato uses a myriad of methods and structures in order to portray the people and circumstances under which the dialogue takes place. While the discussion contained within the dialogue takes up the subject of virtue, the dialogue itself is not constrained to this single topic. Instead, it presents many different sides to the characters and situations held within, in addition to the different sides of the question of virtue presented within. In The Protagoras Plato first sets up the circumstances under which the dialogue will be told. This narrative frame opens as Socrates meets an unnamed friend who, when he fmds out that Socrates has just talked with Protagoras, whom Socrates describes as "the wisest man now living" (Protagoras and Meno, 309), asks Socrates to tell him of their conversation. This Socrates does enthusiastically. How this simple conversation sets up the circumstances of the dialogue is not revealed until much later in the dialogue, when Socrates and Protagoras nearly end their conversation. At this point, Socrates says "... I have something to do and could not stay while you spin out your long speeches, I will leave you. I really ought to be going" (Protagoras and Meno, 330). Here, Socrates claims that he cannot stay with the conversation 65

as another appointment takes precedence, and he repeats the same excuse when he does finally take his leave at the end of the dialogue. Yet when his friend approaches him on the street, just after he has left the discussion, he promptly begins the lengthy recapitulation of the discussion. Socrates is lying in saying he must go away in order to leave the house of Callias; this further casts doubt upon the truth of the actual conversation, as the story of that discussion is told only by Socrates. One would be quick to conclude that the story Socrates tells may not be true, and may even decide that it is based on this information. Yet, if one looks at Socrates' stoty, it becomes obvious that he is more than likely telling the truth, for throughout the dialogue and conversation with Protagoras, Socrates himself is constantly portrayed as petty and manipulative. If Socrates was indeed lying about the events that had just occurred, he surely would not have portrayed himself as such. In this way, though Socrates is still shown to be a liar as detailed earlier, one is safe in assuming that what he says occurred with Protagoras is the trutl1. From here, Socrates begins to describe the course of events that brought him to the house of Callias and to the meeting with Protagoras. Now the only reason Socrates went to see Protagoras was at the request of Hippocrates, who came to him for his help in becoming one of Protagoras' followers. The circumstances under which Hippocrates asks for Socrates' assistance are an example of Plato's constant use of symbolism and allusion. Hippocrates comes to Socrates in the pre-dawn hours, while it is still dark. While waiting for light to break, the two men go out into the courtyard and Socrates begins to test Hippocrates to see if he knows what he will be getting himself involved with. One aspect of this conversation is that it takes place while it is gradually getting lighter and, when it is light, the two men have reached the house of Callias. This movement from dark to light is an often used symbol of the movement from ignorance to knowledge, and this instance is 66

no different. Hippocrates came to Socrates ignorant of what he was truly asking for, effectively in the dark, and Socrates proceeded to enlighten him, corresponding with the gradual break of day. Yet there is also a second allusion in this section, one that is continually prevalent throughout the dialogue. The circumstance of Hippocrates coming to Socrates for his help is one of many allusions by Plato to the structures of law courts and trials. Hippocrates comes to Socrates for his help in "pleading his case" to Protagoras, in effect, engaging Socrates' services as a lawyer. This allusion is particularly interesting in that Socrates himself was subject to a trial and condemned to death himself during the "Tyranny of the Thirty." Yet, in this "trial," the situation is reversed and Socrates is instead the questioner instead of the one being accused. This idea of a trial is a strong aspect of the structure of Socrates' discussion with Protagoras. But before the trial can begin, Socrates and Hippocrates face one obstacle, an obstacle that Plato again uses as an allusion to an important part of Greek culture, that of the Homeric epics. When Socrates and Hippocrates reach the house of Callias, a' porter answers the door and promptly slams it on the two, calling them Sophists. Socrates then explains that "it seemed likely that the crowd of Sophists had put him in a bad temper." When the porter answers again, Socrates says "My good man... we are not Sophists. Cheer up" (Protagoras and Meno, 313, 314) and bids the porter to let him and Hippocrates in. While this also clearly shows Socrates' opinion of Sophists, as he decides that the presence of the Sophists has had an adverse effect on the porter, while his own will do nothing of the sort, it also clearly alludes to Homer, specifically The Odyssey. When Odysseus journeys into the underworld, before meeting with the seer Tiresias, he encounters a gatekeeper who also is in a bad temper. Allusions to Homer continue immediately after Socrates has 67

