ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

Similar documents
Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Roman Ingarden s Ontology: Existential Dependence, Substances, Ideas, and Other Things Empiricists Do Not Like *

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Necessity and Truth Makers

Published in Mind, 2000, 109 (434), pp

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Intermediate Logic Spring. Extreme Modal Realism

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Platonism, Alienation, and Negativity

Daniel von Wachter Free Agents as Cause

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

D I S C U S S I O N. The Theories of Modality A Reply to von Wachter

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

PHIL 399: Metaphysics (independent study) Fall 2015, Coastal Carolina University Meeting times TBA

Trope Theory and the Bradley Regress

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Truthmakers and explanation

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

From Grounding to Truth-Making: Some Thoughts

PHIL 399: Metaphysics (independent study) Fall 2015, Coastal Carolina University Meeting times TBA

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

Are All Universals Instantiated?

Theories of propositions

5 A Modal Version of the

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

What is Formal in Husserl s Logical Investigations?

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

Is a Whole Identical to its Parts?*

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Free Agents as Cause

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Barry SMITH. (Manchester) THE ONTOLOGY OF EPISTEMOLOGY *

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Introduction to Philosophy. Daniel von Wachter

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Book Reviews. The Metaphysics of Relations, by Anna Marmodoro and David Yates. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 304 pages, ISBN:

Identifying the Problem of Personal Identity

proceedings of the aristotelian society

DISCUSSION - McGINN ON NON-EXISTENT OBJECTS AND REDUCING MODALITY

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Bare Particulars. Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006),

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

Compresence is a Bundle A Problem for the Bundle Theory of Objects

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Bradley s Regress. (U): There can be unity in complexity

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Vagueness in sparseness: a study in property ontology

What Is Possible? * Daniel von Wachter , deposited in open-access archive on

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Critical Study of Michael Jubien, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless

Proof of the Existence of Universals and Roman Ingarden s Ontology

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

Against Monism. 1. Monism and pluralism. Theodore Sider

From: Vance, Chad (2013). In Defense of the New Actualism (dissertation), University of Colorado Boulder. 2.2 Truthmakers for Negative Truths

PHIL 181: METAPHYSICS Fall 2006 M 5:30-8:20 MND-3009 WebCT-Assisted

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

RECENT ADVANCES IN METAPHYSICS E. J. Lowe

542 Book Reviews. Department of Philosophy. University of Houston 513 Agnes Arnold Hall Houston TX USA

TABLE OF CONTENTS. Comments on Bibliography and References

To appear in Philosophical Studies 150 (3): (2010).

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

No Physical Particles for a Dispositional Monist? Baptiste Le Bihan Université de Rennes 1. Draft (Forthcoming in Philosophical Papers)

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Transcription:

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES * Daniel von Wachter Internationale Akademie für Philosophie, Santiago de Chile Email: epost@abc.de (replace ABC by von-wachter ) http://von-wachter.de Posted on http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de on 29.8.2009 David Armstrong has recently proposed a new view according to which the properties of a thing are parts of that thing and the predication of properties is necessary (Armstrong 2004). In what follows, after a general remark about Professor Armstrong s conception of ontology, I shall raise objections against this view and defend an alternative account of the connection between particulars and their properties, involving a kind of ontological dependence which is different from Armstrong s necessary connection between particulars and their properties. According to Armstrong s ontology there are particulars and properties. Properties are universals: if a and b are particulars and F is a universal, then a s F-ness is numerically identical with b s F-ness. When Armstrong says There are universals he does not make a claim about the meanings of predicates, he does not answer a question of semantics. Already in his early work on universals he fought against the mistake of confusing universals with meanings: * I thank Professor Armstrong for commenting on my comments. I express my gratitude to the Free State of Bavaria for supporting me during the time of this work through the Bayerischer Habilitationsförderpreis. I am grateful to Johannes Hübner for helpful criticism. 1

