Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

Similar documents
Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

The Expressivist Circle: Invoking Norms in the Explanation of Normative Judgment

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Philosophy in Review XXXI (2011), no. 5

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Skepticism and Internalism

The normativity of content and the Frege point

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Is God Good By Definition?

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Solving the problem of creeping minimalism

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii


Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Miller, Alexander, An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics, Oxford: Polity Press, 2003, pp.

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

what makes reasons sufficient?

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

THE CONDITIONS OF MORAL REALISM

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

Huemer s Clarkeanism


Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Realism and instrumentalism

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

The Prospective View of Obligation

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Kant and his Successors

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

PROCEEDINGS OF THE ARISTOTELIAN SOCIETY. Normative Facts and Reasons FABIENNE PETER SENATE HOUSE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON THE WOBURN SUITE

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

The Concept of Testimony

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

MORAL AND EPISTEMIC OPEN-QUESTION ARGUMENTS

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Varieties of Apriority

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Transcription:

Grazer Philosophische Studien 80 (2010), 333 337. Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN 978-0-19-921883-7. 1. Meta-ethics usually characterises a secondlevel stance toward our moral opinions, which focuses on their meaning, epistemology, and ontological import. Current meta-ethical theorizing, however, does not merely analyse our moral claims in the vacuum. In fact, the richness and complexity of the practices that include moral utterances conform a paramount methodological constraint for Meta-ethics nowadays. Although current Meta-ethics still tries to answer the standard questions that concerned Moore a long time ago, its basic interest is the complex net of regularities and patterns of usage that surround our moral opinions (actionguidance, disagreement, justification, logical embeddings, etc). By accommodating such platitudes, Meta-ethics aims to offer a comprehensive account of the stance we occupy when we make a moral claim. The image depicted above is well-established (Timmons 1999); however, it implies a problematic scenario. Under such image, two meta-ethical theories would offer opposite but equally plausible reconstructions of our moral stance. Here we would not be entitled to choose a meta-ethical theory with the feeling that our preferred choice offers a sound and undisputed story about the status of our moral opinions. Meta-ethics, in sum, would face a sort of impasse (Rosen 1998, Gibbard 2003, Dreier 2004). Now, let us suppose that this is the state of current Meta-ethics. What should we do about this? How could we overcome the impasse? Terence Cuneo s valuable book offers a possible answer to this general worry. In The Normative Web (TNW hereafter) he depicts a possible route for Meta-ethics to pause and take stock (Smith 2005, 6). His overall strategy is to use another normative domain Epistemology to obtain an additional base to cancel the alleged impasse. According to Cuneo, once we become aware of (i) the deep similarities underlying the ethical and epistemological domains of assessment and of (ii) the implausibility of endorsing any variety of irrealism about epistemic demands, a sound case would be made in support of moral realism. And this could help us to cancel the meta-ethical impasse. Cuneo encapsulates his strategy by means of a single and carefully constructed argument. In the next section I will sketch this argument. Then I will focus on a problematic aspect of Cuneo s criticism of epistemic irrealism. Finally, I will raise a general objection to Cuneo s philosophical methodology. But let me start with the argument. 2. Cuneo s core argument for moral realism goes as follows (TNW, 6): (1) If moral facts do not exist, then epistemic facts do not exist. (2) Epistemic facts exist. (3) So, moral facts exist. (4) If moral facts exist, then moral realism is true. (5) So, moral realism is true. Premise 1 is central to Cuneo s case for moral realism. He supports it by means of a two-stage strategy. In chapter 2 and after introducing in chapter 1 (ibid. 29ff.) the main features of what he denominates moral realism of a paradigmatic sort Cuneo notes four similarities between moral and epistemic normative facts. These similarities are essential to support Cuneo s modus tollens from (1) to (3). According to Cuneo, while that Sam s belief about UFO is irrational is a particular normative epistemic fact, that Sam s treatment of Margaret is wrong stands for a particular normative moral fact. Both types of facts are similar in the following sense: they indicate categorical demands or reasons (ibid. 62),