passed the porter and enters into the presence of Protagoras and his Sophists. In typical Homeric style, he' goes through and lists each person present, much like the cataloging Homer did in The Iliad. And while he is listing the Sophists, Socrates continues to borrow from Homer with two quotes from The Odyssey, again from Book 11, when Odysseus jotlrneys into the underworld. By the use of these quotes, Socrates effectively says that by entering this house, he has journeyed into Hell and all around him are just shades. Yet while Odysseus meets the shades of other heroes in his search for Tiresias, who gives him knowledge of his journey home, Socrates is instead seeking the exact opposite. He is meeting, instead of heroes, living fools (in his opinion) as he seeks out the biggest fool of all, Protagoras, whom Socrates will eventually prove to be ignorant. At this point, the discussion between Socrates and Protagoras truly begins. Now, just as there were two ways of looking at Socrates' conversation with Hippocrates, there are two ways of looking at the conversation between him and Protagoras. These are the earlier mentioned structure of a trial, and also as a form of an aristocracy. This aristocracy is dearly displayed by the fact that the conversation takes place only between Socrates and Protagoras, while the rest of the men present only listen. Even though the actual request is on the part of Hippocr!tes, it is Socrates and only Socrates who presents it and Hippocrates remains silent, as if he were not able or of sufficient standing to present his request. The idea of only certain people taking part in the conversation and decisions is continued throughout the dialogue. \Vhen the two men ftrst disagree, it is Callias, Alcibiades, Critias, Prodicus and Hippias who convince them to continue. Of these five men, Callias was walking with Protagoras and Hippias was (/sitting on a seat of honor" (Plato, 314) when Socrates entered. Critias enters with Alcibiades who is, of course, highly favored 68

by Socrates and Socrates himself praises Prodicus as a genius. All of these men, in different ways, represent an aristocracy, as they are all highly regarded and make the decision to continue the discussion between Protagoras and Socrates. The allusion to the structures of a trial, being more prevalent throughout the dialogue, also sets up a series of roles based on that structure for the characters taking part in the conversation: Socrates, Protagoras, and the surrounding Sophists. Socrates and Protagoras function as both questioners and answerers, as they switch these roles throughout their conversation. The circle of men around them serve as a type of jury, as they would applaud when one of the men made a stirring speech or proved a point. Also, when Socrates and Hippocrates entered, the men were in a procession about Protagoras, similar to the way a jury would enter into a courtroom. The role of judge is fujfilled by both Prodicus and Hippias jointly. Hippias, as mentioned earlier, was seated in honor, much like a judge would be. Prodicus enters the room where the conversation takes place from his "chambers," swathed in robes as a judge would be and is also the last person to enter the room which is also a characteristic of a judge. At this point, with all the roles established, the discussion truly begins. Protagoras is the first to answer the question of whether or not virtue can be taught, but the way in which he proves his opinion is interesting in that it is the exact opposite of what Protagoras is supposed to represent. Protagoras is supposed to be the wisest and, consequently, the most advanced person present. Yet his opening argument is to tell the myth of Prometheus and how man gained the gifts of art and serne of respect ai].d justice. Then he shows how men are taught, through punishment, correct morals, and virtue. The use of the mythic opening is interesting in that, while it does help "prove" Protagoras' point, the actual existence of it is something he is supposed to be superior to. 69 «

