Foreword to the second edition

Similar documents
Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

FROM THE ACT OF JUDGING TO THE SENTENCE

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Critical Scientific Realism

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Presentism and eterrnalism HAROLD W. NOONAN. Department of Philosophy. University of Nottingham. Nottingham, NG72RD, UK. Tel: +44 (0)

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Introduction to Philosophy

Published in Mind, 2000, 109 (434), pp

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Undergraduate Calendar Content

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Are All Universals Instantiated?

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT]

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

CONTENTS III SYNTHETIC A PRIORI JUDGEMENTS. PREFACE CHAPTER INTRODUCTldN

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

PHILOSOPHY. Minor in Philosophy. Philosophy, B.A. Ethical theory: One course required. History: Two courses required.

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

KNOWLEDGE OF SELF AND THE WORLD

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

What is consciousness? Although it is possible to offer

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Kant and his Successors

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

CONCRETE UNIVERSALS AND SPATIAL RELATIONS* ANTTI KESKINEN University of Tampere. MARKKU KAINÄNEN University of Helsinki

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Experiences Don t Sum

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Metaphysical Dependence and Set Theory

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

Stephen Mumford Metaphysics: A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press, Oxford ISBN: $ pages.

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Brandeis University Fall 2015 Professor Andreas Teuber

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Anti-)Realisms: The Metaphysical Issue. Publisher Editions Kimé

CONTENTS. CHAPTER 1. CHAPTER II. THE PROBLEM OF DESCARTES, -

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Philosophy Courses-1

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Oakland Philosophy Courses

Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis

Nikolay Milkov NEITHER VERIFIERS NOR VERIFICATORS: THE REFUTATION OF THE THEORY OF TRUTH-MAKING

The British Empiricism

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Transcription:

Foreword to the second edition After fifteen years, a second edition of Ontological Investigations will now appear. It contains three appendices: First, a summary of the conclusions of the book in aphoristic form; second, a piece on universals which provides a more elaborate defence of my realist point of departure; and, third, an appendix on ontology in information science, a topic which is also addressed in this Foreword. 1. Ontology and information science At the time when Ontological Investigations was being written, the term 'ontology' was slowly entering the world of information science. It is easy to understand why. A philosopher ontologist is someone who tries to capture large chunks of the abstract structure of the world. In doing so, of course, he (or she) has to use concepts. But he is using these concepts only in order to say something about the world. He is not looking at concepts in order to find conceptual connections between them. When I say that the English word "cat," the German word "Katze," and the Swedish word "katt" are synonymous, then I am looking at the concept that the three words have in common. But when I make an assertion by using the words "The cat is on the mat," then I am using the concept cat in order to speak about a cat in the world. The assertions in this book are like "The cat is on the mat," though more general and abstract. Knowledge engineers in information science look at concepts and conceptual models. But they need classifications of very abstract concepts for their work, and, rather naturally, they have chosen to call these abstract classifications "ontologies," too. I once gave a brief talk at an ΑΙ-workshop about the difference between using concepts to denote entities in the world and viewing concepts as entities in themselves. It is here published as appendix 3. Out of every philosophical ontology, one can construe an ontology for knowledge engineers. Conversely, every information science ontology can (if only for the peculiar purposes of the philosopher) be regarded as an hypothesis about the abstract structure of the world and as such serve as an object of philosophical discussion. Now, just as ordinary engineers can often reach their practical goals more efficiently with theoretically obsolete

