Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Similar documents
Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

1. Introduction How do we acquire knowledge of the essences of things? This is an important question for

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Circular Justification and Explanation in Aristotle

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Dr. Jason Sheley

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

ARISTOTLE AND THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Horwich and the Liar

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Nicomachean Ethics. Book VI

Reply to Bronstein, Leunissen, and Beere

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Epistemology and sensation

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE SCIENTIA DEI FUTURORUM CONTINGENTIUM 1.8 1

Knowledge in Plato. And couple of pages later:

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Collection and Division in the Philebus

PART TWO EXISTENCE AND THE EXISTENT. D. The Existent

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Kant's Theory of Knowledge, by Harold Arthur

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Aristotle on Necessary Principles and on Explaining X Through the Essence of X

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

Ethical non-naturalism

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Heidegger Introduction

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

William Ockham on Universals

ON UNIVERSALS (SELECTION)

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Posterior Analytics. By Aristotle. Based on the translation by G. R. G. Mure, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. BOOK I.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Review. Philosophy; Page 1 of The Royal Institute of Philosophy,

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

An Analysis of the Proofs for the Principality of the Creation of Existence in the Transcendent Philosophy of Mulla Sadra

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

QUESTION 19. God s Will

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Genus and Differentia: Reconciling Unity in Definition

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Transcription:

Marquette University e-publications@marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 4-1-2017 Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein Owen Goldin Marquette University, owen.goldin@marquette.edu Published version. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Spring 2017): 173-176. DOI. 2017 University of Chicago Press. Used with permission.

David Bronstein. Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Pp. xiii+272. $74.00 (cloth). In this excellent book Bronstein interprets Aristotle s Posterior Analytics ( APo) as unified by the Meno problem, understood as follows: (1) prior to seeking whether S exists, either one knows what S is or one does not; (2) if one knows what S is, one must already know that it exists; (3) if one does not know what S is, then one cannot inquire whether it exists; (4) therefore, one cannot inquire whether S exists. The problem is to be solved in two ways: first through rejecting the presumption, implicit in point 1, that knowledge is an all or nothing matter and, second, by showing that the term what it is is ambiguous and that knowledge of what it is in one sense may fall short of scientific knowledge, but nonetheless allow for inquiry. Bronstein shows how Aristotle employs both of these solutions. The major achievement of Bronstein s book is to show how the APo can be understood as a sequence of solutions to the Meno problem as it arises in different epistemological contexts. Each version of the Meno problem concerns the epistemological presumptions of the solution before. Thus APo 1.1 wonders about how a particular truth can be learned while ignorant of the particular at issue; the solution is that the universal knowledge that makes possible the new knowledge in a sense is knowledge of the particular and in a sense is not. This solution presupposes demonstration, which, Bronstein argues, is productive of new knowledge for the practicing scientist engaged in inquiry. New knowledge is acquired through demonstration insofar as the knowledge of the conclusion is in a sense present in the knowledge of the premises. Demonstration presupposes knowledge of causally basic essences. The Meno problem concerning the inquiry into these essences arises because Aristotle is convinced that true scientific inquiry must be inquiry into real features of the world. Hence the inquiry into an essence cannot get off the ground unless one knows that the kind of which the essence is being sought is some- 173