they are structurally isomorphic in terms of their normative structure (ibid. 65, 70), they both sometimes favour identical responses - some moral facts demand beliefs from us, while some epistemic facts demand intentions (ibid. 74f.), and both are intimately entangled in many cases making it impossible to separate epistemic and moral merit when assessing an agent s beliefs or intentions (ibid. 76, 80). It is important to note that all along his argument Cuneo refers to normative facts in a non-reductive sense (ibid. 29, 39). So when he says that Xs irreducibly exist, he is affirming that (a) there is a commonsensical conception of Xs, in which platitudes of various kinds concerning Xs are fundamental (he stresses the centrality of two platitudes, one about the content of moral and epistemic claims and another one about their authority ibid. 36ff. and 58f.), and that (b) Xs exist if and only if they satisfy these platitudes, and that some entities satisfy such platitudes (ibid. 31). It is in this sense of irreducibility that moral and epistemic facts irreducibly exist. Hence, although Cuneo refers to himself as a moral realist, he is clearly not a naturalist moral realist (Railton 1986). Now let us return to the argument. Once the similarities across domains noted above are in place, Cuneo moves to the second stage of his defence of premise 1. In chapter 3, he notes how the existence of moral facts has been customarily rejected by pointing out some features that such facts imply (their intrinsically motivating force, their inescapability or categoricity, their explanatory queerness, etc). Cuneo argues that it is because of these objectionable features that moral realism seems so implausible. So if moral facts do not exist because of these objectionable features, then nothing has the so-called objectionable features because they make the existence of moral facts so objectionable. But if epistemic facts exist, then something has the objectionable features. From these two claims it follows that if moral facts do not exist, then epistemic facts do not exist. And this is what premise 1 is claiming (TNW, 89f. and 227). In support of premise 2, Cuneo attempts an indirect strategy that aims to debunk the attractive character of some prominent varieties of epistemic irrealism. By doing so he purports to establish the default plausibility of epistemic realism. In chapters 4 to 7, the author attacks a variety of meta-normative views that reject the existence of epistemic facts. He rejects epistemic nihilism (chapter 4), classic epistemic expressivism (chapter 5), sophisticated epistemic expressivism (chapter 6), and epistemic reductionism (chapter 7). The line of criticism attempted by Cuneo against these varieties of irrealism assumes that either they imply unacceptable skepticism, being self-defeating at the very end (error-theory), or that they do not fi t very well with the way we speak about epistemic merit, i.e. with what we try to convey by calling something justifi ed, warranted, rational, etc. (epistemic expressivism and reductionism). In essence, if Cuneo s debunking is plausible then there is at least a prima facie case that we ought to accept the core s argument second premise, or the claim that epistemic claims exist (ibid. 8). Premise 3 follows directly from premise 1 and 2. Normative moral facts exist because they form a genus along with a type of normative facts which existence we are disposed to assume. This is Cuneo s argument. Leaving aside its soundness for a moment, I would like to mention that a great deal of the originality and philosophical insight of this book resides on how Cuneo accommodates this argument into a wider framework in which two normative domains of assessment are connected in suggestive and sometimes unexpected ways (ibid. 73 and 79). At several points, Cuneo offers some suggestive examples of the intimate interconnection between moral and epistemic appraisal. Those who are inclined to endorse a virtue-based framework in Epistemology will fi nd valuable discussions in many places (see, for instance, ibid. 74f.). Interestingly, Cuneo also suggests a possible explanation for the rationale supporting the mutual entanglement between our epistemic and moral assessments. According to him, the epistemic and moral facts to which moral and epistemic appraisals refer are interconnected because both sort of facts are, as it were, grounded in features that comprise the human good (ibid. 80). Because of that deep 334