theories (such as Newtonian mechanics) drawn from the natural sciences rather than with more truthlike ones such as quantum mechanics, so it might well be the case that knowledge engineering can be done more efficiently with bad philosophical ontologies than with truthlike ones. At the moment, however, there seems to be nothing in particular that speaks in favour of such a view. (I find it nice that I am, while writing this foreword, working in a place - the Institute for Formal Ontology and Medical Information Science at the University of Leipzig - where the relationship between philosophical ontologies and information science ontologies has been put on the agenda.) 2. Ontology and political correctness At the beginning of sub-chapter 15.7, I report that "This theory of categories of mine is marxist in inspiration and (to a lesser extent) as regards the problems dealt with, but somewhat analytic in its way of handling these problems. The resulting ontology, however, is most closely related to the positions of two philosophers who belong neither to marxism nor to analytic philosophy: Aristotle and Hussserl." When I wrote the book I was a Marxist and a so-called Euro-Communist (that is, I believed in the combination of planned economy, democracy, and independence from the Soviet Union), and I did as much as I could to stress overlaps between my ontological views and those of classical Marxism. In particular, I did three things: I wrote the sub-chapter 15.7 on "Marxist dialectics and intentionality"; I stressed (in chapter 2) the fact that Friedrich Engels put forward a kind of level ontology; and (in chapter 16.1) that not only Karl Popper, but also Lenin, has claimed that truth can admit of degrees. I even coined the expression "the Lenin-Popper position on truth." Retrospectively, I can now see that I am almost certainly the only one who has ever found this expression funny. As far as I can see, one can without inconsistency combine the realist ontology of my book with both a conservative, a liberal, a socialist, and a feminist political philosophy. This notwithstanding the fact that during the 90s of the last century many philosophically-minded socialists and feminists were radical social constructivists who denied the existence of a mind-independent world about which knowledge can be obtained. Note that I am not saying that each and every part of an ontology has to be VIII

ideologically neutral, parts of the ontology of human nature are probably not. Furthermore, if the belief that the whole of nature is imbued with mind or spirit is regarded as a political ideology, as a kind of "ecologism," then not even this book is ideologically neutral. It denies such a view. 3. Ontology and natural theology Most contemporary Western theologians seem to think that talk of God can have no ontological import whatsoever. Religion, they say, is "merely a language game." However, there are some religious philosophers and some theologians who think otherwise. They think one can rationally argue about the existence of God, even though, for them, the question is both normatively and emotionally loaded. That is, they believe in what the medievals called natural theology. Now, so do I; I regard it as part of ontology. My conclusion, however, differs from theirs. In my considered judgement, the spatiotemporal whole in which we live is for its existence not dependent on any "higher" and non-spatiotemporal existent. In my opinion and in this book, space-time is at the end of the ontological dependence line, though I do not anywhere in the book argue that this has to be the case. This fact, I want all prospective natural theologian readers to notice. 4. Ontology and analytic philosophy As a student in philosophy in Gothenburg, Sweden, I was trained and educated within analytic philosophy. This tradition, though, has been very heterogeneous. For instance, Cambridge analytic philosophy (in particular, Bertrand Russell) and Austrian analytic philosophy (i.e., followers of Franz Brentano such as Alexius Meinong) affirmed ontology, whereas logical positivism and Oxford analytic philosophy after "the linguistic turn" denied it. I wrote my book in the wake of the appearance (1978) of David Armstrong's two-volume book Universals and Scientific Realism, in which an anti-platonist immanent realist position on universals is defended. I thought, quite mistakenly, that Armstrong's Aristotelianism would progressively conquer the Anglo-American and Scandinavian strongholds of analytic philosophy. Therefore, I took very lightly the defence of my realist point of departure, which comprises just a few pages in chapters 1.3 IX

