PROOF. contents. vii. Series editors preface. Ancient 1 Modern 25 Postmodern 45 Conclusion 66. Further reading 71 Index 75

Similar documents
Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Thinking Ethically: A Framework for Moral Decision Making

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Ethics From Moral Intuition To Moral Theory

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Introduction to Ethics

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Definitions: Values and Moral Values

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Time: 3hrs. Maximum marks: 75. Attempt five questions in all. All questions carry equal marks. The word limit to answer each question is 1000 words.

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Philosophy. The unexamined life is not worth living. Plato. O More College of Design Mission Statement

Introduction to Ethics

DEIRDRE N. McCLOSKEY. etmzeou ETHICS FOR AN AGE OF COMMERCE THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS JP CHICAGO AND LONDON

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

#NLCU. The Ethical Leader: Rules and Tools

LYING TEACHER S NOTES

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Introduction to Ethics

ETHICAL THEORY. Burkhardt - Chapter 2 - Ethical Theory

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Ethical non-naturalism

ETHICS (IE MODULE) 1. COURSE DESCRIPTION

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Lecture 8: Deontology and Famine. Onora O Neill Kantian Deliberations on Famine Problems Peter Horban Writing a Philosophy Paper

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Wednesday, March 26, 14. Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Course Syllabus Ethics PHIL 330, Fall, 2009

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Revolution and Reaction: Political Thought From Kant to Nietzsche

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Philosophical Ethics Syllabus-Summer 2018

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

all three components especially around issues of difference. In the Introduction, At the Intersection Where Worlds Collide, I offer a personal story

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

PHIL1010: PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PROFESSOR ROBIN MULLER M/TH: 8:30 9:45AM OFFICE HOURS: BY APPOINTMENT

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Chapter 1 The Activity of Philosophy 2 Chapter 2 Philosophy's History 10 Chapter 3 Philosophy and the Examined life 18

Utilitarianism pp

Tools Andrew Black CS 305 1

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

In the Fall PEs many people who wrote about ethics as an Area of Knowledge indicated that ethical perspectives were always a matter of personal

An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

what makes reasons sufficient?

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers

Ancient & Medieval Virtue Ethics

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Introduction to. Ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Duty Based Ethics. Ethics unit 3

WINGED CUPID PAINTED BLIND: THE GREEN WORLD AS A MIRAGE

Enlightenment, Reason, Religion, and Knowledge

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

The Problem of Normativity

Outline Lesson 2 - Philosophy & Ethics: Says Who?

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

IN OUR AND LIKENESS IMAGE. Creation in our image

Morality in the Modern World (Higher) Religious, Moral and Philosophical Studies (Higher)

Are There Moral Facts

University of York, UK

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

Sandra Rhoten Associate Dean of Students Student Conduct

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Introduction to Ethics

Jacob. Wrestle or Rest - which is it to be?

Logical Appeal (Logos)

The Tao Te Ching/The Tao of Love. Introduction

Nation, Science and Religion in Nehru s Discovery of India

The Nature of Law. Unit One: Heritage CLU3M. C. Olaveson

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Transcription:

& contents Series editors preface vii Ancient 1 Modern 25 Postmodern 45 Conclusion 66 Further reading 71 Index 75 v

Part One & ancient How shall I act? How shall I act? That is the question. It is a question blurted out at a moment of crisis, a question he never meant to ask, at least not aloud. Neoptolemus, son of the slain Achilles, is facing an acute ethical problem. The play is Sophocles Philoctetes (Athens, 409 BCE). Neoptolemus has been brought by Ulysses from Troy, where they are both leaders of the Greek army besieging the city, to the island of Lemnos. They have come to Lemnos because this is where, years ago, on his way to Troy, Ulysses had abandoned Philoctetes. Philoctetes, an erstwhile companion of the demi-god Hercules, had suffered an incurable snake bite, leaving him with a stinking wound and in intolerable pain. His cries of pain were damaging morale and interrupting important sacrificial rituals, and so Ulysses, bowing to pressure from more powerful Greek leaders, left him on the deserted island before sailing on to Troy. Unfortunately for 1