commonality around human good, moral and epistemic facts are authoritative in a similar way (ibid. 36, 59). 3. As I noted above, a basic step in Cuneo s argument premise 2 rests on a sustained criticism of a variety of irrealism traditionally labelled as expressivism. This is one of the most controversial moves in Cuneo s book and it deserves some attention. Let me start by noting how he understands the current divide among expressivists and how he applies it to the epistemological domain. According to Cuneo, we can differentiate between traditional and non-traditional expressivism (ibid. 125). Traditional expressivism defends that utterances involving normative epistemic terms do not perform an assertoric speech-act, and they do not convey an epistemic proposition. Instead, by uttering sentences involving normative epistemic terms the speaker expresses a practical-oriented, desire-like, psychological state. Non-traditional expressivism, on the contrary, defends that although epistemic discourse functions as an expressive device aimed at coordinating a community of agents, such discourse can still be understood as truth-apt and representative (ibid. 147ff.). Both versions of expressivism are committed to a guiding rationale, according to Cuneo. In terms of it, when we offer an expressivist reconstruction of the nature and function of our epistemic discourse we have to avoid an error-theoretic account of such discourse, saving at the same time the appearances of the target discourse (ibid. 128f.). Once the discussion is settled along these lines, Cuneo starts by rejecting traditional expressivism. At this stage, he focuses on second-order normative judgments, i.e. judgments such as It is rational for B to believe that p is justified. Cuneo claims that traditional expressivism (as it appears formulated in Gibbard s Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (1990)) cannot offer a plausible account of second-order epistemic judgments. By plausible, Cuneo means able to respect the guiding rationale formulated above. I will evaluate this particular charge in what follows. Cuneo assumes a general platitude about epistemic concepts when he attacks Gibbard s version of expressivism. Our epistemic merit concepts, he notes, apply non-derivatively to a mental state only if they express either representational or truth-apt contents. After establishing this core platitude about epistemic concepts, Cuneo notes how Gibbard s expressivism is committed to defend that, when B utters the target sentence ( that p is justified ) she is expressing an endorsement of a certain norm, i.e. one demanding her to believe p in her present circumstances. But if so, and here is Cuneo s point, when another speaker (A) utters the second-order epistemic judgment noted above ( It is rational for B to believe that p is justified ), A is applying such a term to a non-representational, nontruth-apt, mental state to B s endorsement of a certain norm. The problem is that this reconstruction goes against the basic platitude about epistemic terms noted before. Hence epistemic expressivism is true only at the price of assuming that epistemic merit concepts do not properly apply to fi rst-order moral judgments. Cuneo concludes that although expressivism is able to avoid an attribution of massive error to our epistemic concepts, it cannot avoid a systematic misapplication of such concepts in some contexts (TNW, 138ff.). I will make two remarks about Cuneo s criticism. First, it is not clear how damaging his objection is. After all, second-order epistemic judgments are somehow tangential to our normative practices at least if we compare them with fi rst-order epistemic judgments. Expressivists endorse this intuition. They stress the action-guiding nature of our normative concepts as their primary rationale. And action-guidance is expressed fundamentally by first-order normative judgments. But if so, it would seem as if Cuneo s criticism missed the point by focusing on second-order normative judgments. The previous point is surely debatable, so let us assume the centrality of second-order epistemic judgments in our epistemic practices. Even so and here goes my second remark it is still not obvious why expressivism cannot make sense of second-order epistemic judgments. Cuneo himself exposes the expres- 335

sivist solution at some point. He writes: But what about second-order E-judgments? ( ) The analysis of such claims that I take to be consistent with the normexpressivist s official account of the character of epistemic thought and discourse is that such judgment consist in higher-order endorsements of a certain kind. (ibid. 138 (italics added)) As this remark suggests, the key point is to make clear the kind of endorsement that norm-expressivism proposes. Remember that Cuneo s criticism depended on a double assumption: (i) that the kind of endorsement involved in our epistemic concepts is fixed by the core platitude about truth and representation, and (ii) that this truth-oriented endorsement works across different levels of epistemic appraisal. Now, surely the best way to read Gibbard s expressivism is by presupposing a certain degree of variability across levels of endorsement, one that reflects that our normative appraisals achieve different aims. Epistemic concepts could behave differently at different levels without this implying conceptual confusion. We could imagine, for instance, a fi rst-level endorsement where the relevant norms are truth-oriented, i.e. whose basic aim is to get external stuff right or to get things represented (Gibbard 1990, 46). But we could also imagine a refl exive, second-order endorsement where the relevant epistemic norms aim to coordinate our reactions (either generally or contextually) toward first-order, truth-oriented, acceptances. These second-order norms are not necessarily norms whose basic rationale is to get stuff right. But they are not purely pragmatic norms either (Gibbard 1990, 36f., Shah 2003). They could be hybrid epistemic norms (norms fixing the degree to which a speaker s interests can enter into the assessment of her epistemic situation in the sense just noted (Stanley 2006)). Or they could be genuine epistemic norms (norms that do not range over truth-apt or representational mental states but that nevertheless can help to maximize the occurrence of these states (Lenman 2008)). Hence, where Cuneo is prone to identify a kind of confusion in the application of a range of concepts, the expressivist can argue back by saying that they are simply offering a supplemented, somehow revisionary, account of the rationale underlying such concepts. This general reply, by the way, would appeal to the very same ecumenical approach that Cuneo favours on the boundaries between moral and epistemic appraisal. Cuneo, as I noted above, recognises this possibility. He rejects it because it fails to capture what we mean to say when we make a non-derivative second-order epistemic judgment (see especially TNW, 141). But at this stage Cuneo s core platitudes are surely doing a lot of work. I will end this commentary by noting something about these platitudes. 4. Cuneo s appeal to platitudes is central to his philosophical methodology. And it is so because the notion of accommodation is central for Meta-ethics nowadays. A great majority of meta-ethicists would be happy to accept that the accuracy of a given meta-ethical theory is proportional to the way in which such theory makes sense of the core intuitions about our moral perspective. But the appeal to platitudes is problematic. And it is easy to explain why. Sometimes the very formulation of these platitudes is implicitly supporting a specific image about the status of our moral practice, which does not facilitate a neutral basis to determine the relative merits of different meta-ethical accounts. In the case at hand, Cuneo endorses a certain platitude about the content of our epistemic concepts (that they apply nonderivatively to truth-apt or representational states). Cuneo refers to such a platitude as a neutral observational basis, and he appeals to it to debunk some varieties of irrealism. The discussion described above was an example of such use. Gibbard s account of second-order epistemic judgment will not work to Cuneo s lights because it does not accommodate an important part of what we mean when we apply an epistemic term. And what we mean is that something (a belief, a policy, etc) is an object of epistemic merit because it would be able to do a good work at representing. 336