I believe that the identification of universals with meanings (connotations, intensions) [...] has been a disaster for the theory of universals. A thoroughgoing separation of the theory of universals from the theory of the semantics of general terms is in fact required. (Armstrong 1978, xiv) Armstrong s reason for assuming universals is not that predicates cannot be replaced by, or defined in terms of, other types of expressions. 1 It is not that we are ontologically committed to universals. His aim is to describe what there is, and he holds that the resemblance between two things consists in there being a universal that both things instantiate. His aim is not to analyze concepts and statements but to describe the structure of reality independently of how we ordinarily think or speak about it. He wants to name not truth conditions but truthmakers. In contemporary philosophy, Armstrong is the forerunner of metaphysics that is independent of semantics, and not many have followed him. There is a great gulf between Armstrong and philosophers who are used to doing metaphysics as a discipline more closely related to semantics, philosophers who are less sceptical about the linguistic turn. Those from the other side of the gulf are in danger to misunderstand some of Armstrong s claims as claims about statements although Armstrong intends them to be about their truthmakers. Armstrong rejects bundle theories, according to which things are bundles of properties and hence consist just of properties. He holds that properties are borne by substrata, by property bearers. According to his new view, the link between particular and universal is partial identity. The properties of a thing are parts of that thing. He also says that the particular and its universal overlap. This takes Armstrong to the view that predication is necessary. Once one has identity, even if only partial identity, there will be found necessity. If a thing loses one of its properties it thereby ceases to exist, it becomes a different entity. Likewise the universal becomes a different entity. Every thing has all of its properties necessarily. 1 David Lewis realizes that Armstrong is doing something rather different from what authors do who say they do metaphysics when he writes: I suggest that Armstrong has an unfamiliar notion of analysis. Analysis is not, primarily, a quest for definitions. Rather, it is a quest for truth-makers. (Lewis 1992, 203) 2

It is Armstrong s presupposition, I take it, that a thing has its parts necessarily. Given that the properties of a thing are parts of that thing it follows that a thing has all of its properties necessarily, in the sense that if it loses one it ceases to exist and becomes a different thing, and if it had had different properties it would have been a different thing. 2 Likewise, universals are necessarily instantiated as they are. Having just the instances it has is essential to the universal being what it is (Armstrong 2004). I have four objections. 1. Overlap Armstrong says that a particular and its universals overlap. According to Armstrong s conception of universals (at least until his A World of States of Affairs), if a and b are F then a s F-ness and b s F-ness are numerically identical. But then F is a part of a, and F has no parts that are not part of a. The particular and its universal overlap, but they do not properly overlap, they do not overlap in the ordinary sense. This does not affect Armstrong s claim that a thing has its properties necessarily. But why does Armstrong hold that a universal has its instances necessarily? The instances of a universal are not parts of the universal. If b ceases to instantiate F, then F is less often instantiated, but it does not lose a part. There is therefore no reason to assume that F ceases to be and becomes a different entity unless Armstrong now gives up his view that a s F-ness and b s F-ness are numerically identical. 2. Mereological essentialism Armstrong assumes that a thing has its parts necessarily, i.e. if a whole loses one of its parts it thereby ceases to exist. This doctrine, sometimes called mereological essentialism, has its defenders, 3 but it is neither uncontroversial 2 Armstrong says only that had the particular lacked one of the properties that it actually has, it would have been a different particular. He does not say explicitly that if a thing loses one of its properties, it thereby ceases to exist. But I assume that the former entails the latter. 3 Mereological essentialism is held by Ingarden 1965, 43, p. 110, and also by Chisholm 1976, Appendix B and ch. III. 3

nor without alternative. Contra mereological essentialism one may hold that some things can survive the loss or replacement of some of their parts. After all we say that a car can have one its door replaced or I can lose a finger or I (or my body) can get a new kidney without ceasing to exist or becoming a different thing. Things which, contra mereological essentialism, can survive the replacement of parts are sometimes called entia successiva (van Inwagen 1991). Roderick Chisholm (1976, Appendix B and ch. III) proposed an alternative to Armstrong s view that things do not survive the loss of parts. He says of entia successiva that they are constituted by entities for which mereological essentialism is true. A tyre of my car was replaced means (roughly): There was one thing, T1, which ceased to exist when the tyre was replaced; there was another thing, T2, containing the parts of T1 except a different tyre. Before the replacement of the tyre my car was constituted by T1, after that by T2. My car survived the replacement of the tyre, but T1 did not. Chisholm thus provides a method to translate sentences apparently about cars that can change parts into sentences about cars that cease to exist when they lose parts. For him there are entia successiva, but they can be reduced to more basic entities for which mereological essentialism is true. Roman Ingarden (1965, 43), on the other hand, argues that individual things (substances), for which mereological essentialism is not true, are more basic than wholes, for which mereological essentialism is true. A thing, e.g. a table, can also be taken as, or conceptualized, as a whole. The scheme of a whole is then thrown over the thing (Ingarden 1965, 117). The whole ceases to exist if it loses a part, but a thing can survive the loss of a property or a part (although strictly speaking only wholes but not things have parts). My own view is that we can form the concepts of part and whole in different ways. We can stipulate that a whole that loses a part thereby ceases to exist. Ordinarily, however, if we ask questions about the diachronic identity of a thing with parts, we do so on the background of a certain sortal concept under which the thing is subsumed. The sortal concept provides the conditions of diachronic identity of the thing. Whether the loss of a certain part means the end of the thing depends on the sortal concept. A violin, for example, does not become a different violin and does not cease to exist if the fingerboard is renewed. 4

