THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Similar documents
THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

USE OF THESES. Australian National University

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

USE OF THESES. Australian National University

USE OF THESES. «1 s a. ٢ ٦ ٠ ٦ Australian

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Horwich and the Liar

Page 2 of 8 Stage 2 Religion Studies Student Response

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

e x c e l l e n c e : an introduction to philosophy

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

ISSA Proceedings 2002 Dissociation And Its Relation To Theory Of Argument

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

National Quali cations

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Constructing A Biblical Message

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

2004 by Dr. William D. Ramey InTheBeginning.org

Russell: On Denoting

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Prentice Hall U.S. History Modern America 2013

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

NATIONAL PROPERTY POLICY FOR THE UNITING CHURCH IN AUSTRALIA

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Postmodal Metaphysics

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Study Guide for Job - Ecclesiastes

Prentice Hall United States History Survey Edition 2013

Summary Kooij.indd :14

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

G. H. von Wright (1916 )

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Florida State University Libraries

John D. Caputo s book is one in a new series from Penguin called Philosophy in

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

Evidence and Transcendence

A Freewheeling Defense of Kant s Resolution of the Third Antinomy

Reply to Robert Koons

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

THE RIGHTS AND OBLIGATIONS 1/ OF ALL THE CHRISTIAN FAITHFUL [Canons ]

Philosophy 1100 Honors Introduction to Ethics

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

PHIL 2000: ETHICS 2011/12, TERM 1

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Christianity, science and rumours of divorce

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Section 4. Attainment Targets. About the attainment targets

QCAA Study of Religion 2019 v1.1 General Senior Syllabus

Student Outcome Statement

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Russell on Plurality

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Immaculate Conception Church Wilmington, North Carolina

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

The Concept of Testimony

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

Wittgenstein and Austin on What is in Common : A Neglected Perspective?

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Transcription:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE: +61 2 6125 4631 R.G. MENZIES LIBRARY BUILDING NO:2 FACSIMILE: +61 2 6125 4063 THE AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY EMAIL: library.theses@anu.edu.au CANBERRA ACT 0200 AUSTRALIA USE OF THESES This copy is supplied for purposes of private study and research only. Passages from the thesis may not be copied or closely paraphrased without the written consent of the author.

VALUES, VALUING AND EVALUATION by DIANE JOYCE AUSTIN A thesis submitted for the degree of Master of Arts in the Australian National University August, 1969

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to acknowledge the advice and guidance given to me by Mr. William Ginnane, Mr. Kim Lycos and Professor Peter Herbst during the writing of this thesis. My particular thanks go to Mr. Ginnane for his critical reading of drafts of the thesis and the many helpful suggestions that he proffered. Many of the examples used in this thesis were first brought to my attention by Mr. Ginnane. However, any errors found in this work are entirely my own.

CONTENTS INTRODUCTION CHAPTER I -SOME VARIETIES AND ROLES OF EVALUATION Hare's View Criticisms of Hare's View CHAPTER II - THE AMBIGUITY OF "VALUE" Predicative Use (i) Predicative Use (ii) Verbal Use (i) Verbal Use (ii) Substantival Use CHAPTER III - OBJECTS OF VALUING The Notion of a Proper Object Objects of Wanting Proper Objects of Valuing CHAPTER IV - Reactions VALUING AND RELATED CONCEPTS Acquaintance and Reactions Some Reactions - Difference Symptoms of Valuing Antithesis of Valuing CHAPTER V - Points of Comparison and REASONS FOR VALUING THINGS Reasons for Valuing a Kind of Thing Reasons for Valuing a Specimen of a Kind Values and Evaluation CHAPTER VI - SOME CONCLUSIONS AND QUERIES Some Thoughts on Evaluation Philosophical Anthropology Reconsidered BIBLIOGRAPHY Page l 6 6 9 40 40 47 48 50 54 65 66 73 77 101 101 103 112 127 142 145 149 168 175 180 180 198 202

