ican pragmatism, provide a new basis for a fruitful insight into legal argumentation?

Similar documents
UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Assertion and Inference

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT]

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii

Department of Philosophy

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Introduction to Calderoni s The Philosophy of Values

Lecture Notes Oliver Wendell Holmes and Jerome Frank, Legal Realism

Combining Pricean and Peircean Pragmatism. Henrik Rydenfelt

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

What is a counterexample?

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS ITALO TESTA

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

TABLE OF CONTENTS. Comments on Bibliography and References

Commentary on Feteris

Skepticism and Internalism

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

Brandom s Pragmatist Inferentialism and the Problem of Objectivity Ulrich Reichard University of Durham

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

Philosophy Courses-1

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

CONSTRUCTIVISM IN ETHICS

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind, Epistemology

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

Philosophy Courses-1

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Inquiry: A dialectical approach to teaching critical thinking

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

The New Puzzle of Moral Deference. moral belief solely on the basis of a moral expert s testimony. The fact that this deference is

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

x Philosophic Thoughts: Essays on Logic and Philosophy

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation

A. V. Ravishankar Sarma

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen

An Introduction to Metametaphysics

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

A number of epistemologists have defended

Münster Lectures in Philosophy

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

Hanti Lin. Contact Information Phone: +1 (412) Academic Positions

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Philosophy Courses in English

Department of Philosophy

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

SYLLABUS. Department Syllabus. Philosophy of Religion

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

The Big Schema of Things:

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)


PRESTON STOVALL PH.D. CANDIDATE ACLS FELLOW DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH

NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Transcription:

Preface Legal argumentation has become one of the prominent research domains of legal philosophy in the last fifty years and its study has deeply influenced this discipline. This is a consequence of three main assumptions which are generally accepted by legal scholars at present days: (1) Legal language is fundamentally indeterminate because of the plurality of functions that it fulfils in legal activities and institutions, as well as in everyday life; (2) The indeterminacy of legal language, however, does not prevent legal interpretation and adjudication from being "rational", "reasonable", "just", "correct"; (3) In fact the criteria of rationality, reasonableness, justice and correctness which apply to legal interpretation and adjudication consist in, or are expressed by, rules governing a linguistic practice: the practice which aims at justifying, in a public context, that thus-and-so ought to be the case according to the law. Although this is largely undisputed by legal philosophers, the following issues among others remain highly controversial: (1) what the nature of legal indeterminacy is; (2) what kind of rationality applies in the legal domain; (3) how the rules governing legal argumentation, if any, can be properly singled out and analyzed. An original and promising way to address these issues has been recently supplied by Robert Brandom's semantic inferentialism. Brandom's inferentialist project which goes from Making It Explicit of 1994 to the recent Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas of 2009 gives a unified picture of the problems of linguistic indeterminacy, of the sources of rationality, and of the structure of argumentative practices. According to this picture, if we apply it to the legal domain, (1) the content of a legal provision is given by the set of inferences this provision is involved in within legal argumentation; (2) the inferential articulation of a legal provision is governed by rules; (3) these rules determine the normative status of the participants in a linguistic practice and express the criteria of rationality, reasonableness, justice and correctness which characterize a social community. Might these claims, which find their origin in the tradition of Amer-

vi DAMIANO CANALE & GIOVANNI TUZET ican pragmatism, provide a new basis for a fruitful insight into legal argumentation? In order to address this issue, the Editors of this volume, with the contribution of Michael Esfeld from the University of Lausanne, developed from 2004 to 2006 a research project sponsored by Bocconi University in Milan, which aimed at exploring the possibility of an "inferentialist account" of legal argumentation. More generally, the research sought to determine (i) whether an inferentialist account can explain some general aspects of legal reasoning and legal decisionmaking; (ii) whether the study of legal practice can contribute to some aspects of an inferentialist theory of content and reasoning. The results of this research were discussed with several scholars engaged in the study of language and argumentation, in the occasion of an international conference held in Milan, at Bocconi University, on October 5-6, 2006. This book contains the (revised versions of the) papers presented at that conference; three further papers have been included in the book, in order to enrich the analytical and critical picture of "legal inferentialism" presented here. The book is divided into two parts. The first one, Inferentialism on Debate, aims at discussing some aspects of Brandom's inferentialist project that are relevant for the study of argumentation. On the basis of the distinction between what is said and what is implicated in linguistic communication, Carlo Penco considers, in Chapter 1, to what extent one is committed to what she does not say, and to what point one is bound to recognize the consequences of what she says: It is the problem of our inferential responsibility and its limits. In Chapter 2, Michael Esfeld looks at the sources of the normative status that Brandom attributes to meaning and content. This issue leads the Author to discuss the relationship between naturalism, cognitivism and the naturalistic fallacy, and to propose a naturalistic explanation of the sources of normativity. In Chapter 3 Italo Testa firstly takes into account the philosophical debate between Robert Brandom and Jürgen Habermas, which highlights some relevant concerns for the inferentialist project as to the social basis of normativity and content. Starting from this account, the Author then looks at the relationship between recognition and normativity, on the one hand, and recognition and criticism, on the other. Chapter 4, by Giorgio Bongiovanni, Antonino Rotolo and Corrado Roversi, is devoted to the evaluation of an inferentialist approach with respect to the relationship between law and morality. On the basis of Robert Alexy's pragmatic foundation of this relationship i.e. the "claim-tocorrectness" thesis, the Authors discuss some problematic aspects of Bran-