theatre & ethics Ulysses and the Greek leaders, however, it turns out that Philoctetes possesses a bow and arrows which, according to prophecy, are the weapons which will secure for the Greeks victory in their war on Troy. So Ulysses has brought young Neoptolemus a Greek leader whom Philoctetes has never met, and against whom, therefore, he bears no grudge to entrap Philoctetes and bring him to Troy, where, the Greeks hope, he will use his bow and arrows and bring the war to a successful conclusion. In the opening scene of the play, as they set foot on the island, Ulysses reveals to Neoptolemus the purpose of their mission. Neoptolemus is to present himself to Philoctetes as a fellow victim of the Greek leadership, with a concocted story about having been deprived by the Greek leaders of his right to his dead father s weapons. Neoptolemus, a young man of virtue, is initially horrified at the proposition that he should lie to obtain Philoctetes trust: Rather, much rather would I fall by virtue / Than rise by guilt to certain victory, he tells Ulysses (p. 208). Ulysses, however, soon persuades him, arguing fi rst that the ends (victory over Troy) justify the means (lying to Philoctetes): We need not blush at aught / That may promote our interest and success (p. 210). Ulysses follows this up with the promise that Neoptolemus will win a double prize for going along with his cunning plan: he will gain a reputation for being both valiant and wise (p. 211). This seems to do the trick. Ulysses withdraws and Neoptolemus heads into the interior of the island in search of his stinking, pain-wracked victim. 2

He soon fi nds his man and presents his pack of lies. Philoctetes almost inevitably falls for it, expressing passionate sympathy for the young man, who, in his turn, agrees, out of pity for a man so deeply affl icted, to rescue him from the desert island. With bonds of pity and sympathy established, Philoctetes even allows Neoptolemus to take hold of his miraculous bow and arrows. Philoctetes falls into an appalling spasm of renewed agony, as though he were about to die, and it is as he recovers consciousness that Neoptolemus, his hands literally on the prize, experiences his ethical crisis. How shall I act? he asks himself. One version of ethical thought, held by the Greek philosopher Aristotle, among others, is that ethics rests in the character of an individual. The improvement of your character and the fulfi lment of its potential is the aim of ethics, and, indeed, of life itself, according to Aristotle. However, Neoptolemus agreed to go along with Ulysses against his better judgement, or his sense of his own virtue because he was persuaded that in doing so he would be serving a higher cause. He might have imagined that he was acting ethically because his action could be defi ned as seeking the greatest good of the greatest number of people. This is the basis for what is often called utilitarian ethics, generally associated with the English philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1748 1832) and the Scottish philosopher James Mill (1773 1836). Although Neoptolemus might feel uneasy about compromising his character as a man who does not lie, the greater good (victory over Troy) of the greater number (the Greeks as a whole) ought to prevail over his personal sense of virtue. 3

theatre & ethics He might also have been guided by a belief that his actions amounted to the fulfi lment of the will of the Gods, made clear in the prophecy that only Philoctetes and his magical bow and arrows would bring about victory over Troy. This would be another kind of ethical argument, in which ethical action consists in following pre-determined rules. In some cultures at some moments in history, ethics has tended to be defi ned in just these terms: you do as you are told by religious authorities. In some cultures at other moments in history, the belief that you should do as you are told by religious authorities has been challenged. Sometimes the commandments of religion seem to come into confl ict with other reasons and desires for action. It is at such moments that an ethical crisis occurs. Sophocles Philoctetes dramatises just such a crisis. Neoptolemus own ethical judgement seems to be in confl ict not only with the judgement of the famously wise (and wily) senior leader Ulysses but also with the will of the Gods. This situation arises because new sources of ethical judgement have entered the equation, unforeseen by Neoptolemus. At fi rst he seems secure in his ethical stance. He is a man of virtuous character, and men of virtuous character do not tell lies. This position is rapidly undermined, and he proceeds to act in accordance with Ulysses utilitarian view of ethics (or, one might argue, on the wholly unethical grounds that people will think he is brave and clever if he does so). However, confronted with the pain and suffering of a fellow human being, he experiences such powerful feelings of sympathy that he is moved to act differently, to 4