At any rate, if a theory entails that a violin ceases to exist if it loses a part, then that counts strongly against that theory, because that seems just false and there is no discovery that would convince us otherwise. Likewise, if a theory entails, as Armstrong s new view does, that a violin becomes a different violin if it loses a property, then that counts strongly against that theory. 3. Essential properties My view that conditions of diachronic identity are provided by sortal concepts leads me to relativism about necessary (or essential ) properties. Whether the loss of a certain property entails the end of the existence of the thing does not depend on the thing in itself but on the sortal concept under which the thing is subsumed. A traditional substance ontologist (e.g. Roman Ingarden) denies this because he holds that the property bearer of a thing is an exemplification of a kind universal. A thing continues to exist as long as its kinded property bearer continues to exist. What this kind is and on which properties the property bearer is dependent (the essential properties ) does not depend on the sortal concept; rather, it is something to be discovered about the thing in itself. It seems to me that Armstrong s ontology leads to relativism about essential properties too. He argues that all monadic universals are properties and that there are no kind universals (which he calls substantival universals ) irreducible to conjunctions of properties (Armstrong 1978, 61-67). It seems to follow that it is nothing to be discovered about the thing in itself what the kind is which is relevant for the conditions of diachronic identity of the thing; that is, the kind K such that it is true to say that the thing ceased to exist if and only if it is not a K anymore. It seems to me that what the conditions of diachronic identity are then depends on under which sortal concept the thing is subsumed, and there are several sortal concepts under which the thing can be subsumed. The end of the existence of a thing with parts is ontologically just a change in which properties are instantiated where. It differs from other such changes only because through it a certain sortal concept does not apply anymore. Armstrong, however, is not a relativist about essential properties (as he has confirmed in conversation). He holds that all predication of properties is 5

necessary in the sense that if a particular lacked a property which it actually has, then it would have been a different particular. So my objection here is that Armstrong s ontology leads to relativism about necessary properties and that he therefore should not hold that any, let alone all, predication of properties is necessary. There is no ontological fact of the matter whether the loss of a certain property entails the end of the existence of the thing. 4. Ontological glue Armstrong s main argument against bundle theories is that they have great difficulty with the metaphysics of the uniting principle or principles of bundling (Armstrong 2004). They fail to provide the ontological glue holding the bundle together. Armstrong s alternative is that the link between particular and universal is partial identity. I shall now raise an objection against Armstrong s view and, in the light of this objection, defend a solution of the gluing problem that is also available to the bundle theorist. Armstrong wants to solve the gluing problem with his new view. The properties of a thing are parts of it, and if it loses a property it thereby ceases to exist. The thing has its properties necessarily. Therefore the thing cannot lose properties and has in this sense unity, the gluing problem is thus solved. The link between particular and universal is partial identity and not a genuine relation of compresence or instantiation, the acceptance of which would lead to a regress. I have two objections against this solution. First, according to classical extensional mereology, a whole, or mereological sum, continues to exist as long as all its parts continue to exist. Consider a thing which, according to Armstrong s new view, is a whole of which the properties of the thing are parts. According to Armstrong s theory of universals (Armstrong 1978 and 1997), if a thing loses a property the property does not thereby cease to exist (at least as long as it is instantiated by other things). So the whole consisting of the properties of a thing is not destroyed by the thing losing a property. It continues to exist even if the properties that are parts of it are not all instantiated by the thing anymore. According to Armstrong s new view the link between a particular and its universals is the same as, and nothing more than, the link between a whole and its parts. But the link between a particu- 6