PREFACE vii dom's account which are related to the role of cooperation in practical reason and to the notion of disagreement. In Chapter 5 the Editors of this volume give an example of inferentialist analysis of legal argumentation by reconstructing the normative commitments and entitlements which are undertaken by two lawyers in the discussion of a legal case. This analysis permits to show the advantages and drawbacks of an inferentialist approach in legal argumentation theory. The aim of the second part of the book, Inferentialism, Argumentation and Pragmatism, is to consider legal inferentialism within the manifold tradition of pragmatism both from a historical and a theoretical point of view (Chapters 6 and 7), and to confront it with other approaches to the study of legal argumentation which have a similar background (Chapters 8, 9 and 10). In Chapter 6 Pascal Engel focuses on the relationships between epistemology and ethics from a "genealogical" point of view, taking into consideration some theories of what he calls the "norms of thought", from Kant to the beginning of the 20 th century. Chapter 7 is devoted to the relevance of logic in the legal domain: in particular, Susan Haack reconstructs the anti-formalist stance of the classical legal pragmatism at the end of the 19 th and beginning of the 20 th century, and highlights its topical interest with regard to the contemporary achievements in the philosophy of logic. In Chapter 8 John Woods takes into account the consequences of the contemporary "pragmatic turn" in the study of legal argumentation as to the problem of evidence in criminal law. The Author analyzes the influence of actors and context on evidentiary inference and its abductive structure. In Chapter 9 Eveline Feteris presents a pragma-dialectical approach to the study of legal argumentation and uses it in order to clarify the features, and to evaluate the consequences, of teleological-evaluative argumentation in the legal domain. In Chapter 10, finally, Andrea Rossetti presents a linguistic analysis of the Italian verb "dovere" which shows how the different functions of this verb depend on the set of inferences it can be entailed by in a given reference context. To conclude, we would like to warmly thank the Authors for their patience and valuable help in realizing this book, and Bocconi University for the financial support provided for its publication. Damiano Canale and Giovanni Tuzet

viii DAMIANO CANALE & GIOVANNI TUZET NOTE ON CONTRIBUTORS GIORGIO BONGIOVANNI is professor of philosophy of law at the University of Bologna Law School. He is associate editor of "Ratio Juris. An International Journal of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law". His publications include: Reasonableness and Law (co-edited with G. Sartor and C. Valentini, 2009), Oggettività e morale (2007), Costituzionalismo e teoria del diritto (2005) and several papers on constitutional theory, legal theory, and metaethics and practical reason. DAMIANO CANALE is full professor of Philosophy of Law at Bocconi University, Milan. His research interests cover philosophy of language, legal argumentation, history of legal and political concepts, bioethics. He is author of La costituzione delle differenze. Giusnaturalismo e codificazione del diritto civile nella Prussia del '700 (2000); Forme del limite nell'interpretazione giudiziale (2003); and coeditor with P. Grossi and H. Hofmann of A History of Philosophy of Law in the Civil Law World, 1600-1900 (2009). His papers on legal theory and legal argumentation have been published in "Ratio Juris", "Informal Logic" and "Argumentation". PASCAL ENGEL is ordinary professor of contemporary philosophy at the University of Geneva. He has written on the philosophy of logic, of language and of mind, and on epistemology. Among his books are The Norm of Truth (1991), Davidson et la philosophie du langage (1994), Philosophie et psychologie (1996), Truth (2002), Ramsey: Truth and Success (with J. Dokic) and Va savoir (2007). MICHAEL ESFELD is full professor of epistemology and philosophy of science at the University of Lausanne (Switzerland) since 2002. His main areas of research are the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science, in particular physics. His current research projects focus on reductionism, mental causation, the causal theory of properties, causation in physics, and structural realism. His books include Naturphilosophie als Metaphysik der Natur (2008), Holism in Philosophy of Mind and Philosophy of Physics (2001) as well as introductory books to the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science in French and German. EVELINE T. FETERIS is associate professor at the Department of Speech Communication, Argumentation Theory and Rhetoric, University of Amsterdam. Her research interests cover legal argumentation, argumentation theory, legal theory and legal philosophy. Her major publications include Dialectical Legal Argument: Formal and Informal Models (special issue of "Artificial Intelligence and Law", 2000, with H. Prakken), Strategic Maneuvering with the Intention of the Legislator in the Justification of Judicial Decisions ("Argumentation", 2008),