HOPOS The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science thing real, but a version of the Meno problem arises: How can one know this unless one knows what the kind is? The problem is solved in 2.8 10 through distinguishing different modes of knowing the what it is of some kind or attribute. Preliminary nonscientific accounts allow the investigator sufficient epistemological toehold for the inquiry into what the kind is. His account presupposes that one already has a grasp of the indemonstrable principles of the sciences, which Bronstein, following Ross and me, takes to be definitions of the simple kinds that are considered as the subjects by the sciences studying the attributes. The Meno problem arises, again, concerning the inquiry into these simple essences. It is solved in 2.13, where Aristotle advocates a version of Plato s method of division for the sake of ascertaining this essence. The use of this method in the case of inquiry into essences presupposes preexistent knowledge of basic differentiae. How is it that one can learn the relevant differentiae, prior to collating them by the method of division? Again, the answer lies in distinguishing different senses by which something is known. APo 2.19 shows how perception gives us the necessary preexisting knowledge to allow the inquiry to proceed. Bronstein understands the Posterior Analytics to be offering an overarching account of the temporal progress of scientific research into a fact S is P. Revising the influential interpretation of Charles, Bronstein takes the stages of scientific inquiryintoafacttobeasfollows: At Stage 1, we do not know whether a subject S exists and we seek whether it exists. At Stage 2, we know that S exists, and we seek what it is (its essence). At Stage 3, we know what S is, and we seek whether P belongs to it as one of its demonstrable attributes. At Stage 4, we know that P belongs to S as one of its demonstrable attributes and we seek why it belongs (the cause). At Stage 5, we know why P belongs to S (6). Bronstein s Aristotle is concerned with method, how scientific inquiry proceeds, and not merely with the logical and conceptual relations that hold among the elements of those explanatory schemes at which one arrives. In the remainder of this review, I will signal and indicate problems with some of the key interpretative moves that Bronstein makes and will take issue with one. One of the classic problems concerns the relationship between nous (intellection), demonstration, and induction. Bronstein accepts a standard account of induction as a mode of reasoning by which a universal (characteristic or predication) is discerned through particulars and takes the point of APo 2.19 to be that the human mind is such as to be able to do this. The problem concerns how to reconcile this with the teaching that nous is that by which a universal principle is grasped. The traditional account has it that nous is a kind of intuition, which, given appropriate perceptions, will lead to a cognitive grasp of the explanatory principles at work. In recent decades there has been a move away from attrib- 174

Book Reviews SPRING 2017 uting to Aristotle the extravagant view that human beings have such a powerful epistemological principle; this move is in part motivated by the problem of how to integrate the intuitionist notion that nous grasps the principles of science with Aristotle s view that these principles are attained only after hard work. The main alternative (the explanationist interpretation) is that nous secures definitions only by grasping that they are the principles that will do the explanatory work that needs to be done. Bronstein rejects this view, since he holds Aristotle to a strict temporal time line according to which stage 3 of inquiry, the inquiry into what S is, must precede stage 5, the attaining of an explanation of why S is P. Accordingly, Bronstein thinks that a grasp of a definition as a definition must precede the noetic grasp of the definition as grounding demonstrations. The method of division is that by which we have the prenoetic grasp of the definitions. But this simply reproduces the problem that the intuitionist and explanationist lines of interpretation are meant to solve. How is it that the mind grasps differentiae and demonstrated attributes of the kind in question and is able to distinguish them? The alternatives seem to be intuition, selection on the basis of explanatory power, or some combination of the two. Bronstein follows Ross and me in taking Aristotle s theory of explanation to rest on the metaphysical distinction between subject and attribute; the inquiry into the essence of a subject has a different form, and a different role in the time line of inquiry, than that of the inquiry into the essence of an attribute. The subject need not be a true metaphysical subject; all that matters is that, like line in geometry, it is regarded as a subject by the science that studies it. Bronstein distinguishes basic subjects such as line or animal from subordinate subjects such as human being, which are to basic subjects as species to encompassing genera. Triangle he takes to be a subordinate subject and distinguishes it from demonstrable attributes such as eclipse. This raises problems for Bronstein that he does not adequately address: Aristotle is explicit that the geometer proves that there are triangles, which suggests that there is a demonstration in which triangle or perhaps is a side of a triangle is the predicate term. A demonstration might be something like Euclid Elements 1.1, which could be understood as showing that a certain (equilateral) triangle exists, on the basis of first principles concerning the basic subjects of line and circle. Confirmation of this can be found in APo 1.10 76b9, where deflectionandverging,which,likeatriangle,arisewhen more than one straight line stands in a certain relation, are classified as demonstrable attributes. I therefore suggest that an item such as triangle and eclipse have the same status: they are the attribute of a basic subject s standing in a certain relation to another subject and, as such, are properly to be understood as predicates of the basic subjects (although language can be simplified so that both 175

HOPOS The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science triangle and eclipse can stand as grammatical subjects). I note that Bronstein incorrectly attributes to me the view that attributes, like eclipse and (forming a) triangle (in relation to other lines), are to be identified with subordinate subjects (170). I agree that this is wrongheaded; further, I think that it is wrong to understand triangle as a subordinate subject. Aristotle does not think that triangle is a kind of line. The interpretation of a text as thorny as the Posterior Analytics is bound to elicit some disagreements. What Bronstein gets wrong should not obscure how very much he gets right, not least of which is his discerning a coherent line of argument that runs through the whole text and his showing how Aristotle had a very great deal to say on how scientific inquiry is to be conducted. Owen Goldin, Marquette University