and 1.4. I hope that in this edition this mistake is somewhat remedied by appendix 2 and by the three paragraphs below. Obviously, we regard our everyday mesoscopic world as perceivable and as containing numerically different things with many different properties. Often, several things are perceived as having the same property. In such perceptions there seems to be an immediate revelation to the effect that the world contains universals. If one perceives, let's say on a tennis court, three exactly similar spherical balls, one may find it obvious that, independently of language and of relations of resemblance, there are three different things that are qualitatively identical with respect to their shape. Apart from numerical identity and difference, the world seems to contain qualitative identity and difference; and where there is qualitative identity there is a universal. Every non-aristotelian view of universals seems to contain some flagrantly non-commonsensical stain. The non-realisms of conceptualism and predicate nominalism imply a complete denial of mind-independent properties such as shape; everything that is universal is said to belong to concepts or predicates. The essence of the non-realism of trope nominalism is the astonishing view that every property is necessarily only a once-andfor-all occurrent. Platonist realism, on the other hand, posits the existence of universals outside space and time plus a peculiar relation of "participation in" between the spherical tennis balls in this world and a universal sphericality outside this world. Immanent realism, with its view that universals have a repeatable existence in - and only in - the ordinary spatiotemporal world, may seem to lack a corresponding remarkable peculiarity, but this is not quite true. When worked out in its details, such a realism has to claim that one single universal can be wholly present in several different things that are spatially or temporally scattered. Prima facie, this is a bit odd, too, which means that all positions on the problem of universals are odd. But they are not equally so. Immanent realism is the least odd position, and the existence of universals in re is the best explanation of the kind of property perceptions mentioned. According to Plato, all instances of a certain universal participate in "their" universal. According to my brand of immanent realism, it is rather the other way round: a universal participates in all its instances. Here come five views of mine: X

(i) there are universale, but there are no universale outside the spatiotemporal world; (ii) since a universal can have many instances, it cannot be identical with any of its instances; (iii) since a set does not exist in any of its elements (a set has elements), a universal cannot be identical with the set of its instances (or e.g. with a set of tropes); (iv) since a mereological sum does not exist in any of its parts (it has parts), a universal cannot be identical with the mereological sum of its instances (or with such a sum of tropes); (v) since a spatiotemporal aggregate does not exist in any of the aggregated units, a universal cannot be identical with the aggregate of its instances (or with any aggregate of tropes). Besides Armstrong's book, there is another great analytic-philosophical book that I would like to mention, namely John Searle's Intentionality (1983). Here, language is ontologically embedded. I read it in 1984, but, unfortunately, I only had time to comment on it in footnotes in the first edition of this book. Had it appeared some years earlier, I would have tried to stand on its shoulders in the way I tried to do with Armstrong's book (see chapter 1.3). Having paid this truly earnest homage to Armstrong and Searle, I want to make another point perfectly clear. Armstrong has defended immanent realism with respect to universale, but he has also (mistakenly) tried to reduce intentional states to ordinary material states. Searle, on the other hand, has (rightly) argued that intentional states are non-reducible entities, but he regards (mistakenly) the problem of universals as merely a conceptual muddle not worth the attention of serious philosophers. There is, though, one great philosopher who has defended both a kind of immanent realism for universals ("species") and the non-reducibility of intentional states, namely Edmund Husserl. Furthermore, Husserl laid bare the existence of different kinds of "relations of existential dependence," and the latter, as will become clear, are absolutely crucial to my ontology. In spite of his "transcendental turn," I regard Husserl as the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century. Back to analytic philosophy. I know neither who has coined the term analytic metaphysics nor exactly when it came into common use. But I XI

know that it was not available to me when I wrote Ontological Investigations. Had it been, then I would have made clear that, while each chapter in the book can be regarded as a piece of analytic metaphysics, it would be nonetheless misleading to give the whole book such an epithet. Why? Because the book is an attempt at systematic metaphysics, too. In my opinion, analytic and systematic metaphysics are too distinct endeavours which should however be approached in tandem. Systematic metaphysics ought to be done the way analytic metaphysics is done, and systematic metaphysics is needed even by those who have no urge for a complete ontology; they need it as a consistency test of all the fragmentary presumed truths they have come to accept when visiting various corners of analytic metaphysics. If one has taken definite stands on the problems of, say, universale, causality, and the mind-body relation, then one ought also to ask oneself if the three positions taken are consistent with each other. If one concludes that they are, then one has entered the domain of systematic metaphysics. Armstrong, Searle, and Husserl, are systematic metaphysicians in this sense, and so also were Aristotle and Plato. 5. Ontology and epistemology Leibniz claimed (and I agree) that even an omnipotent God would have to stay within the framework of logical truths. Analogously, I would like to claim that even an omnipotent epistemology (which I do not believe exists) would have to stay within the framework of ontology. Just take a look at Descartes and Kant. Descartes claimed that philosophy ought to start with an all-embracing systematic doubt. But when he tried to doubt everything, he came to the conclusion that, for sure, a thinking enduring substance exists. Some of his contemporaries complained, rightly, that he should have confined himself to the conclusion that necessarily a "thought" or a "something" exists. My point is that one cannot rationally claim that nothing at all exists. Every epistemology has to start with some ontology. In Kant, this fact comes out in the following way. He claimed that philosophy ought to start with an investigation of the faculty of knowing; but, then, he presupposed the existence of such a faculty. As is clearly stated in the last chapter of the book, I regard substantive epistemological investigations as regional-ontological investigations, and I XII