PREFACE ix The Rational Reconstruction of Weighing and Balancing on the Basis of Teleological-Evaluative Considerations ("Ratio Juris", 2008). SUSAN HAACK is Distinguished Professor in the Humanities, Cooper Senior Scholar in Arts and Sciences, Professor of Philosophy and Professor of Law, University of Miami. Her books include Philosophy of Logics; Evidence and Inquiry; Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic; Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate; Defending Science Within Reason; Pragmatism Old and New; and Putting Philosophy to Work. Her legal scholarship has been primarily on issues in evidence law (especially the law of scientific evidence) and on legal pragmatism. CARLO PENCO teaches philosophy of language at the University of Genoa. His main research areas are Philosophy of Language, Communication Theory and the Foundations of Cognitive Science, and Artificial Intelligence. Recent publications include an introduction to the philosophy of language (2008), Explaining the mental (2007) and papers published in "History and Philosophy of Logic", "Modern Logic", "Pragmatics & Cognition", "Topoi". ANDREA ROSSETTI is professor of philosophy of law at the University of Milan- Bicocca, where he also teaches legal informatics. His works concern the possibility of the use of formal systems for the expression of the law and the ontology of social and intangible objects (Deontica in Jean-Louis Gardies. Logica e ontologia degli atti sociali, 1999; Modi deontici nei sistemi giuridici, 2004). Currently his studies focus on the concept legal document. Since 1999, he deals with legal informatics; in particular, he has devoted several essays to the idea of openness in the ICT. ANTONINO ROTOLO is associate professor of philosophy of law at the University of Bologna Law School. He is a member of CIRSFID (Centre for Research in History of Law, Philosophy and Sociology of Law, and Computer Science and Law) at the University of Bologna. He published two monographic volumes about reasoning by analogy in the law (2001) and multi-modal logics for modeling the interaction between agents and normative systems (2002). He has also extensively written on normative reasoning, law and logic, logics for artificial Intelligence and law, and formal methods for practical reasoning. CORRADO ROVERSI is currently lecturer in legal philosophy at the University of Bologna. He has a degree in philosophy from the University of Bologna and a doctorate in analytic philosophy and general jurisprudence from the University of Milan. He is a member of CIRSFID (Centre for Research in the History, Philosophy, and Sociology of Law, and in Computer Science and Law) at the University of Bologna. He has written one monograph and several papers on social

x DAMIANO CANALE & GIOVANNI TUZET and legal ontology, the theory of norms and normativeness, and the philosophy of normative language. ITALO TESTA is assistant professor of history of political philosophy at the University of Parma. He is author of Hegel critico e scettico (2002), Teorie dell'argomentazione (2006), Ragione impura (2006), and co-editor of Hegel contemporaneo (2003), Lo spazio sociale della ragione (2009). Recent articles include Selbstbewusstsein und zweite Natur, in Hegels Phaenomenologie des Geistes (2008); Criticism from within nature. The dialectic from first to second nature between McDowell and Adorno, in "Philosophy and Social Criticism" (2007). GIOVANNI TUZET is assistant professor of philosophy of law at Bocconi University. His areas of interest cover epistemology, philosophy of logic, normative sciences and legal argumentation. His writings include La prima inferenza (2006), Projectual Abduction ("Logic Journal of the IGPL", 2006) and, with D. Canale, On Legal Inferentialism ("Ratio Juris", 2007), On the Contrary: Inferential Analysis and Ontological Assumptions of the A Contrario Argument ("Informal Logic", 2008), The A Simili Argument: An Inferentialist Setting ("Ratio Juris", 2009), What is the Reason for This Rule? An Inferential Account of the Ratio Legis ("Argumentation", forthcoming). JOHN WOODS is director of the Abductive Systems Group at UBC and Charles S. Peirce Professor of Logic in the Logic and Computational Sciences Group at King's College London. Recent writings include Paradox and Paraconsistency (2003), Agenda Relevance (2003) and The Reach of Abduction (2005), the latter two with Dov Gabbay. Seductions and Shortcuts: Error in the Cognitive Economy is forthcoming in 2010. NOTE ON CONTRIBUTIONS Some sections of the Editors' Chapter are taken from their papers Interpretive Scorekeeping, in "Analisi e diritto 2005", Turin: Giappichelli, 2006, pp. 81-97, and On Legal Inferentialism, in "Ratio Juris", Vol. 20, 2007, pp. 32-44. A French and shorter version of Pascal Engel's Contribution was published in "Revue de théologie et de philsophie", N. 140, 2008, pp. 29-47. The Chapter by Susan Haack is reprinted from "Ratio Juris", Vol. 20, 2007, pp. 1-31. All the other writings collected in this Volume are previously unpublished.