Once Protagoras has finished, Socrates feigns being awestruck at his eloquence, much like he did in The Phaedrus when Phaedrus fmished his oration of Lysias' speech. As he was in The Phaedrus Socrates was not impressed by the speech and was fully prepared to question it and its maker. The tactic Socrates uses is to question one single aspect of the speech made by Protagoras, as Socrates begins his first role as questioner. Instead of displaying support for his own position, he instead seeks to undermine Protagoras' by examining one minute aspect of his speech and leading Protagoras around by his nose until he contradicts himself, which is not accomplished by Socrates as he and Protagoras reach the point at which they first decide to end the conversation. In this disagreement, the rest of the men in the room participate in the conversation for the first time. When the two speakers are unable to come to terms in order to continue their discussion, Callias, A1cibiades and Critias all offer "evidence," acting almost as witnesses to why they should continue. Prodicus and Hippias fulml their role as judges, as, after the "witnesses" finish, they both make general statements of why the discussion should continue, much like a true judge would compel a trial to continue. The solution to this problem is reached by Socrates himself, who proposes that he and Protagoras switch roles as questioner and answerer, in order for Socrates to "show him how, in [his] submission, the respondent should speak" (Plato, 334), as the source of the argument was that Socrates complained of Protagoras' answers being too long for him to follow. This again shows Socrates' true opinion of Protagoras for, though he earlier praised him as wise, he now is going to show hiin his faults. Protagoras, now acting as questioner, begins by asking Socrates to explain an apparent discrepancy in a poem by Simonides. When faced with this challenge, Socrates calls on Prodicus as a "witness" and in doing so, again quotes Homer. The quote comes from Book 21 of The Iliad, when Achilles 70

was battling Skamandros. Skainandros called on his brother for assistance in defeating Achilles. But, in fear that he could be defeated, Hera sent Achilles assistance in the form of Hephaestus who forced Skamandros back. This passage being invoked here by Socrates alludes to the fact that, unless Protagoras is aided from some other quarter, he will be defeated by the combination of Socrates and Prodicus. That is exactly what happens as the discrepancy is resolved by the two by the fact that the word "hard" in the poem had a different meaning for Simonides and that there was no discrepancy. By this explanation, Socrates succeeds in showing Protagoras' ignorance, as he vehemently denied the existence of two meanings that truly did exist. But not only is Protagoras shown to be lacking is this section, so is Socrates again shown to be a liar. His objection to continuing the argument was that Protagoras' answers were too long. Yet, in his explanation of the poem, Socrates himself begins an equally lengthy speech in interpretation. His ability to form and follow a line of thought throughout a speech is clearly shown here and his earlier objections are shown to be false. Once Socrates has finished his defense, Protagoras silently refuses to continue with the agreed upon rules, in which he now becomes answerer. Socrates answers for him as he again quotes from Homer, again from The Iliad. The quote is from Book loin which Diomedes chose Odysseus to accompany him in infiltrating the City of Troy. In the circumstances of the discussion/trial, Socrates could be seen as readying an assault on Protagoras, which in fact he does, resuming his ironical role of questioner, considering his fate to come. Socrates again returns to the same minute point that he examined in Protagoras' original speech, once again leading Protagoras into contradicting himself, which he is able to accomplish this time. In the process of this questioning, Socrates again continues a lengthy line of thought, the same of which he claimed to be incapable. But Socrates does manage to make his point, that 71

virtue cannot be taught. At this point, the discussion ends and Socrates takes his leave, again citing his fictional other appointment. The structures that Plato uses throughout this dialogue all selve to give more detail to the circumstances and characters that are within the confmes of the dialogue. They succeed in showing the different sides of the participating members, through the exchange of roles and multiple allusions, even as they themselves debate the different sides of the question of virtue. 72

Works Cited Plato. The Protagoras and Meno. Trans. W.K.C. Guthrie. Harmonclsworth, Middlesex, 1956. - - -. Phaedrns and Letters VII and VIII. Trans. Walter Hamilton. Ed. Betty Raidce. London: Penguin Group, 1973. 73