But again it is not difficult to be suspicious of Cuneo s preferred formulation of this particular platitude. What we want to explain about epistemic concepts is a set of regularities involved in our epistemic practices how our epistemic concepts are referred to in cases of disagreement, how they are used in first-personal processes of reasoning, how they are the focus of processes of justification, etc. Now, can we extract from this constellation of practices involving epistemic concepts a substantive platitude such as Cuneo s? I doubt so. As Neil Sinclair writes referring to the surface grammar of our moral language: ( ) to say that moral talk is descriptive would be to say that moral talk involves the expression of mental states that descriptively represent the world in moral ways. And ( ) these claims are part of the realist meta-theory ( ) It is surely undeniable that moral talk involves moral predication ( ) But to assume that it also involves commitment to a certain metatheoretical understanding of that predication is much more controversial. Better to say that the uncontroversial phenomenon here is the meta-theoretical neutral one of moral predication. Sinclair, N. (forthcoming) Sinclair s remark is important. It points out a sort of methodological constraint in our appeal to platitudes: we should depict the platitudes shaping our moral stance along a neutral line of commitment. I suppose that the advice contained here can also be extended to the epistemic domain. Here as well we should be able to describe our practices neutrally, without assuming any metaphysical view about the status of such practice. If we were able to do so, the regulative role played by our platitudes would be secured. A major job for Cuneo then is to attain a certain level of neutrality in his appeal to platitudes. If that neutrality is not secured I doubt that Gibbard s account of second-order epistemic judgments can be so easily rejected. The same goes for other platitudes endorsed by Cuneo, e.g. the one about the categorical nature of our moral and epistemic duties. Setting aside this general concern The Normative Web is clearly an important book. It takes a powerful intuition and develops its consequences in a careful way. I strongly recommend it to anyone working on Meta-ethics, Epistemology or Theory of Rationality. Antonio GAITÁN TORRES Universidad de Granada / University of Oxford REFERENCES Blackburn, Simon 2006: Anti-Realist Expressivism and Quasi-Realism. In: David Copp (ed), Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 146 163. Dreier, James 2004: Meta-Ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives 18, 23 44. Gibbard, Allan 2003: Thinking How to Live. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press. 1990: Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press. Lenman, James 2008: Review of Terence Cuneo s The Normative Web. Notre Dame Philosophy Reviews, http://ndpr. nd.edu/review.cfm?id=13365. Railton, Peter 1986: Moral Realism. Philosophical Review 95, 163 207. Rosen, Gideon 1998: Blackburn s Essays on Quasi-Realism. Nous 32:3, 386 405. Shah, Nishi 2003: How Truth Governs Belief. The Philosophical Review112:4, 447 482. Sinclair, Neil (forthcoming): Presumptive Arguments for Moral Realism. Smith, Michael 2005: Meta-Ethics. In: Frank Jackson & Michael Smith (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3 30. Stanley, Jason 2006: Knowledge and Practical Interest. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Timmons, Mark 1999: Morality without Foundations. A Defence of Ethical Contextualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 337