lar and one of its universals can be broken up whilst the link between the whole and its parts, one of which is the universal, continues to hold. With tropes the situation would be different, but with universals as parts of things Armstrong s solution does not seem to work. Of course, intuitively we would say that if a violin is taken apart then the whole ceases to exist, or that if a leg is cut off a table the table loses a part and the leg is no longer a part of the table. That is so because, against classical extensional mereology, we often mean by a whole something whose parts are somehow connected. 4 We usually use a concept of a whole according to which the whole loses a part if a certain relation between the part and the rest of the whole ceases to hold; e.g. if the part ceases to be physically connected to the rest of the whole, i.e. if it is cut off. But such a concept of a whole would not help Armstrong because it would require an additional relation connecting the parts. Armstrong would have to use a concept of a whole according to which a thing is a whole that has the properties of the thing as parts and that loses a property as part if the thing ceases to instantiate the property. But accepting a relation of instantiation besides the relation of being a part is exactly what Armstrong wants to avoid. Secondly, I suggest that necessary predication does not glue a universal to a particular in the required way. The trouble is that the dependence relation that Armstrong uses is no glue. Let me explain by sketching Edmund Husserl s und Roman Ingarden s account of the unity of a thing, which I think succeeds where Armstrong s new view does not succeed. 5 Husserl and Ingarden, like Armstrong, using the concept of a part in a wide sense, take the properties of a thing to be parts of the thing. Husserl and Ingarden, however, take properties to be particulars ( Momente ), tropes as they are called today. (They believe that there are universals as well as tropes, tropes being exemplifications of universals.) However, unlike some modern defenders of tropes (e.g. Campbell 1990), they do not take them to be inde- 4 Various such concepts of a whole have been developed in detail by Ingarden 1965, 43. 5 Edmund Husserl presents his view in his Third Logical Investigation On the theory of wholes and parts (Husserl 1913). His Polish pupil Roman Ingarden accepts much of Husserl s view and develops it further in his mammoth treatise on ontology The Controversy about the Existence of the World (Ingarden 1964, 14, and 1965, ch. VIII). 7

pendent entities. They are not little nuggets. Husserl says that the properties of a thing are intimately united, they penetrate each other, such that it is impossible (which for Husserl and Ingarden means synthetically impossible, not analytically or logically impossible) that one exists without being together with other properties in the unity of a thing. Husserl and Ingarden call properties seinsunselbständig, i.e. self-insufficient entities. Tropes cannot exist on their own. Self-insufficiency is a kind of ontological dependence. Husserl distinguishes in this sense concrete parts of a thing, which can be chopped off, from abstract parts of a thing, e.g. a thing s properties, which cannot be chopped off. The properties of a thing are mutually dependent on each other so that they cannot be chopped off (although some can be replaced by new properties) Now this kind of ontological dependence functions as ontological glue because it prevents a thing from falling apart. In Armstrong s new view, however, there is nothing that prevents a thing from falling apart. It says that if a thing falls apart it becomes a different thing, but it leaves open the possibility of the thing falling apart. I therefore suggest that bundle theories can be defended against Armstrong s criticism that they cannot explain the unity of a thing, and that Armstrong s own explanation of the unity of a thing is objectionable. References Armstrong, David M. 1978. Universals and Scientific Realism II: A Theory of Universals. Cambridge UP.. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Oxford UP.. 2004. Four Disputes About Properties. Synthese forthcoming. Campbell, Keith. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Blackwell. Chisholm, Roderick. 1976. Person and Object. La Salle (Illinois): Open Court. Husserl, Edmund. 1913. Logische Untersuchungen II/1. Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1980. Ingarden, Roman. 1964. Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt I: Existentialontologie. Tübingen: Niemeyer. (Engl. Time and Modes of Being. Translated by H. R. Michejda. Springfield, Ill.: Charles Thomas.). 1965. Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt II/1: Formalontologie. Tübingen: Niemeyer. 8

Lewis, David K. 1992. Armstrong on combinatorial possibility. In Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology. Cambridge UP, 1999, 196-214. Originally published in Australasian Journal of Philosophy. van Inwagen, Peter. 1991. Entia Successiva. In Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology, edited by H. Burkhardt and B. Smith. Munich: Philosophia, 248-249. 9