INTRODUCTION Professor von Wright has stated that those.concepts relevant to ethics may be divided approximately into three 1 groups The three groups he suggests are value concepts, which include the concepts of good, bad and evil, normative concepts, which include obligation, right, prohibition and permission, and finally, concepts which belong to "the notion of ahuman act" and "notions which are relevant to action" such as desire, end, need, want, intention, motive, reason and will. Von Wright suggests that the study of this third group of concepts could be called a "Philosophical Theory of Man" or "Philosophical Anthropology", for such a study is often embarked upon if the view is held that "one can look for the foundation of morals. in the needs and wants of man and in the specific nature of man as agerit" 2 This rather sweeping categorization does draw.attention to an approach to ethics that has been neglected of late - the use of "Philosophical Anthropology" to clarify our l. Georg Henrik von Wright, The Varieties of Goodness (London, 1963), p.6. 2. Ibid, pp.7-8. 1

2 understanding of value-concepts and of evaluation. In the following study, this approach will be adopted in order to discuss the capacity of men to value things, and also, to have values. The relation of evaluation to both these capacities will be discussed 1, for it will be seen that men only value and have as values, things which they believe to be good in some way or other. It will be suggested that the notion of what it is to value something will remain obscure until our understanding of evaluation is broadened to encompass particular interests, wants and purposes of individual human beings. In a sense, this could be called a meta-ethical study, for the primary interest of the thesis is to offer a partial answer to the question, "What does it mean to say 1 that someone values 1 something?" In answering this question, it is hoped that some light will also be thrown on the nature of values, and on the types of evaluation associated with valuing. It is thus a conceptual study of valuing, evaluation and values, and some relations that hold between them. One could say that it is an attempt to clarify and broaden our understanding of the meaning of these three words. However, it should not be thought that 1. In Chapter I the substantival and verbal uses of the word "value" are discussed. To have values and to value something are both distinguished from what it is to evaluate something.

3 such a study presupposes that the meanings of these words, that the concepts involved, are fixed and need only to be explicated. Although we know well enough how and when to use phrases like, "He evaluated X", "He values X", or "X is one of his values", the grounds on which we make such statements remain unclear, the relations between such concepts obscure. It is in the clarification of issues such as these that we may come to a better understanding of what the words mean. It is at this point that our reference to "Philosophical Anthropology" becomes relevant, for it will be tacitly assumed that attention to particular wants, interests and purposes of men, help to clarify the concepts mentioned, and certain relations between them. Thus, this study should be seen not only as one of conceptual analysis, but also as one of concept construction, for concepts of what it is to value something and what it is to have values are in particular confused. {The extreme ambiguity of the word "value" contributes to this confusion.) A lucid account of this type of procedure has been offered by von Wright. Reflection on the grounds for calling things by words is a ~ of conceptual investigation. The aim of the type of investigation of which I am speaking, is not to 'uncover' the existing meaning. of some word or expression, veiled as it were behind the bewildering complexities of common usage. The idea of

4 the philosopher as a searcher of meanings should not be coupled with an idea or postulate that the searched entities actually are there - awaiting the vision of the philosopher. If this picture of the philosopher's pursuit were accurate, then conceptual investigation would, for all I can see, be an empirical inquiry into the actual use of language or the meaning of expressions. Philosophic reflexion on the grounds for calling a thing 'x' is challenged in situations, when the grounds have not been fixed, when there is no settled opinion as to what the grounds are. The concept s ti 11 remains to be moulded and therewith its logical connexions w~th other concepts to be established. The words and expressions, the use of which bewilder the philosopher, are so to speak in search of a meaning.l This being the case, I do not apologise for the fact that certain distinctions I shall draw concerning the use of the word "value" are not reflected clearly in common usage. Although not often recognised as such, considerations that could be termed "Philosophical Anthropology" have emerged in meta-ethical studies. A very brief study of this type is attempted by Professor Hare in his book The Language of Morals, to be found in chapter eight which is called "Commending and Choosing". However,.the neglect of this type of study has tended to produce very restricted and misleading views of the nature of evaluation in l. Ibid, p.s (von Wright's italics).

5. 1 1 part1.cu ar I wish to discuss Professor Hare's attempted explanation of the logical nature of value-words, in order to show how his concept of what it is to evaluate something may be broadened to encompass varieties of evaluation other than those he describes. As it will be seen that evaluation of an object in a manner to be specified is a precondition of it being valued, this discussion is a necessary preliminary to our analysis of what it is to value something. 1. An example of such a limited view of evaluation may be found in J.O. Urmson's "On Grading", in A.G.N. Flew (Ed.), Logic and Language, Second Series (Oxford, 1961), pp.l59-186.