reveal to Philoctetes the whole plot and to ally himself with Philoctetes against Ulysses. Neoptolemus, feeling sympathy for his fellow human, may also have started to feel that there is something inherently wrong not just in the act of lying but in the act of using another human being in the way that Ulysses had proposed. Think about Neoptolemus initial position, in which his ethical stance is determined, or, shall we say, constituted, by his virtuous character. To remain a virtuous character, and thereby preserve his own ethical position, he needs to be in full control of his own actions. He needs to be able to conceive of himself as fully responsible for what he does. If he were somehow tricked into acting out of character and did something that contradicted his sense of his own virtue, he would, justifi ably, feel violated, feel that something intrinsic and vital to his sense of who he is had been spoiled or tarnished in some way. He would feel, frankly, used. This is precisely how Philoctetes would feel if he fell for Neoptolemus lies and surrendered his bow and arrows. He would feel that he had been used as a means to achieve someone else s end. So might Neoptolemus feel, if he stopped to think about how Ulysses had treated him. No wonder Neoptolemus stops dead in his tracks and asks, How shall I act? It seems as though a whole history of moral philosophy is caught up in this one moment, including moral philosophy from centuries and locations of which neither the fictional character Neoptolemus nor his playwright-creator, Sophocles, would have known anything. How shall I act? is one succinct way of posing the question 5

theatre & ethics of ethics. It is also, as you will, of course, have noticed from the very beginning, a theatrical question. In both senses it is a difficult question, and in neither sense is it satisfactorily resolved by the answer that you should act better, although this answer is often tempting. The fact that this question can be posed as both ethical and theatrical suggests that there is at least some reason for writing (and reading) a book called Theatre & Ethics. As the example from Sophocles Philoctetes shows, at least some theatre appears to dramatise ethical questions, and it therefore makes sense that we think about what happens when it does. We might also think about any other ways in which the practice of theatre be it as participant or spectator might produce distinctive ways of thinking about ethics. It may also make sense to imagine that this might cut both ways and that some consideration of ethics might enable distinctive ways of thinking about (and doing) theatre. This book offers some preliminary thoughts about both. In continuing to sketch out an answer to the question of what is at stake in the bringing together of theatre and ethics, I now outline the shape of the book as a whole. This book is divided into three chronological parts: Ancient, Modern and Postmodern. In this fi rst part, Ancient, I consider the legacy of ancient Greek theatre and philosophy and how that legacy might guide us in thinking historically about the relationship between theatre and ethics. Just like theatre and philosophy today, the theatre and philosophy of the ancient Greeks concerned themselves with ethical and political issues, as well as with the relationships between these real-life activities and the fictions about 6

them we create within the field we now call art. In all three parts I explore these relationships and how the practice of theatre both reflects and contributes to the development of social, economic and political relations between the people who make and watch performance. I argue throughout that the ethical dimensions of theatrical production and spectatorship cannot be separated from the specific historical circumstances in which they take place. Much of this fi rst part addresses the philosophical challenge raised by Plato, whose writing appears to insist that there is something unethical about theatre itself. This idea that theatre itself might be unethical is one to which I return at the end of the book, with the suggestion that an unethical or anti-ethical theatre might be something we both desire and need. It is therefore part of the argument of this book that there is nothing natural, inevitable or even desirable about the conjunction between theatre and ethics suggested by the & of my title. In the second part, Modern, I take a huge leap forward in time to examine the origins social, political, philosophical and theatrical of the ethical frameworks with which most people in the modern Western world are most familiar. These are the ethical frameworks that take shape when individuals and the societies they form are no longer subjugated to ethical codes imposed from outside or above: by kings or gods. In this modern period the theatre participates in a process of managing the way people think about their relationships with one another and their potential for creating societies in which everyone can enjoy freedom as 7