regard all regional-ontological investigations such as those made in the book as fallible. 6. Ontology and ontological thinking Since the publishing of the first edition of the book in 1989,1 have in some articles been able to make some of the ideas put forward more clear and distinct. These articles are listed below and related to different chapters. Chapter 1.1: Hume's Scottish Kantianism, in the Polish journal Ruch Filozoficny LIX (2002), 421-53. (Here, in contradistinction to the book, I make a real attempt to unravel David Hume's ontology.) Chapters 1.3 and 1.4: Determinables as Universale, The Monist 83 (2000), 101-21; see appendix 2. Chapter 2: Hartmann's Nonreductive Materialism, Superimposition, and Supervenience, Axiomathes XIII (2001), 1-21. Critical Notice of Armstrong's and Lewis' Concepts of Supervenience, SATS - Nordic Journal of Philosophy 3 (2002), 118-22. The Asymmetries of Property Supervenience, in S. Lindström & P o. Sundström (eds.), Physicalism, Consciousness, and Modality, Umeä Preprints in Philosophy 2002:1,95-124. (In chapter 2, I ought to have mentioned the fact that the proposed ontology contains relations of supervenience, but I didn't.) Chapters 4.1, 4.5, and 11.2: Physical addition, in R. Poli & P. Simons (eds.), Formal Ontology, (Kluwer: Amsterdam 1996), 277-88. Presuppositions for Realist Interpretations of Vectors and Vector Addition, in U. Meixner & P. Simons (eds.), Proceedings of the 22nd international Wittgenstein Symposium 1999, (öbv&hpt: Wien 2001), Chapter 5: Functions, Function Concepts, and Scales, The Monist 86 (2004), Chapter 6: Pattern as an Ontological Category, in N. Guarino (ed.), Formal Ontology in Information Systems, (IOS Press: Amsterdam 1998), Chapter 8: Marty on Grounded Relations, in K. Mulligan (ed.). Mind, Meaning and Metaphysics, (Kluwer: Amsterdam 1990), 151-56. XIII

Chapter 13.5: Intentionality and Tendency: How to make Aristotle up-to-date, in K. MuMijgan ^ed^), Language, Truth and Ontology, (Kluwer: Amsterdam Chapter 13.7: Perception as the Bridge Between Nature and Life-World, in C. Bengt-Pedersen & N.Thomassen (eds.), Nature and Life-World, (Odense UP: Odense 1998), 113-37. Chapter 14: The Unnoticed Regional Ontology of Mechanisms, Axiomathes* VIII (1997), 411-28. Chapter 15: Stearic's Monadological Construction of Social Reality, in D. Koepsell & L.S. Moss (eds.), John Searle's Ideas About Social Reality, (Blackwell: Oxford 2СГОЗ), 233-55. 7. Ontological gratitude First, I want to thank the publisher and ontologist Rafael Hüntelmann for taking the risk of publishing this volume. Second, I want to thank Kevin Mulligan and Barry Smith for having helped me, supported me, encouraged me, and discussed with me for more than twenty years now, and for having urged me to try to get a second edition published. Leipzig in February 2004, Ingvar Johansson XIV