theatre & ethics well as social solidarity. The plays of William Shakespeare offer an early example of the theatre playing this kind of role. Towards the end of the modern period (and the end of the second part of this book) the plays of Bertolt Brecht represent a critical response to this modern ethical framework, and one which ushers in a phase of ethical thought and performance for which I am using the term Postmodern as the title of the third and fi nal part of the book. In Part Three, I consider the ethical philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas (1906 95), which arose in response to what Levinas (and others) viewed as the disastrous consequences of certain aspects of modern rationality. In this view the genocide committed by the Nazis in the 1940s represented the logical extension of a kind of rationality that had turned both irrational and unethical. Levinasian ethics seeks to replace an ethics based on the freedom of the individual (modern) or the realisation of individual potential (ancient) with an ethics oriented entirely towards the other. Performance conceived in relation to Levinas postmodern ethics encourages the spectator to stop seeing the performance as an exploration of his or her own subjectivity and, instead, to take it as an opportunity to experience an encounter with someone else. Performance, in this view, invites the spectator to assume ethical responsibility for the fragile life of the other. Here I consider work by the performance group Goat Island and the artist Walid Raad, as well as some recent critical writing about performance. At the beginning of the twenty-fi rst century, thought about the relationship between theatre and ethics has 8

& index Abramović, Marina, 59 61, 65 Adorno, Theodor, 50 1 aesthetics, 55 6, 63 6, 67 Aristotle, 3, 39 40, 44, 51 autonomy, 26, 31, 37 emotion, 17 19, 21 2, 32 6, 44, 64 encounter, 53 5, 60 1, 64 6 enlightenment, 26, 30, 31 41, 44, 45, 50 1 bourgeoisie, bourgeois subject, 26, 31, 38, 40 2, 44 Brecht, Bertolt, 70 The Good Person of Szechwan, 41 4 The Decision, 45 8 character, 5, 9 10, 20 compassion, 40 decision, 46 9 dramatisation, 6, 13 D Urso, Maria Donata, 67 9 economy, 26 7, 28, 30, 43 efficacy, 56 freedom, 7, 12, 37 Goat Island, 8, 61 3, 65 Heathfield, Adrian, 61 3, 64 6 Horkheimer, Max, 50 1 Jonson, Ben (The Alchemist), 28 9 Kant, Immanuel, 36 7, 52 Lehmann, Hans-Thies, 56 9, 64 6 Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, 39 40, 70 Levinas, Emmanuel, 8, 51 6, 60, 63, 65, 66 7, 69 75

theatre & ethics modernity, 26, 27 31, 45, 50 1 responsibility, 52 5, 58 9, 63 nation, 38 41 other, the, 8, 13, 52 4, 66, 68 9 perception, 56 8 Phelan, Peggy, 59 61, 64 6 philosophy, 5 7, 12, 13, 22 3, 30 1, 51 3 Plato, 7, 16 24, 66, 70 politics, political relations, 30, 38 42, 46 8, 49 51, 56, 63 6 Raad, Walid, 8, 58 9 rationality, reason, 8, 12, 17 19, 32, 38, 45, 50 1, 64 religion, 4, 11, 23 4, 25 representation, 18 19, 21 Shakespeare, William (King Lear), 8, 29 30 Smith, Adam, 33 6 social relations, 7, 12, 14, 15, 27, 28, 29, 30 Sophocles (Philoctetes), 1 6, 11 14, 25 spectatorship, 9, 15, 20, 24, 35 6, 43 4, 47 9, 59 61, 63 8 suffering, 1 4 sympathy, 3, 5, 21 2, 34 6 truth, 15 16 universality, 31, 36 9 virtue, 3 76